Skip to main content
Log in

The Dimensionality of Visual Space

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The empirical study of visual space (VS) has centered on determining its geometry, whether it is a perspective projection, flat or curved, Euclidean or non-Euclidean, whereas the topology of space consists of those properties that remain invariant under stretching but not tearing. For that reason distance is a property not preserved in topological space whereas the property of spatial order is preserved. Specifically the topological properties of dimensionality, orientability, continuity, and connectivity define “real” space as studied by physics and are the spatial properties that characterize the physical universe as being an integral whole. By contrast the geometrical analysis of VS has taken little cognizance of its topology. Instead such properties have been presupposed a priori rather than being established a posteriori by empirical means, perhaps because these properties are self-evident. Applying the method of coordinative definition expounded by Hans Reichenbach for determining geometrical and topological properties of physical space (PS), it can be shown that VS fulfills the topological criteria of being a “real” space sui generis. Though theorized to be produced by the brain, the topology of VS is not topologically equivalent (homeomorphic) with the structure and activity of the brain because, as will be shown, the topology of VS cannot be formed from the topology of the brain without tearing and/or cutting and pasting.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7
Fig. 8
Fig. 9
Fig. 10
Fig. 11
Fig. 12
Fig. 13
Fig. 14
Fig. 15
Fig. 16
Fig. 17

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Translated as “visual space,” the term actually introduced by Hering was the German term Sehraum, as opposed to wirklichen Raum, or “real space” in English (Hillebrand 1929).

  2. By “metageometry” was meant what is now called non-Euclidean geometry (Russell 1959).

  3. Ophthalmologist LeGrand Hardy and his associates differentiated visual space from physical space in much the same way: “‘Physical space’ is a measurable, engineering space of the outside world. It is the space in which houses, bridges, roadways and railways are mapped and built with great precision. ‘Visual space’ is the immediate instantaneous impression we have of our environment as a three dimensional manifold; the immediate impression we have of objects about us in relative terms; farther-nearer; larger-equal” (Hardy et al. 1951: 53).

  4. Morgan cites a paper by Battro et al. (1976) which advances the idea that VS is not hyperbolic as Luneburg claimed.

  5. The physical properties Morgan lists in support of his argument are from Hinckfuss (1975). Morgan did not heed the caveat, however, which Hinckfuss added regarding these properties: “It is not being alleged, of course, that each item in the lists [of properties of space] is a true statement, but only that it has been believed to be true by someone at some time.”

  6. Cf. Mach (1906a).

  7. For a review of Luneburg’s work and that inspired by it see the analysis by philosopher Patrick Suppes (1977).

  8. Philosopher Wayne Stromberg (1975) addressed certain conceptual inconsistences in Gestalt theory’s account of 3-D visual perception in terms of figure–ground relationships.

  9. Cf. Ranucci and Rollins (1977).

  10. Of course there are no ocular muscles between the eyes but that fact may not be experienced as such, given the musculature covering the nose.

  11. From a topological standpoint these reports are significant because the cyclopean viewpoint is maintained: the projection is merely inverted or turned around, but the perspective remains otherwise unchanged. It does not result in seeing VS from behind, as it were, so that it being one-sided topologically is unchanged.

  12. I am indebted to Professor of Philosophy Graham Nerlich of the University of Adelaide for lively correspondence in the past to discuss points about visual geometry in his stimulating book The Shape of Space (1976).

  13. For criticism of Luneburg’s theory, see Hardy et al. (1951), Gibson (1959), Baird (1970) and Battro et al. (1976).

  14. Dimensionality is used here in the sense given in the OED: “[T]he condition of having (a particular number of) dimensions; dimensional quality.”

  15. Evidently Schrödinger is using “sensual” as a synonym for “sensory,” as indicated by the OED, “Of or pertaining to the senses or physical sensation; sensory. Now rare.”

  16. Cf. Koffka (1935) and Angeles (1981): “[Q]ualities, primary/secondary. 1. Primary qualities are (a) those qualities such as motion, rest, size (extension) shape (figure), solidity (impenetrability), number, structure, (b) which are believed to be inherent characteristics of matter in itself and not to depend for their existence on consciousness. 1. Secondary qualities are those (a) sensed qualities such as of color, smell, taste, sound, hear, cold, (b) which are believed to be caused in us by the primary qualities inherent in matter and (c) which depend for their existence on the operations of the mind. Primary qualities exist in reality only independently of an observer. Secondary qualities exist only as content in consciousness. This distinction has in general been made since the time of Leucippus and Democritus… and was commonly accepted during the rise of modern science by thinkers such as Galileo, Boyle, Newton. The distinction in philosophy is mainly associated with Locke.”

