Skip to main content
Log in

Equanimity and Intimacy: A Buddhist-Feminist Approach to the Elimination of Bias

  • Published:
Sophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this article I criticize some traditional impartiality practices in Western philosophical ethics and argue in favor of Marilyn Friedman’s dialogical practice of eliminating bias. But, I argue, the dialogical approach depends on a more fundamental practice of equanimity. Drawing on the works of Tibetan Buddhist thinkers Patrul Rinpoche and Khenpo Ngawang Pelzang, I develop a Buddhist-feminist concept of equanimity and argue that, despite some differences with the Western impartiality practices, equanimity is an impartiality practice that is not only psychologically feasible but also central to loving relationships. I conclude by suggesting ways that feminist dialogical practices for eliminating bias and meditative practices are mutually supportive.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Young (1986, 1990), Benhabib (1987), and Friedman (1993).

  2. See Burrow (2005), Reilly (2007), and Schutte (1998).

  3. See Li (1994), Li (2002), Li (2008), Pang-White (2009), Po-Wah Lai Tao (2000), Dalmiya (2001), Curtin and Powers (1994), and Ross (in Lintott, 2011).

  4. Because my focus is the practice of impartiality, I follow Friedman (1993) and largely abstract these methods from the various theoretical contexts in which they were proposed.

  5. See Hare (1981), Chap. 6; Friedman (1993, 15).

  6. Marilyn Friedman (1993) makes this point (see Chap. 2).

  7. Patrul Rinpoche’s definition is fairly typical. See also Tsongkhapa (2000, 36), Kamilasila (2001, 48), and Vasubandhu’s commentary to the Mahahyanasutralamkara (2004, 228).

  8. I borrow the term ‘near enemy’ from the fifth-century Buddhist philosopher Buddhaghosa’s Path of Purification (Visuddhimagga). Buddhaghosa notes that each immeasurable quality has a ‘far enemy,’ or opposite trait, and a ‘near enemy,’ which is a trait that seems similar to the immeasurable quality but is in fact distinct. It is an enemy because, due to its similarity, it is easy to unknowingly lapse into feeling the ‘near enemy,’ in this case indifference, instead of the true immeasurable quality, equanimity.

  9. Goodman (2009) Chap. 1.

  10. By ‘reactive’ habit patterns I mean emotional, psychological, and even physical reactions that have become habits.

  11. See Kamilasila (2001, 54).

  12. McFall (1989) makes a similar criticism that impartiality is incompatible with love (p. 16).

  13. See Curtin and Powers (1994).

  14. Khenpo Pelzang does not consider the possibility that one may experience anger or hatred when contemplating one’s mother [‘…a mother is only ever kind; there is no such thing as a mother who is not’ (p. 140)]. Some contemporary Buddhist teachers who teach in the West, such as Mingyur Rinpoche (2009), suggest using another relation if one does not spontaneously generate love and gratitude when contemplating one’s mother.

  15. See Cottingham (1983).

  16. See Baron (1991).

  17. See Cottingham (1983) and McFall (1989).

  18. The implications of this discussion for understanding the ethics of mothering is a fascinating topic, but one that I do not have space to develop here.

References

  • Baron, M. (1991). “Impartiality and Friendship,” Ethics, Vol. 101, No. 4.

  • Benhabib, S. (1987). The generalized and the concrete other: The Kohlberg-Gilligan controversy and moral theory. In E. Kittay & D. Meyers (Eds.), Women and moral theory. Totowa: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burrow, S. (2005). The Political Structure of Emotion: From Dismissal to Dialogue. Hypatia: A Journal of Feminist Philosophy 20, 4:27–43.

  • Cottingham, J. (1983). “Ethics and Impartiality,” Philosophical Studies, Vol. 43. p. 83-99.

  • Curtin, D., & Powers, J. (1994). Mothering: Moral cultivation and feminist ethics. Philosophy East and West, 44(1), 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dalmiya, V. (2001). Particularizing the moral self: A feminist buddhist exchange. Sophia: International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, Metaphysical Theology and Ethics, 40(1), 61–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1993). What are friends for? Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, C. (2009). The consequences of compassion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1979). Communication and the Evolution of Society. Translated by Thomas McCarthy. Boston: Beacon Press.

  • Hare, R. M. (1981). Moral thinking. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heim, M. (2008). “Buddhism and the Emotions” in Oxford Handbook of Religion and Emotion. NY: Oxford University Press.

  • Kamilasila. (2001). Stages of meditation (The Dalai Lama, commentator). Ithaca: Snow Lion Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Li, C. (1994). The Confucian concept of Jen and the feminist ethics of care: A comparative study. Hypatia: A Journal of Feminist Philosophy, 9(1), 70–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Li, C. (2002). Revisiting Confucian Jen ethics and feminist care ethics: A reply to Daniel Star and Lijun Yuan. Hypatia: A Journal of Feminist Philosophy, 130-140.

  • Li, C. (2008). Does Confucian ethics integrate care ethics and justice ethics? The case of Mencius. Asian Philosophy, 18(1), 69–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McFall, L. (1989). Integrity. Ethics, 98, 5–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pang-White, A. (2009). Reconstructing modern ethics: Confucian care ethics. Journal of Chinese Philosophy, 36(2), 210–227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pelzang, K. N. (2004). A guide to the words of my perfect teacher. Padmakara Group, trans. Boston: Shambala.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reilly, N. (2007). Cosmopolitan Feminism and Human Rights. Hypatia: A Journal of Feminist Philosophy 22, 4:180–198.

  • Patrul Rinpoche (1994). The words of my perfect teacher. Padmakara Group, trans. San Francisco: HarperCollins Publishers.

  • Mingyur Rinpoche (2009). Joyful wisdom. New York: Three Rivers Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schutte, O. (1998) Cultural Alterity: Cross-cultural Communication and Feminist Theory in North-South. Hypatia: A Journal of Feminist Philosophy 13, 2 (Monsoon 1998): 53–72.

  • Smith, A. (1948). A theory of moral sentiments. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tao, J. P.-W. (2000). Two perspectives of care: Confucian Ren and feminist care. Journal of Chinese Philosophy, 27(2), 215–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tsongkhapa. (2000). Lam rim chen mo (The stages of the path). The Lam Rim Chenmo Translation Committee, trans. Ithaca: Snow Lion Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, I. (1986). Impartiality and the civic public. Praxis International, 5, 381–401.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, I. (1990). Justice and the politics of difference. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Emily McRae.

Additional information

Thank you to James Anderson, Mavis Biss, Harry Brighouse, Claudia Card, Anne Hansen, and John Makransky for helpful comments of previous drafts. This paper was written with a dissertation fellowship from the American Association of University Women.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

McRae, E. Equanimity and Intimacy: A Buddhist-Feminist Approach to the Elimination of Bias. SOPHIA 52, 447–462 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-013-0376-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-013-0376-y

Keywords

Navigation