Skip to main content
Log in

Simplifying with Free Choice

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper offers a unified semantic explanation of two observations that prove to be problematic for classical analyses of modals, conditionals, and disjunctions: (1) the fact that disjunctions scoping under possibility modals give rise to the free choice effect and (2) the fact that counterfactuals license simplification of disjunctive antecedents. It shows that the data are well explained by a dynamic semantic analysis of modals and conditionals that uses ideas from the inquisitive semantic tradition in its treatment of disjunction. The analysis explains why embedding a disjunctive possibility under negation reverts disjunction to its classical behavior, is general enough to predict less studied simplification patterns, and also makes progress toward a unified perspective on the distinction between informative, inquisitive, and attentive content.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Kamp’s (1973, 1978) discussion of the free choice effect is seminal, though the label goes back to von Wright (1968).

  2. Pragmatic treatments of the free choice effect include Alonso-Ovalle (2006), Fox (2007), Franke (2011), Klinedinst (2007), Kratzer and Shimoyama (2002), and Schulz (2005). Semantic approaches include Aher (2012), Aloni (2007), Barker (2010), Fusco (2015a, b), Geurts (2005), Simons (2005), Starr (2016), Zimmermann (2000). Simplification has also received some attention in the literature: Franke (2011), Klinedinst (2009), and van Rooij (2010) offer pragmatic explanations for why counterfactuals should simplify in a variably strict analysis, while Alonso-Ovalle (2009) and van Rooij (2006) propose semantic approaches.

  3. Recent processing and acquisition studies suggest significant differences between free choice effects and scalar implicatures (see Chemla and Bott 2014 and Tieu et al. 2016, respectively), but of course this does not prove that free choice cannot be a pragmatic affair.

  4. As I will discuss more explicitly in Sect. 4.2, not all counterfactuals with negated conjunctions as antecedents seem to simplify, but I take this to be part of the explanandum rather than showing that there is nothing to be explained here in the first place. Nute’s (1980) original example moves from ‘If Nixon and Agnew had not both resigned, Ford would never have become president’ to ‘If Nixon had not resigned, Ford would never have become president’ and ‘If Agnew had not resigned, Ford would never have become president.’ One may worry that the appeal of Nute’s example stems from our knowledge of the historical facts, however, and so it is preferable to choose are more arbitrary case such as (6).

  5. The appeal to acceptance and rejection inducing update procedures owes inspiration to Aher (2012) and to Groenendijk and Roelofsen (2015), who think of acceptance and rejection as static relations between inquisitive states and sentences. The idea that free choice effects are to be explained in terms of the inquisitiveness of disjunction is also prominent in Aloni (2007), Ciardelli et al. (2009), and Roelofsen (2013). Its implementation here has the important consequence of offering a straightforward explanation of why disjunctive possibilities embedded under negation behave in a classical fashion.

  6. Bringing presuppositions into the picture also raises the question of how they project and a proper answer requires minor modifications to some of our original update rules. For instance, in order to predict that presuppositions project out of the possibility operator one would need to say that \(\sigma [\Diamond \phi]^{+}_{s} \tau \) holds just in case \(\tau = \{w \in \sigma :\langle {\mathtt{info}}(s), \underline{\bot}\rangle \notin [\phi]^{+}_{s}\}\) and, moreover, \(\exists \nu . \sigma [\phi]^{+}_{s} \nu \). Likewise for the negative entry: \(\sigma [\Diamond \phi]^{-}_{s} \tau \) holds just in case and, moreover, \(\exists \nu . \sigma [\phi]^{-}_{s} \nu \). I set these additional complexities, which would also affect the update rules to disjunction, aside to streamline the notation and since getting all the facts about presupposition projection right goes beyond the scope of this investigation.

  7. I appeal here to the ‘standard recipe’ for deriving quantity implicatures. See, for instance, Geurts (2014) and references therein.

  8. Fusco (2015a) suggests that it is the very availability of the sluice in (12b) which shows that the disjunction takes scope over the modal in (12a).

  9. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for the 20th Amsterdam Colloquium for drawing my attention to this case.

  10. The claim that implicatures may cancel presuppositions is empirically well-attested, though the former are not always given priority over the latter in case of a conflict. See Beaver (2010) and references therein for detailed discussion.

  11. On the other hand, the fact that not all existential quantifiers need to receive a test semantics may account for Klinedinst’s (2007) observation that singular existentials do not behave like free choice items.