  17. I am indebted to physicist Nick Herbert for bringing to my attention the relevance of Mach’s views on sensations qua the fundamental elements in Mach’s phenomenalist epistemology.

  18. By complexes of sensations Mach evidently meant the physicist’s observations.

  19. Though in his presentation Ward does not refer to corresponding work on intensity and extensity in theoretical physics, cf. philosopher Karl Robert Eduard von Hartmann: “The quantity, or the extensity factor, of energy is attached to one structure and cannot be transferred to another structure without carrying with it parts of the first; but the intensity factor can pass from one structure to another.” Quoted in Jung (1972: 20).

  20. “Dimensionality without Dimensionality” is one of any number of characteristic Wheelerisms that take the form ‘A without A,’ roughly, anything presupposing A can never explain A, and was his remedy for circular reasoning or tautologies, evidently using Einstein as his point of departure who sought to formulate “force without force.” Thus Wheeler speaks of “charge without charge,” “mass without mass,” etc. Students and associates of Wheeler’s compiled an anthology of essays in his honor, and called it, appropriately, Magic Without Magic (Klauder 1972). Saul-Paul Sirag (personal communication, 1984) suggested the most fitting title for a biography of Wheeler would be “Without Without Without.”

  21. Cf. Quinn (1981): “As [Bertrand] Russell suggested, these punctual elements [idealized geometrical points] are qualitatively homogeneous; there is no inherent quality in a single point, as there is in a single color, by which it can be qualitatively distinguished from another.”

  22. Remarkably the experimental quest for a Ganzfeld of completely uniform illumination and color has yielded the paradoxical result of a “black out,” in which persons lose the power of sight temporarily, and their visual field (VS) disappears completely (Gibson and Waddell 1952; Avant 1965).

  23. Katz (1935) refuted Buhler’s proposal that our perception of empty space is the result of “air-light,” light reflected off of dust particles in the air.

  24. “Since one-sidedness is equivalent to non-orientability, we have again proved the one-sidedness of the projective plane” (Lietzmann 1965: 149).

  25. This conceptualization was developed more fully by Reichenbach (1991).

  26. Quoted from an unpublished abstract (1982), “Plato’s cave revisited: The projection of space–time from C [S4].” The abbreviation “C[S4]” denotes the symmetric-four group in algebraic group theory.

  27. The late Avrum Stroll, professor of philosophy at University of California, San Diego, pointed out that my thinking in this context paralleled that of Goodman (1977) and I remain grateful to him for that and much fruitful discussion of the language of surfaces. I am also indebted to Saul-Paul Sirag for enlightening and copious tutoring concerning grand unification schemes.

  28. I am indebted to the Derek Fender, late professor of Applied Science and Biology in Bioinformation Systems at Caltech, who first got me thinking about stereopsis in terms of topology, and envisioned that my dissertation research would be to model stereopsis as a catastrophe as theorized by René Thom (1975). This was in response to a conference paper of mine entitled “Is the engram a stereogram?” (Rosar and Perrott 1980) in which I had argued that visual mental images lack stereopsis, but that stereopsis is remembered and visualized as separate figure–ground relationships.

  29. Blank also suggested that the brain might be responsible for the putative curvature of VS: “In a metric geometry the straight lines or geodesics are paths of shortest length. This fact leads one to conjecture that the visual geodesics, the loci which give the impression of straightness, must be associated with something like a least action principle in the visual neural organization. Perhaps a physiological understanding of visual space perception may eventually be reached by pursuing this possible connection between the metric of visual space and neural function.” (1957: 234–235) However, I identified and analyzed certain problems in the Gestalt use of topological and topographic concepts relative to brain mapping (Rosar 1985).

