Skip to main content
Log in

Interpretivism without Judgement-Dependence

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In a recent article in this journal, Krzysztof Poslajko reconstructs—and endorses as probative—a dilemma for interpretivism first posed by Alex Byrne. On the first horn of the dilemma, the interpretivist takes attitudes to emerge in relation to an ideal interpreter (and thus loses any connection with actual folk psychological practices). On the second horn, the interpretivist takes attitudes to emerge in relation to individuals’ judgements (and thus denies the possibility of error). I show that this is a false dilemma. By taking a model-theoretic approach to folk psychology, and marrying interpretivism with dispositionalism, interpretivists can viably reject the notion of an ideal (or canonical) interpreter—and relativize attitudes to actual lay interpreters—without taking on board the unacceptable epistemological consequences of allowing that attitudes are judgement-dependent.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. When Poslajko discusses the literature on folk psychology, he misleadingly claims that “all the major contenders in the mind-reading debate … namely the theory-theory approach, the simulation theory and the phenomenological view, see propositional attitudes as having a sort of tracking epistemology in the sense that our cognitive efforts are trying to be correct descriptions of mental reality. As different as these theories are, they all assume that when we attribute mental states to others, we are in the business of trying to discover what the mental states of the other are” (2020: 718). For one thing, Poslajko does not mention model-theoretic approaches, which have become a major contender. He also overstates the extent to which there is a consensus assumption of the epistemological goals of mental state attribution. An increasingly influential strand of the folk psychology literature is dedicated to arguing that mental state attribution serves a wide variety of non-epistemological normative and regulatory goals (Morton 2003; McGeer 2007; Andrews 2012; Zawidzki 2013; Bohl 2015; Spaulding 2018; Curry 2018, 2020a, b).

  2. Poslajko (2020: 715) briefly discusses Schwitzgebel’s dispositionalism without recognizing this potential marriage with interpretivism. Interpretivists must be dispositionalists, given how interpreters construe beliefs. By my lights, anti-reductionist dispositionalists ought to be interpretivists too: they hold that to believe is to have an appropriate pattern of dispositions, and how interpreters model beliefs is the best—maybe the sole viable—non-reductionist candidate for what makes a pattern of dispositions appropriate.

  3. In conversation, philosophers sometimes object to interpretivism by claiming that human beings (or our phylogenetic ancestors) had to have evolved beliefs before we could evolve interpretive capacities; thus, beliefs must exist independent of interpretive capacities. I think objectors find this argument compelling because, in imagining pre-interpretive humans, they fail to bracket their own interpretive capacities. Of course it is perfectly imaginable that pre-interpretive humans had beliefs—relative to the folk psychological models brought to bear by those doing the imagining. It is even plausible that they had to have had some such beliefs in order to become interpreters (though, due to mindshaping processes (Zawidzki 2013), the evolutionary story is likely more complex than this premise lets on). However, bracketing the imaginer’s own folk psychological capacities, it is also perfectly imaginable that pre-interpretive humans merely had dispositions, and that patterns of these dispositions emerged as beliefs only once practices of interpretation evolved.

References

  • Andrews, K. (2012). Do apes read minds? Towards a pluralistic folk psychology. MIT Press.

  • Baker, L. R. (1995). Explaining attitudes: A practical approach to the mind. MIT Press.

  • Bohl, V. (2015). We read minds to shape relationships. Philosophical Psychology, 28(5), 674–694.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. (1998). Interpretivism. European Review of Philosophy, 3, 199–223.

    Google Scholar 

  • Curry, D. S. (2018). Beliefs as inner causes: the (lack of) evidence. Philosophical Psychology, 31(6), 850–877.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Curry, D. S. (2020a). Interpretivism and norms. Philosophical Studies, 177(4), 905–930.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Curry, D.S. (2020b). Street smarts. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02641-z.

  • Davidson, D. (2001). Inquiries into truth and interpretation. OUP.

  • Dennett, D. C. (1987). The intentional stance. MIT Press.

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2005). Folk psychology as a model. Philosophers’ Imprint, 5(6), 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maibom, H. (2003). The mindreader and the scientist. Mind and Language, 18(3), 296–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maibom, H. (2009). In defence of (model) theory theory. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 16, 6(8), 360–378.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malle, B. F. (2008). The fundamental tools, and possibly universals, of human social cognition. In Handbook of motivation and cognition across cultures (pp. 267–296). Academic Press.

  • McGeer, V. (2007). The regulative dimension of folk psychology. In Folk Psychology Re-Assessed (D. Hutto, M. M. Ratcliffe, Eds.), pp. 137–156. Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4020-5558-4

  • Mölder, B. (2010). Mind ascribed: An elaboration and defence of interpretivism. John Benjamins.

  • Morton, A. (2003). The importance of being understood: Folk psychology as ethics. Routledge.

  • Poslajko, K. (2020). Can deflationism save interpretivism? Philosophia, 48, 709–725.

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. Chicago.

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2002). A phenomenal, dispositional account of belief. Noûs, 36(2), 249–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2013). A dispositional approach to the attitudes: Thinking outside the belief box. In New essays on belief, ed. Nikolaj Nottelmann (Palgrave Macmillan): 75–99.

  • Spaulding, S. (2018). How we understand others: Philosophy and social cognition. Routledge.

  • Zawidzki, T. (2013). Mindshaping: A new framework for understanding human social cognition. MIT Press.

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Lindsey Fiorelli, Justin Bernstein, and two anonymous reviewers.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Devin Sanchez Curry.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Curry, D.S. Interpretivism without Judgement-Dependence. Philosophia 49, 611–615 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-020-00231-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-020-00231-4

Keywords

Navigation