Skip to main content
Log in

How to Advance the Debate on the Criminal Responsibility of Antisocial Offenders

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Neuroethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Should offenders with psychopathy or those exhibiting extreme forms of antisocial behaviour be considered criminally responsible? The current debate seems to have reached a stalemate. Several scholars have argued that neuropsychological data on individuals with psychopathy might be relevant for determining their criminal responsibility. However, relying on such data has not produced a consensus among legal scholars and philosophers on whether individuals with psychopathy should be excused from responsibility. We offer a diagnosis about why this debate has reached a standoff. We argue that part of the problem is that psychopathy, being a syndrome-based category, is too heterogeneous and thus offers low prospects for being integrated with neuropsychological data that might support significant conclusions about the criminal responsibility of individuals with psychopathy. Moreover, the construct of psychopathy was not originally devised to discriminate criminally accountable from unaccountable antisocial individuals. To overcome these difficulties and advance the debate, we extend a currently less discussed theoretical framework for bridging biopsychology and the law that focuses on neuropsychological constructs, domains, and processes that directly measure capacities of offenders that are relevant for criminal responsibility, without necessarily relying on mediating syndrome-based constructs. The novelty of our contribution is that the biopsychological bases of exculpation can be further developed and used for determining more fine-grained categorisations of antisocial personality types. We show how this framework provides guidelines for interdisciplinary research that can significantly advance our understanding of the preconditions for criminal responsibility and help the legal practice of ascribing or withholding it.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Data Availability

The data availability statement is not applicable.

Notes

  1. This issue is further complicated by studies suggesting that there is no unified cognitive capacity for delivering moral judgments (for discussion, see [38]). This might also explain why empirical research failed to provide sufficient evidence for general deficits in moral understanding associated with the construct of psychopathy [39].

  2. In this respect, our approach can be characterized as sharing the general principles of RDoC and applying them to the legal domain. However, it is important to note that we only adopt an “RDoC-style” approach, as we want to remain uncommitted about the specifics of the RDoC model in clinical practice. In fact, there are several RDoC-style proposals in the psychological and psychiatric literature (e.g., biocognitive fingerprinting, computational psychiatry, etc.) that, while sharing the fundamental principles of RDoC, implement them in varying manners (see, e.g., [26, 61]).

  3. The difference may also be reflected in some of the desiderata for forensic and clinical categories. Generally, we would want clinical and forensic constructs that are valid and reliable. However, in certain contexts, the trade-off between their sensitivity and specificity might differ between clinical and forensic cases. Sensitivity refers to the ability of a construct to accurately identify individuals who have a particular condition or characteristic, while specificity refers to the ability of a construct to accurately identify individuals who do not have the condition or characteristic. In a forensic setting, specificity might be more important, as justice requires that it is better for a guilty person to go free than for an innocent person to be punished. If legal constructs are not specific enough, they run the risk of including innocent individuals within their scope. For instance, if a forensic DNA test used to identify a suspect from a crime scene is not specific enough and produces a false positive result, an innocent person might be falsely accused and wrongly convicted of a crime they did not commit. In the clinical case, sensitivity might be more important, as the primary goal of the clinical system is to accurately identify and diagnose individuals who may need treatment. For instance, if a mammogram lacks sensitivity, it can potentially result in delayed diagnosis and treatment of breast cancer, which may cause a patient to miss the chance for early detection and treatment, significantly decreasing their chances of survival.

  4. There are intriguing philosophical questions regarding the understanding of relations between constructs, domains, and measurable processes. For instance, we will later discuss inhibition as a significant domain of self-control. This raises the question of whether inhibition and its associated mental processes provide causal underpinnings for self-control or if they are constitutively related (for empirically grounded discussion, see [73]). Answering these questions requires addressing broader issues in the philosophy of psychology/mind, particularly concerning levels of psychological explanation and their ontology (for contrasting perspectives in the legal context, see [72, 74]). In our discussion, we need not commit to the precise metaphysics of these relations. We will minimally presuppose that the relevant domains and associated mental processes (to be determined collectively by philosophers, legal scholars, and mental health practitioners) should provide at least necessary conditions for the proper functioning of legally relevant mental capacities.