References

  • Aher M (2012) Free choice in deontic inquistive semantics (DIS). Lect Notes Comput Sci 7218:22–31. doi:10.1007/978-3-642-31482-7_3

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aloni M (2007) Free choice, modals, and imperatives. Nat Lang Semant 15(1):65–94. doi:10.1007/s11050-007-9010-2

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alonso-Ovalle L (2006) Disjunction in alternative semantics. Ph.D. thesis, University of Massachusetts, Amherst

  • Alonso-Ovalle L (2009) Counterfactuals, correlatives, and disjunction. Linguist Philos 32(2):207–244. doi:10.1007/s10988-009-9059-0

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barker C (2010) Free choice permission as resource-sensitive reasoning. Semant Pragmat 3(10):1–38. doi:10.3765/sp.3.10

    Google Scholar 

  • Barker C, Shan C-C (2014) Continuations and natural language. Oxford University Press, New York. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199575015.001.0001

    Google Scholar 

  • Beaver DI (2001) Presupposition and assertion in dynamic semantics. CSLI Publications, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • Beaver DI (2010) Have you noticed that your Belly Button Lint colour is related to the colour of your clothing? In: Bäuerle R, Reyle U, Zimmermann TE (eds) Presuppositions and discourse: essays offered to Hans Kamp. Elsevier, Oxford, pp 65–99

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Champollion L, Ciardelli I, Zhang L (2016) Breaking de Morgan’s law in counterfactual antecedents. Proc SALT 26:304–324

  • Chemla E, Bott L (2014) Processing inferences at the semantics/pragmatics frontier: disjunctions and free choice. Cognition 130(3):380–396. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2013.11.013

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ciardelli I, Groenendijk J, Roelofsen F (2009) Attention! Might in inquisitive semantics. In: Proceedings of SALT XIX, pp 91–108

  • Coppock E, Brochhagen T (2013) Raising and resolving issues with scalar modifiers. Semant Pragmat 6(3):1–57. doi:10.3765/sp.6.3

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine K (1975) Critical notice. Mind 84(335):451–458. doi:10.1093/mind/LXXXIV.1.451

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel K (2001) Counterfactuals in a dynamic context. In: Kenstowicz M (ed) Ken Hale: a life in language. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 123–152

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox D (2007) Free choice and the theory of scalar implicatures. In: Sauerland U, Stateva P (eds) Presupposition and implicature in compositional semantics. Palgrave Macmillan, Hampshire, pp 71–120

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Franke M (2011) Quantity implicatures, exhaustive interpretation, and rational conversation. Semant Pragmat 4(1):1–82. doi:10.3765/sp.4.1

    Google Scholar 

  • Fusco M (2015a) Deontic disjunction. Ph.D. thesis, UC Berkeley

  • Fusco M (2015b) Deontic modality and the semantics of choice. Philos Impr 15(28):1–27

    Google Scholar 

  • Geurts B (2005) Entertaining alternatives: disjunctions as modals. Nat Lang Semant 13(4):383–410. doi:10.1007/s11050-005-2052-4

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geurts B (2014) Quantity implicatures. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511975158

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillies AS (2007) Counterfactual scorekeeping. Linguist Philos 30(3):329–360. doi:10.1007/s10988-007-9018-6

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Groenendijk J, Roelofsen F (2015) Towards a suppositional inquisitive semantics. In: Aher M, Hole D, Jeřábek E, Kupke C (eds) Logic, language, and computation: 10th international Tbilisi symposium on logic, language, and computation, TbiLLC 2013, Gudauri, Georgia, 23–27 Sept 2013. Revised Selected Papers. Springer, Berlin, pp 137–156. doi:10.1007/978-3-662-46906-4_9

  • Heim I (1982) The semantics of definite and indefinite noun phrases. Ph.D. thesis, University of Massachusetts, Amherst

  • Iatridou S (2000) The grammatical ingredients of counterfactuality. Linguist Inq 31(2):231–270. doi:10.1162/002438900554352

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamp H (1973) Free choice permission. In: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol 74, pp 57–74. http://www.jstor.org/stable/4544849

  • Kamp H (1978) Semantics versus pragmatics. In: Guenthner F, Schmidt SJ (eds) Formal semantics and pragmatics for natural languages. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 255–287. doi:10.1007/978-94-009-9775-2_9

  • Klinedinst N (2007) Plurality and possibility. Ph.D. thesis, UCLA

  • Klinedinst N (2009) (Simplification of)\(^{2}\) disjunctive antecedents. Presuppositions and implicatures: proceedings of the MIT-Paris workshop (MWPL60). MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 135–151

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer A (1981) The notional category of modality. In: Eikmeyer H-J, Rieser H (eds) Words, worlds, and contexts. New approaches to word semantics. Walter de Gruyter & Co, Berlin, pp 38–74

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer A (1991) Modality. In: von Stechow A, Wunderlich D (eds) Semantics: an international handbook of contemporary research. Walter de Gruyter & Co, Berlin, pp 639–650

