Skip to main content
Log in

Scientific Ethos and Foundations of Conscious Activity

  • Regular Article
  • Published:
Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Clarification of the scientific ethos provides the opportunity to reconstruct the foundations on which the conscious activity in science is based. Contemporary scientific society does not fully recognize this metaphysical issue because of the domination of the power of naturalistic argument. The ethos of science does not show its natural embodiment; it is the complex of social and psychological norms, which rules each scientist unconsciously. Embodiment of the scientific ethos in Wittgenstein and Husserl exhibits metatheoretical prerequisites for critique of the theory presented by Robert Merton. The phenomenological approach offered by Husserl helps to visualize the scientific ethos. The analytical approach developed by Wittgenstein allows enriching this procedure. Interaction of these approaches provides disclosure of scientific mind for representation of conscious activity within science. The author maintains four theses. I. The form of attributive proposition cannot express scientific ethos, thereby, scientific ethos cannot be actually universalistic. II. The scientific ethos demands disclosure of metaphysical perspective of understanding, and it cannot lead to ordinary social forms of interaction. III. The phenomenology of scientific ethos is a branch of metaphysical studies that presupposes the correspondence between personal experiences and extraordinary forms of communication. IV. Contradictions in the scientific ethos are necessary, and they demand the corresponding theory for the explanation. Thesis (I) opens a way to interpretation of a scientific ethos as the semi-formalized description of the bases of science. It discloses new way for psychological understanding of scientific activity. The science is a complex of propositions on the base of the extra-rational assumptions of the nature of knowledge. Thesis (II) discloses options of understanding of this nature. Theses (III) and (IV) provide investigations of a metaphysical origin of scientific knowledge, namely, irremovable contradictions and wisdom as elements of the general scientific ethos.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Ally, M. (2012). Ecologizing Sartre’s ontology: Nature, science, and dialectics. Environmental Philosophy, 9(2), 95–121. https://doi.org/10.5840/envirophil20129217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alter, T., & Walter, S. (2007). Phenomenal concepts and phenomenal knowledge: New essays on consciousness and physicalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, R. E. (1982). Speech imagery is not always faster than visual imagery. Memory and Cognition, 10(4), 371–380. https://doi.org/10.3758/BF03202429.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 350BC/1928. The Works of Aristotle (Vol. VIII). Edited by W. Ross. Oxford: The Clarendon Press.

  • Arroyo, C. 2009. The role of feelings in Husserl's ethics. Idealistic Studies 39(1/3): 11–22. https://doi.org/10.5840/idstudies2009391/310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. L. (1962). How to do things with words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baddeley, A. D., & Lewis, V. (1981). Inner active processing in Reading: The inner voice, the inner ear, and the inner eye. In A. Lesgold & C. A. Perfetti (Eds.), Interactive processes in reading (pp. 107–129). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, L. R. (1995). Explaining attitudes: A practical approach to the mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (1983). Mental pictures and cognitive science. Philosophical Review, 93(4), 499–542.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, M. W. (2010). The life-world as moral world: Vindicating the life-world en route to a phenomenology of the virtues. Bulletin d'Analyse Phénoménologique, 6(3), 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruzina, R. 2010. Husserl’s “naturalism” and genetic phenomenology. New Yearbook for Phenomenology & Phenomenology Philosophy 10(1): 91–125. 10/nyppp2010104.

  • Burch, M. I. (2013). The existential sources of phenomenology: Heidegger on formal indication. European Journal of Philosophy, 21(2), 258–278. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0378.2010.00446.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casement, W. (1988). Husserl and philosophy of history. History and Theory, 27(3), 229–240. https://doi.org/10.2307/2504919.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (1993). Connectionism and compositionality: Why Fodor and Pylyshyn were wrong. Philosophical Psychology, 6(3), 305–319. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089308573094.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, A.-M. (2004). Wittgenstein and ethical norms: The question of ineffability visited and revisited. Florianópolis, 3(2), 121–134.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1981). Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy, 78(2), 67–90. https://doi.org/10.2307/2025900.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, A. 1987. The Nature of Mental Things. Notre dame: Notre Dame University Press.

  • Coltheart, V. (1999). Phonological codes in Reading comprehension, short-term memory, and memory for rapid visual sequences. In V. Coltheart (Ed.), Fleeting memories cognition of brief visual stimuli (pp. 181–225). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conant, J. 1989. Must We Show What We Cannot Say? In R. Flemming, & M. Payne (eds.) The Senses of Stanley Cavell. Lewisburg: Bucknell University Press.

  • Crowell, S. (1995). Heidegger’s phenomenological decades. Management World, 28(4), 435–338. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01273742.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dahlstrom, D. O. (1994). Heidegger's method: Philosophical concepts as formal indications. The Review of Metaphysics, 47(4), 775–795. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1004250206794.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1974). Belief and the basis of meaning. Synthese, 27(3–4), 309–323. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00484597.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guerrero, María C.M. de 2005. Inner speech – L2 : thinking words in a second language. New York: Springer science+business media, Inc.