  5. It should also be noted that there is some uncertainty about whether inhibition should be understood as a process or an outcome of goal-directed behaviour (for discussion, see [73]). We will remain neutral about these issues by construing attention as a capacity that might be subserved by different processes.

  6. A reviewer has noted that our method may be relevant to other categories of mental disorders, which aligns with our RDoC-style approach for reconsidering traditional psychiatric categories in forensic sciences. For instance, the specific type of inhibitory control dysfunction that may excuse individuals from accountability could be present across various conventional categories, such as bipolar disorder, schizophrenia, and autism spectrum disorder, in addition to antisocial personality disorder. Although this has implications for our approach, exploring these other categories is beyond the scope of this paper. It is worth noting, though, that where these other categories are associated with severe forms of antisocial behaviour, our general approach can be straightforwardly applied to them as well (see, e.g., [89]).

References

  1. Kiehl, K.A., and W.P. Sinnott-Armstrong, eds. 2013. Handbook on psychopathy and law. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Malatesti, L., J. McMillan, and P. Šustar, eds. 2022. Psychopathy: Its uses, validity and status, vol. 27. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Malatesti, L., and J. McMillan, eds. 2010. Responsibility and psychopathy: Interfacing law, psychiatry, and philosophy. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Hare, R.D. 2003. The Hare psychopathy checklist revised (2nd ed.). Multi-Health Systems.

  5. Glenn, A.L., A. Raine, and W.S. Laufer. 2011. Is it wrong to criminalize and punish psychopaths? Emotion Review 3 (3): 302–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Patrick, C.J., ed. 2018. Handbook of psychopathy, 2nd ed. The Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Jalava, J., and S. Griffiths. 2017. Philosophers on psychopaths: A cautionary tale in interdisciplinarity. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 24 (1): 1–12. https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2017.0000.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Jefferson, A., and K. Sifferd. 2018. Are psychopaths legally insane? European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 14 (1): 79–96. https://doi.org/10.31820/ejap.14.1.5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Jurjako, M., and L. Malatesti. 2018. Neuropsychology and the criminal responsibility of psychopaths: Reconsidering the evidence. Erkenntnis 83 (5): 1003–1025. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-017-9924-0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. American Psychiatric Association & American Psychiatric Association, eds. 2013. Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-5 (5th ed). American Psychiatric Association.

  11. Cuthbert, B.N. 2022. Research Domain Criteria (RDoC): Progress and potential. Current Directions in Psychological Science 31 (2): 107–114. https://doi.org/10.1177/09637214211051363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Murphy, D. 2017. Can psychiatry refurnish the mind? Philosophical Explorations 20 (2): 160–174. https://doi.org/10.1080/13869795.2017.1312499.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Buckholtz, J.W., V.F. Reyna, and C. Slobogin. 2016. A neuro-legal lingua franca: Bridging law and neuroscience on the issue of self-control. Mental Health Law & Policy Journal. https://ssrn.com/abstract=2788178. Accessed 18 Aug 2022

