Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Moving Beyond Computational Cognitivism: Understanding Intentionality, Intersubjectivity and Ecology of Mind

  • Editorial
  • Published:
Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The emergence of the Cognitive Sciences, in the middle of the 20th Century, was initially based on an abstract model of the mind: the computer metaphor. The human mind was understood in analogy to the digital computer, as a rule-based, symbol processor. As a consequence, the human being was envisioned as logically–rationally guided, radically disembodied and isolated from culture. Over the last few decades, several disciplines, such as Biology, Mathematics, Philosophy, Psychology and Neuroscience, have begun to address the study of intentionality, intersubjectivity and natural cognition. Searching for a better understanding of these complex issues, a number of approaches have been developed with the promise of capturing the specific qualities of human cognition, radically omitted from a computationalist view of mind. Nevertheless, since these research programs are rather recent, concrete methodological designs and empirical approaches in the form of experimentally testable hypotheses are still scarce. This special issue brings together several perspectives in order to propose alternative research approaches in the topics of Intentionality, Intersubjectivity and Ecology of Mind. We believe it is necessary to discuss and advance towards explicit empirical frames in the form of actual experiments, specific predictions and formal models. The essays presented here constitute an attempt to move in this direction, with the specific aim of reconsidering the study of some forgotten properties of brain and mind.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It is important to emphasize that the notion of classic computation does not need to be exhaustive of what is a valid computational process. In other words, perhaps a biological system is a better computer than the best computer in existence. However, it still is one, only under a different paradigm of what we understand as computation (e.g.: Gabriel and Goldman 2006). See also Cosmelli et al. (2008).

  2. It is important to emphasize that although a certain temporary sequence exists between classic computationalism and the alternative approaches of cognition, there are simultaneous antecedents often interwoven throughout both perspectives (Ibáñez 2007a, b).

References

  • Anderson, M. (2003). Embodied cognition: A field guide. Artificial Intelligence, 149, 91–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, R. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47, 139–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chandler, M. J., & Carpendale, J. I. M. (1998). Inching toward a mature theory of mind. In M. Ferrari, & R. J. Sternberg (Eds.) Self-awareness: Its nature and development (pp. 148–190). New York: The Guilford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. (1986). Neurophilosophy. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body and world together again. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58, 10–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cole, M., & Engeströn, Y. (1991). A cultural–historical approach to distributed cognition. In G. Salomon (Ed.) Distributed cognition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cornejo, C., Ibañez, A., & Lopez, V. (2007a). Significado, contexto y experiencia. In C. Cornejo, & E. Kronmüller (Eds.) La pregunta por la mente: Aproximaciones desde Latinoamérica. Chile: JCSaez.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cornejo, C., Simonetti, R., Ibañez, A., Aldunate, N., Ceric, F., Lopez, V., et al. (2007b). Gesture and metaphor: Electrophysiological evidence of cross-modal coordination by audiovisual stimulation. Brain and Cognition (in press).

  • Cornejol, C., Simonetti, F., Aldunate, N., Ibáñez, A., López, V., & Melloni, L. (2007c). Electrophysiological evidence of different interpretative strategies in irony comprehension. Journal of Psycholinguist Research, 36(6), 411–430 (2007 Nov).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cosmelli, D., Soto-Andrade, J., & Tanter, E. (2008). Programming paradigms and mind metaphors: Convergence and cross-fertilization in the study of cognition. Biological Research (in press).

  • Decety, J., & Grezes, J. (2006). The power of simulation: Imagining one’s own and others’ behavior. Brain Research, 1079, 4–14.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Descombes, V. (2001). The mind’s provisions: A critique of cognitivism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press (Hardcover).