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer A, Shimoyama J (2002) Indeterminate phrases: the view from Japanese. In: Proceedings of the third Tokyo conference on psycholinguistics, pp 1–25

  • Larson RK (1985) On the syntax of disjunction scope. Nat Lang Linguist Theory 3(2):217–264. doi:10.1007/BF00133841

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis DK (1973) Counterfactuals. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • McKay T, van Inwagen P (1977) Counterfactuals with disjunctive antecedents. Philos Stud 31(5):353–356. doi:10.1007/BF01873862

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nute DE (1975) Counterfactuals and the similarity of worlds. J Philos 72(21): 773–778. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2025340

  • Nute DE (1980) Topics in conditional logic. Reidel, Dordrecht. doi:10.1007/978-94-009-8966-5

    Google Scholar 

  • Roelofsen F (2013) A bare bone attentive semantics for Might. In: Aloni M, Franke M, Roelofsen F (eds) The dynamic, inquisitive, and visionary life of \(\phi \), \(?\phi \), and \(\Diamond \phi \). ILLC Publications, Amsterdam, pp 190–215

    Google Scholar 

  • Rooth M, Partee BH (1983) Generalized conjunction and type ambiguity. In: Bäuerle R, Schwarze C, von Stechow A (eds) Meaning, use and interpretation of language. De Gruyter, Berlin, pp 361–383

    Google Scholar 

  • Santorio P (2016) Alternatives and truthmakers in conditional semantics. University of Leeds, Manuscript

    Google Scholar 

  • Schulz K (2005) A pragmatic solution for the paradox of free choice permission. Synthese 147(2):343–377. doi:10.1007/s11229-005-1353-y

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simons M (2005) Dividing things up: the semantics of or and the modal/or interaction. Nat Lang Semant 13(3):271–316. doi:10.1007/s11050-004-2900-7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker RC (1968) A theory of conditionals. In: Rescher N (ed) Studies in logical theory. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 98–112

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker RC (1975) Indicative conditionals. Philosophia 5(3):269–286. doi:10.1007/BF02379021

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Starr WB (2014) A uniform theory of conditionals. J Philos Log 43(6):1019–1064. doi:10.1007/s10992-013-9300-8

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Starr WB (2016) Expressing permission. Proc SALT 26:325–346

  • Szabolsci A, Haddican B (2004) Conjunction meets negation: a study in cross-linguistic variation. J Semant 21(3):219–249. doi:10.1093/jos/21.3.219

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tieu L, Romoli J, Zhou P, Crain S (2016) Childrens knowledge of free choice inferences and scalar implicatures. J Semant 33(2):269–298. doi:10.1093/jos/ffv001

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Rooij R (2006) Free choice counterfactual donkeys. J Semant 23(4):383–402. doi:10.1093/jos/ffl004

    Google Scholar 

  • van Rooij R (2010) Conjunctive interpretation of disjunction. Semant Pragmat 3(11):1–28. doi:10.3765/sp.3.11

    Google Scholar 

  • Veltman F (1996) Defaults in update semantics. J Philos Log 25(3):221–261. doi:10.1007/BF00248150

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Wright GH (1968) An essay on deontic logic and the theory of action. North-Holland, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Warmbrōd K (1981) Counterfactuals and substitution of equivalent antecedents. J Philos Log 10(2):267–289. doi:10.1007/BF00248853

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Willer M (2013a) Dynamics of epistemic modality. Philos Rev 122(1):45–92. doi:10.1215/00318108-1728714

    Google Scholar 

  • Willer M (2013b) Indicative scorekeeping. In: Proceedings of the 19th Amsterdam Colloquium, pp 249–256

  • Willer M (Forthcoming) Lessons from Sobel sequences. Semant Pragmat

  • Zimmermann TE (2000) Free choice disjunction and epistemic possibility. Nat Lang Semant 8(4):255–290. doi:10.1023/A:1011255819284

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to audiences at the University of Chicago, the 20th Amsterdam Colloquium, and the 2nd UC Berkeley Meaning Science Workshop (organized by Seth Yalcin). Special thanks to Martin Aher, Fabrizio Cariani, Lucas Champollion, Ivano Ciardelli, Melissa Fusco, Daniel Lassiter, Matt Mandelkern, Patrick Munoz, Paul Portner, Paolo Santorio, Floris Roelofsen, Will Starr, and two anonymous reviewers for Topoi for extensive and very helpful comments and discussion.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Malte Willer.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Willer, M. Simplifying with Free Choice. Topoi 37, 379–392 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-016-9437-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-016-9437-5

Keywords

Navigation