  14. Meynen, G. 2016. Legal insanity: Explorations in psychiatry, law, and ethics. Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-44721-6.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  15. Simon, R.J., and H. Ahn-Redding. 2006. The insanity defense, the world over. Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Gröning, L., U.K. Haukvik, S.J. Morse, and S. Radovic. 2022. Remodelling criminal insanity: Exploring philosophical, legal, and medical premises of the medical model used in Norwegian law. International Journal of Law and Psychiatry 81: 101776. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ijlp.2022.101776.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Moore, M.S. 2015. The quest for a responsible responsibility test: Norwegian insanity law after Breivik. Criminal Law and Philosophy 9 (4): 645–693. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-014-9305-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Robinson, D.N. 1996. Wild beasts & idle humours: The insanity defense from antiquity to the present. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Glenn, A.L., W.S. Laufer, and A. Raine. 2013. Author Reply: Vitacco, Erickson, and Lishner: Holding psychopaths morally and criminally culpable. Emotion Review 5 (4): 426–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Moore, M.S. 2016. The neuroscience of volitional excuse. In Philosophical foundations of law and neuroscience, ed. D. Patterson and M.S. Pardo, 179–230. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198743095.003.0010.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  21. Morse, S.J. 2008. Psychopathy and criminal responsibility. Neuroethics 1 (3): 205–212. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-008-9021-9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Jurjako, M., and L. Malatesti. 2022. The value-ladenness of psychopathy. In Psychopathy: Its uses, validity and status, vol. 27, ed. L. Malatesti, J. McMillan, and P. Šustar, 215–233. Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-82454-9_12.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  23. Sadler, J.Z. 2008. Vice and the diagnostic classification of mental disorders: A philosophical case conference. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology 15 (1): 1–17. https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.0.0152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. De Brito, S.A., A.E. Forth, A.R. Baskin-Sommers, I.A. Brazil, E.R. Kimonis, D. Pardini, P.J. Frick, R.J.R. Blair, and E. Viding. 2021. Psychopathy. Nature Reviews Disease Primers 7 (1): 49. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41572-021-00282-1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. DeLisi, M. 2016. Psychopathy as unified theory of crime. Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  26. Brazil, I.A., J.D.M. van Dongen, J.H.R. Maes, R.B. Mars, and A.R. Baskin-Sommers. 2018. Classification and treatment of antisocial individuals: From behavior to biocognition. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews 91: 259–277. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neubiorev.2016.10.010.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Malatesti, L., and E. Baccarini. 2022. The disorder status of psychopathy. In Psychopathy. Its uses, validity, and status, ed. L. Malatesti, J. McMillan, and P. Šustar, 291–309. Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  28. Nadelhoffer, T., and W.P. Sinnott-Armstrong. 2013. Is psychopathy a mental disease? In Neuroscience and legal responsibility, ed. Nicole A. Vincent, 229–255. Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  29. Ene, I., K.K.-Y. Wong, and G.D. Salali. 2022. Is it good to be bad? An evolutionary analysis of the adaptive potential of psychopathic traits. Evolutionary Human Sciences 4: e37. https://doi.org/10.1017/ehs.2022.36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Jurjako, M. 2019. Is psychopathy a harmful dysfunction? Biology & Philosophy, 34(5). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-018-9668-5.

  31. Međedović, J., B. Petrović, J. Želeskov-Đorić, and M. Savić. 2017. Interpersonal and affective psychopathy traits can enhance human fitness. Evolutionary Psychological Science 3 (4): 306–315. https://doi.org/10.1007/s40806-017-0097-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Yannoulidis, S. 2012. Mental state defences in criminal law. Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Sifferd, K.L. 2022. Legal insanity and moral knowledge: Why is a lack of moral knowledge related to a mental illness exculpatory? In Agency in mental disorder, ed. M. King and J. May, 113–135. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198868811.003.0006.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  34. Blair, R.J.R. 1995. A cognitive developmental approach to morality: Investigating the psychopath. Cognition 57 (1): 1–29. https://doi.org/10.1016/0010-0277(95)00676-P.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Aharoni, E., W. Sinnott-Armstrong, and K.A. Kiehl. 2012. Can psychopathic offenders discern moral wrongs? A new look at the moral/conventional distinction. Journal of Abnormal Psychology 121 (2): 484–497. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0024796.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. Aharoni, E., W. Sinnott-Armstrong, and K.A. Kiehl. 2014. What’s wrong? Moral understanding in psychopathic offenders. Journal of Research in Personality 53: 175–181. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jrp.2014.10.002.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. Marshall, J., A.L. Watts, and S.O. Lilienfeld. 2018. Do psychopathic individuals possess a misaligned moral compass? A meta-analytic examination of psychopathy’s relations with moral judgment. Personality Disorders: Theory, Research, and Treatment 9 (1): 40–50. https://doi.org/10.1037/per0000226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Rosenberg Larsen, R., and D. Sackris. 2023. Are there “moral” judgments? European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 19 (2): (S1)1-23. https://doi.org/10.31820/ejap.19.2.1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Sackris, D. 2022. The disunity of moral judgment: Implications for the study of psychopathy. Philosophical Psychology, 1–26. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2022.2155125.