    Google Scholar 

  • Dietrich, E. (2000). Cognitive science and the mechanistic forces of darkness. Tecne, 5, 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dourish, P. (2001). Where the action is: The foundations of embodied interaction. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H., & Dreyfus, S. (1990). Making a mind versus modeling the brain: Artificial Intelligence back at a branchpoint. In S. R. Graubard (Ed.) The artificial intelligence debate: False starts, real foundations. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engelsted, N. (1993). At a crossroads. An introduction. In N. Engelsted, et al. (Ed.) The societal subject. Aaurus: Aarhus University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engeström, I. (1991). Activity theory and social transformation. Multidisciplinary Newsletter for Activity Theory, 7, 6–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (2000). The mind doesn’t work that way. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, W. (1997). Three centuries of category errors in studies of the neural basis of consciousness and intentionality. Neural Networks, 10, 1175–1183.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, W. (2000). Neurodynamics: An exploration of mesoscopic brain dynamics. London, UK: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, K., & Bidell, T. (2005). Dynamic development of action, thought, and emotion. In R. Lerner (Ed.) Theoreticals models of human development (6th ed.). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabriel, R., & Goldman, R. (2006). Conscientious Software? OOPSLA, 4, 22–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., & Goldman, A. (1998). Mirror neurons and the simulation theory of mind reading. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 12, 493–501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, R. P. (1993). Autism and the development of mind. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holland, J., Hutchins, E., & Kirsch, D. (2000). Distributed cognition: Toward a new foundation for human–computer interaction research. New York: New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ibáñez, A. (2007a). Complexity and cognition. Nonlinear Dynamics, Psychology, and Life Sciences, 11, 51–90.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Ibáñez, A. (2007b). The neurodynamic core of consciousness and neural Darwinism. Revista de Neurología (Behavioral Neurology), 45(9), 547–555.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ibáñez, A., Lopez, V., & Cornejo, C. (2006). ERPs and contextual semantic discrimination: Evidence of degrees of congruency in wakefulness and sleep. Brain and Language, 98(3), 264–275.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M. (1987). The Body in the Mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, P., Chisalita, C., & van der Veer, G. (2005). Cognition, technology, and work: Special issue on collaboration in context. Cognition, Technology & Work, 7, 70–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Juarrero, A. (1999). Dynamics in action: Intentional behavior as a complex system. Massachusetts: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors we live by. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Li, S. (2003). Biocultural orchestation of developmental plasticity across levels. Psychological Bulletin, 129, 171–194.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Lutz, A., & Thompson, E. (2003). Neurophenomenology. Integrating subjective experience and brain dynamics in the neuroscience of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10, 31–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynn, R., & Stein, F. (1991). Imaginated and situated cognition. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orsucci, F. (Ed.) (1988). In The complex matters of the mind. Singapore: World Scientific.

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoham, Y., & McDermott, D. (1988). Problems in formal temporal reasoning. Artificial Intelligence, 36, 234–287.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E., & Varela, F. (2001). Radical embodiment: Neural dynamics and consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10, 418–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M., & Carpenter, M. (2007). Shared intentionality. Developmental Science, 10(1), 121–125.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, C., & Aitken, K. J. (2001). Infant intersubjectivity: Research, theory, and clinical applications. Journal of Child Psychological Psychiatry, 42, 3–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tschacher, W., & Dauwalder, J. (Eds.) (2003). In The dynamical systems approach to cognition. Singapore: World Scientific.

  • Varela, F., Thompsom, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. (1996). From robots to Rothko. In M. Boden (Ed.) The philosophy of artificial life. Amsterdam: Dress.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whiten, A. (Eds.) (1991). In Natural theories of mind. Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Wilson, B., & Myers, K. (1999). Situated cognition in theoretical and practical context. In D. Jonassen, & S. Land (Eds.) Theoretical foundations of learning environments. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winograd, T. (1984). What does it mean to understand natural language. Cognitive Science, 4, 209–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winograd, T., & Flores, F. (1986). Understanding computers and cognition: A new foundation for design. Norwood, NJ: Ablek Pub. Corp.

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1952). Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Agustín Ibáñez.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Ibáñez, A., Cosmelli, D. Moving Beyond Computational Cognitivism: Understanding Intentionality, Intersubjectivity and Ecology of Mind. Integr. psych. behav. 42, 129–136 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12124-007-9045-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12124-007-9045-4

Keywords

Navigation