  • Dennett, D. (1969). Content and consciousness. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. 1996. Coming to Our Senses: A Naturalistic Program for Semantic Localism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Dilthey, W. 1907/1954. The Essence of Philosophy. Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press.

  • Doria, N. G. (2009). No more than conjectures: Popper and the ethics of scientific Enterprise. Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science, 43(2), 116–125. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12124-008-9086-3.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1982). The varieties of reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1978). Mental Representation. Erkenntnis, 13(1), 9–61. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00160888.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, O. (1992). Consciousness Reconsidered. Cambridge, mass. The MIT Press.

  • Geach, P. (1957). Mental acts: Their content and their objects. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glazebrook, T. 2000. Heidegger’s philosophy of science (perspectives in continental philosophy). New York: Fordham University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (1927/1967). Sein und Zeit. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1900). Logische Untersuchungen (Bd. 1) [Logical Ivestigations. Vol. 1]. Leipzig: Verlag von Veit & Comp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. 1911/1987. Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft. [Philosophy as Rigorous Science]. In E. Husserl, Gesammelte Werke, Bd. XXV, 30–67. Dordrecht/Boston/Lancaster: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, E. (1931). Méditations cartésiennes. [Cartesian Meditations]. Paris: Colin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. 1977. Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. Erstes Buch: Allgemeine Einführungin die reine Phänomenologie (Bd. 1). [ideas for a pure phenomenology and phenomenological philosophy. First book: General introduction to pure phenomenology] the Hague, Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Hutto, D. D. (2003). Wittgenstein and the end of philosophy: Neither theory nor therapy. Basingstoke: Palgrave.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1982). Epiphenomenal Qualia. The Philosophical Quarterly, 32(127), 127–136. https://doi.org/10.2307/2960077.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, D. (2009). Propositions and propositional acts. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 39(3), 435–462. https://doi.org/10.1353/cjp.0.0056.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Konopka, A. (2008). A renewal of Husserl’s critique of naturalism. Environmental Philosophy, 5(1), 37–59. https://doi.org/10.5840/envirophil20085127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kremer, M. (2002). Mathematics and meaning in Tractatus. Philosophical Investigations, 25, 272–303. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9205.00175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (2011). The sources of intentionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1975). Outline of theory of truth. The Journal of Philosophy, 72(19), 695–717. https://doi.org/10.2307/2024634.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kurtz, P. (1969). Phenomenology and naturalism. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 7(1), 74–77. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1358246113000027.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merton, R. K. (1973). The sociology of science. Theoretical and empirical investigations. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moran, D. (2008). Husserl’s transcendental philosophy and the critique of naturalism. Continental Philosophy Review, 41, 401–425. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-008-9088-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (1987). Reality and representation. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peucker, H. (2008). From logic to the person: An introduction to Edmund Husserl's ethics. The Review of Metaphysics, 62(2), 307–325.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1926). The language and thought of the child. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1959/2002). The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (1979). The rate of ‘mental rotation’ of images: A test of a holistic analogue hypothesis. Memory and Cognition, 7(1), 19–28. https://doi.org/10.3758/BF03196930.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Ricœur, P. 1966/2014. The later Wittgenstein and the later Husserl on language. Études Ricœuriennes / Ricœur Studies 5(1): 28–48. https://doi.org/10.5195/errs.2014.245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.-P. 1940. L'Imaginaire: Psychologie phénoménologique de l'imagination. [the imaginary: A phenomenological psychology of the imagination]. Paris: Gallimard.

  • Sartre, J.-P. 1943. L'Être et le néant: Essai d'ontologie phénoménologique. [Being and Nothingness: An Essay on Phenomenological Ontology ]. Paris: Gallimard.

  • Searle, J.R. 1992. The Rediscovery of the Mind. Cambridge, mass.: The MIT Press.

  • Siewert, C. (1998). The significance of consciousness. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sokolov, A. N. (1972). Inner speech and thought. New York: Plenum.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Spengler, O. 1926. The Decline of the West. Translated by C. F. Atkinson. New York: A. A. Knopf.

  • Tarski, A. (1944). The semantical concept of truth and the foundations of semantics. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 4, 341–375. https://doi.org/10.2307/2102968.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vygotsky, L. S. (1962). Thought and language. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, H. (1972). Husserl and historicism. Social Research, 39(4), 696–719.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1922). Tractatus Logico-philosophicus. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. 1953/1968. Philosophical Investigations (3d ed.). Translated by G. Anscombe. New York: Macmillan.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sergey B. Kulikov.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The author declares that he has no conflict of interest.

Research Involving Human Participants and/ or Animals

All procedures performed in studies involving human participants were in accordance with the ethical standards of the institutional and/or national research committee and with the 1964 Helsinki declaration and its later amendments or comparable ethical standards.

Ethical Approval

This article does not contain any studies with animals performed by any of the authors.

Informed Consent

Informed consent was obtained from all individual participants included in the study.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kulikov, S.B. Scientific Ethos and Foundations of Conscious Activity. Integr. psych. behav. 54, 158–178 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12124-019-09483-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12124-019-09483-6

Keywords

Navigation