  40. de Sio, F.S. 2011. Irresistible desires as an excuse. King’s Law Journal 22 (3): 289–307. https://doi.org/10.5235/096157611798456753.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  41. Jurjako, M., and L. Malatesti. 2016. Instrumental rationality in psychopathy: Implications from learning tasks. Philosophical Psychology 29 (5): 717–731. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2016.1144876.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  42. Meloy, J.R., A. Book, A. Hosker-Field, T. Methot-Jones, and J. Roters. 2018. Social, sexual, and violent predation: Are psychopathic traits evolutionarily adaptive? Violence and Gender 5 (3): 153–165. https://doi.org/10.1089/vio.2018.0012.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  43. Glimmerveen, J.C., J.H.R. Maes, and I.A. Brazil. 2022. Psychopathy, maladaptive learning and risk-taking. In Psychopathy. Its uses, validity, and status, eds. L. Malatesti, J. McMillan, and P. Šustar, 189–211. Springer.

  44. Glimmerveen, J.C., J.H.R. Maes, E. Bulten, I. Scheper, and I.A. Brazil. 2022. So what’cha want? The impact of individualised rewards on associative learning in psychopathic offenders. Cortex 149: 44–58. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cortex.2022.01.006.

  45. Jalava, J., and S. Griffiths. 2022. Psychopathy: Neurohype and its consequences. In Psychopathy. Its uses, validity, and status, ed. L. Malatesti, J. McMillan, and P. Šustar, 79–98. Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-82454-9_6.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  46. Blair, R.J.R., D.G.V. Mitchell, K.S. Peschardt, E. Colledge, R.A. Leonard, J.H. Shine, L.K. Murray, and D.I. Perrett. 2004. Reduced sensitivity to others’ fearful expressions in psychopathic individuals. Personality and Individual Differences 37 (6): 1111–1122. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.paid.2003.10.008.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. Hastings, M.E., J.P. Tangney, and J. Stuewig. 2008. Psychopathy and identification of facial expressions of emotion. Personality and Individual Differences 44 (7): 1474–1483. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.paid.2008.01.004.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  48. Poeppl, T.B., M.R. Donges, A. Mokros, R. Rupprecht, P.T. Fox, A.R. Laird, D. Bzdok, B. Langguth, and S.B. Eickhoff. 2019. A view behind the mask of sanity: Meta-analysis of aberrant brain activity in psychopaths. Molecular Psychiatry 24 (3): 463–470. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41380-018-0122-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  49. Deming, P., M. Heilicher, and M. Koenigs. 2022. How reliable are amygdala findings in psychopathy? A systematic review of MRI studies. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews 142: 104875. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neubiorev.2022.104875.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  50. Blair, R.J.R., D. Mitchell, and K. Blair. 2005. The psychopath: Emotion and the brain. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Greenspan, P. 2016. Responsible psychopaths revisited. The Journal of Ethics 20 (1–3): 265–278. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-016-9231-z.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  52. Glass, S.J., and J.P. Newman. 2006. Recognition of facial affect in psychopathic offenders. Journal of Abnormal Psychology 115 (4): 815–820. https://doi.org/10.1037/0021-843X.115.4.815.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  53. Dargis, M., R.C. Wolf, and M. Koenigs. 2018. Psychopathic traits are associated with reduced fixations to the eye region of fearful faces. Journal of Abnormal Psychology 127 (1): 43–50. https://doi.org/10.1037/abn0000322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  54. Larson, C.L., A.R. Baskin-Sommers, D.M. Stout, N.L. Balderston, J.J. Curtin, D.H. Schultz, K.A. Kiehl, and J.P. Newman. 2013. The interplay of attention and emotion: Top-down attention modulates amygdala activation in psychopathy. Cognitive, Affective & Behavioral Neuroscience 13 (4): 757–770. https://doi.org/10.3758/s13415-013-0172-8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  55. Shane, M.S., and L.L. Groat. 2018. Capacity for upregulation of emotional processing in psychopathy: All you have to do is ask. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience 13 (11): 1163–1176. https://doi.org/10.1093/scan/nsy088.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  56. Groat, L.L., and M.S. Shane. 2020. A motivational framework for psychopathy: Toward a reconceptualization of the disorder. European Psychologist 25 (2): 92–103. https://doi.org/10.1027/1016-9040/a000394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  57. Maibom, H.L. 2008. The mad, the bad, and the psychopath. Neuroethics 1 (3): 167–184. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-008-9013-9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  58. Aono, D., G. Yaffe, and H. Kober. 2019. Neuroscientific evidence in the courtroom: A review. Cognitive Research: Principles and Implications 4 (1): 40. https://doi.org/10.1186/s41235-019-0179-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  59. Brzović, Z., M. Jurjako, and P. Šustar. 2017. The kindness of psychopaths. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 31 (2): 189–211. https://doi.org/10.1080/02698595.2018.1424761.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  60. Griem, J., N.J. Kolla, and J. Tully. 2022. Key challenges in neurocognitive assessment of individuals with antisocial personality disorder and psychopathy. Frontiers in Behavioral Neuroscience 16: 1007121. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnbeh.2022.1007121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  61. Jurjako, M., L. Malatesti, and I.A. Brazil. 2020. Biocognitive classification of antisocial individuals without explanatory reductionism. Perspectives on Psychological Science 15 (4): 957–972. https://doi.org/10.1177/1745691620904160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  62. Maibom, H.L. 2018. What can philosophers learn from psychopathy? European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 14 (1): 63–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  63. Cooke, D.J. 2018. Psychopathic personality disorder: Capturing an elusive concept. European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 14 (1): 15–32. https://doi.org/10.31820/ejap.14.1.1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  64. Rosenberg Larsen, R. 2018. False-positives in psychopathy assessment: Proposing theory-driven exclusion criteria in research sampling. European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 14 (1): 33–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  65. Patrick, C.J., D.C. Fowles, and R.F. Krueger. 2009. Triarchic conceptualization of psychopathy: Developmental origins of disinhibition, boldness, and meanness. Development and Psychopathology 21 (3): 913–938.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  66. Baskin-Sommers, A.R., I.A. Brazil, J. Ryan, N.J. Kohlenberg, C.S. Neumann, and J.P. Newman. 2015. Mapping the association of global executive functioning onto diverse measures of psychopathic traits. Personality Disorders 6 (4): 336–346. https://doi.org/10.1037/per0000125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  67. Lilienfeld, S.O., S.F. Smith, and A.L. Watts. 2013. Issues in diagnosis: Conceptual issues and controversies. In Psychopathology: History, diagnosis, and empirical foundations, ed. W.E. Craighead, D.J. Mikllowitz, and L.W. Craighead, 1–35. Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Bolton, D., and G. Gillett. 2019. The biopsychosocial model of health and disease: New philosophical and scientific developments. Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  69. Pickersgill, M. 2012. Standardising antisocial personality disorder: The social shaping of a psychiatric technology. Sociology of Health & Illness 34 (4): 544–559. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9566.2011.01404.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  70. Campbell, C., and N. Eastman. 2014. The limits of legal use of neuroscience. In Bioprediction, biomarkers, and bad behavior, ed. I. Singh, W.P. Sinnott-Armstrong, and J. Savulescu, 91–117. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Glannon, W. 2014. The limitations and potential of neuroimaging in the criminal law. The Journal of Ethics 18 (2): 153–170. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-014-9169-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  72. Hirstein, W., K. Sifferd, and T. Fagan. 2018. Responsible brains: Neuroscience, law, and human culpability. The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  73. Werner, K.M., M. Inzlicht, and B.Q. Ford. 2022. Whither inhibition? Current Directions in Psychological Science 31 (4): 333–339. https://doi.org/10.1177/09637214221095848.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  74. Pardo, M. S., & Patterson, D. M. 2013. Minds, brains, and law: The conceptual foundations of law and neuroscience. Oxford University Press.

  75. Buckholtz, J.W., and D.L. Faigman. 2014. Promises, promises for neuroscience and law. Current Biology: CB 24 (18): R861-867. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cub.2014.07.057.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  76. Pernu, T.K., and N. Elzein. 2020. From neuroscience to law: Bridging the gap. Frontiers in Psychology 11: 1862. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2020.01862.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  77. Schopp, R.F. 2008. Automatism, insanity, and the psychology of criminal responsibility: A philosophical inquiry. Cambridge Univ. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Dillon, D.G., and D.A. Pizzagalli. 2007. Inhibition of action, thought, and emotion: A selective neurobiological review. Applied and Preventive Psychology 12 (3): 99–114. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.appsy.2007.09.004.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  79. Baskin-Sommers, A.R., S. Ruiz, B. Sarcos, and C. Simmons. 2022. Cognitive–affective factors underlying disinhibitory disorders and legal implications. Nature Reviews Psychology 1 (3): 145–160. https://doi.org/10.1038/s44159-022-00020-8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  80. Baskin-Sommers, Ae. R. 2016. Dissecting antisocial behavior: The impact of neural, genetic, and environmental factors. Clinical Psychological Science 4 (3): 500–510. https://doi.org/10.1177/2167702615626904.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  81. Aspinwall, L.G., T.R. Brown, and J. Tabery. 2012. The double-edged sword: Does biomechanism Increase or decrease judges’ sentencing of psychopaths? Science 337 (6096): 846–849. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1219569.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  82. Morse, S.J. 2022. Is executive function the universal acid? Criminal Law and Philosophy 16 (2): 299–318. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-021-09607-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  83. Burghart, M., Schmidt, S., & Mier, D. (2023). Executive functions in psychopathy: A meta-analysis of inhibition, planning, shifting, and working memory performance [Preprint]. PsyArXiv. https://doi.org/10.31234/osf.io/naxvg

  84. Hirstein, W. 2022. Neuroscience and normativity: How knowledge of the brain offers a deeper understanding of moral and legal responsibility. Criminal Law and Philosophy 16 (2): 327–351. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-021-09600-w.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  85. Glimmerveen, J.C., I.A. Brazil, B.H.(Erik) Bulten, and J.H.R. Maes. 2018. Uncovering naturalistic rewards and their subjective value in forensic psychiatric patients. International Journal of Forensic Mental Health, 17(2), 154–166. https://doi.org/10.1080/14999013.2018.1452081.

  86. Ichikawa, N., G.J. Siegle, A. Dombrovski, and H. Ohira. 2010. Subjective and model-estimated reward prediction: Association with the feedback-related negativity (FRN) and reward prediction error in a reinforcement learning task. International Journal of Psychophysiology: Official Journal of the International Organization of Psychophysiology 78 (3): 273–283. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ijpsycho.2010.09.001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  87. Loehr, J.D., D. Kourtis, and I.A. Brazil. 2015. It’s not just my fault: Neural correlates of feedback processing in solo and joint action. Biological Psychology 111: 1–7. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.biopsycho.2015.08.004.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  88. Baskin-Sommers, A.R., and I.A. Brazil. 2022. The importance of an exaggerated attention bottleneck for understanding psychopathy. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 26 (4): 325–336. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2022.01.001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  89. Bošnjak, M., M. Jurjako, and L. Malatesti. 2022. The criminal responsibility of high-functioning autistic offenders in Croatia. Balkan Journal of Philosophy 14 (2): 137–148. https://doi.org/10.5840/bjp202214217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

This paper is an outcome of the project Responding to antisocial personalities in a democratic society (RAD), http://rad.ffri.hr/en/, that is funded by the Croatian Science Foundation (CSF – HRZZ) (PI: Luca Malatesti, grant IP-2018-01-3518).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Luca Malatesti.

Ethics declarations

Originality and Exclusivity

All authors have seen and agreed with the contents of the manuscript. They certify that the submission is original work and is not under review at any other publication.

Competing Interest

The authors have no conflicts of interest to declare.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Jurjako, M., Malatesti, L. & Brazil, I.A. How to Advance the Debate on the Criminal Responsibility of Antisocial Offenders. Neuroethics 17, 1 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-023-09535-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-023-09535-0

Keywords

Navigation