References

  • Angeles P (1981) Dictionary of philosophy. Barnes and Noble, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Avant L (1965) Vision in the ganzfeld. Psychol Bull 64:246–258

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baird J (1970) Psychophysical analysis of visual space. Pergamon, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Battro A, Netto S, Rozestraten J (1976) Riemannian geometries of variable curvature in visual space: visual alleys, horopters, and triangles in big open fields. Perception 5:9–23

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beloff J (1962) The existence of mind. Citadel, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein H, Phillips A (1981) Fiber bundles and quantum theory. Sci Am 245:122–137

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackmore J (1972) Ernst Mach: his life, work, and influence. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Blank A (1957) The geometry of vision. British J Physiol Opt 14: 154–169, 213, 222–235

  • Blumenfeld W (1913) Untersuchungen über die scheinbare Gröfse im Sehraume. Z Psychol 65:241–404

    Google Scholar 

  • Boring E (1926) Auditory theory with special reference to intensity, volume, and localization. Am J Psychol 37:157–188

  • Boring E (1932) The physiology of consciousness. Am Assoc Adv Sci 75:32–39

    Google Scholar 

  • Brooke H (1823) A familiar introduction to crystallography. W. Phillips, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Budd M (1985) Music and the emotions: the philosophical theories. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge M (1980) The mind–body problem: a psychological approach. Pergamon, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carr B (2007) Universe of multiverse? Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland P (1981) Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. J Philos 78:67–90

    Google Scholar 

  • Coxeter H (1963) Regular polytopes. Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Craig E (1969) Phenomenal geometry. Brit J Philos Sci 20:121–134

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crick F (1984) Function of the thalamic reticular complex: the searchlight hypothesis. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 81:4586–4590

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Culbertson J (1963) The minds of robots: sense data, memory images, and behavior in conscious automata. University of Illinois Press, Urbana

    Google Scholar 

  • Culbertson J (1976) Sensations, memories and the flow of time: a theory of subjective states—reductive materialism using a space–time analysis. Cromwell Press, UK

    Google Scholar 

  • Daniels N (1972) Thomas Reid’s discovery of a non-Euclidean geometry. Philos Sci 39:219–234

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davies P (1977) Space and time in the modern universe. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes R (1931) The philosophical works of Descartes rendered into English, vol 1. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • DeWitt B (1983) Quantum gravity. Sci Am 249:112–129

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eddington A (1920) Space, time and gravitation: an outline of the general relativity theory. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Eddington A (1928) The nature of the physical world. MacMillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Einhäuser W, Martin K, König P (2004) Are switches in perception of the Necker cube related to eye position? Eur J Neurosci 20:2811–2818

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Einstein A (1961) Relativity: the special and the general theory. Bonanza, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Erkelens C (2012) Contribution of disparity to the perception of 3D shape as revealed by bistability of stereoscopic Necker cubes. See Perceiving 25:561–576

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Erkelens C (2015) The perspective structure of visual space. I-Perception 6:1–13

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Flew A (1951) Essays on logic and language. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Freedman D, van Nieuwenhuizen P (1985) The hidden dimensions of spacetime. Sci Am 52:74–81

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frisby J (1980) Seeing: Illusion, brain and mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gengerelli J (1937) The dichotomy of science and philosophy. Psychol Rev 44:117–137

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibson J (1950) The perception of the visual world. Houghton Mifflin, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson J (1959) Perception as a function of stimulation. In: Koch S (ed) Psychology: a study of a science, vol 1. McGraw-Hill, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson J (2015) The ecological approach to visual perception. Psychology Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson J, Waddell D (1952) Homogenous retinal stimulation and visual perception. Am J Psychol 65:263–270

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gloning I, Gloning K, Hoff H (1968) Neuropsychological symptoms and syndromes in lesions of the occipital lobe and the adjacent areas. Gauthier-Villars, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Gooddy W (1988) Time and the nervous system. Praeger, New York

  • Goodman N (1977) The structure of appearance. Reidel, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gregory R (1970) The intelligent eye. McGraw-Hill, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gregory R (1980) Perceptions as hypotheses. Philos Trans R Soc B 290:181–197

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gregory R (2007) The great detective. Nature 445:152

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grünbaum A (1973) Philosophical problems of space and time. Reidel, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Haber R (1980) How we perceive depth from flat pictures. Am Sci 68:370–380

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacker P (1987) Languages, minds and brains. In: Blakemore C, Greenfield S (eds) Mindwaves: thoughts on intelligence, identity, and consciousness. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacker P (1991) Experimental methods and conceptual confusion: an investigation into R. L. Gregory’s theory of perception. Iyyun. Jerus Philos Q 40:289–314

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanson N (1958) Patterns of discovery: an inquiry into the conceptual foundations of science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardy L, Rand G, Rittler M (1951) Investigation of visual space: the Blumenfeld alleys. AMA Arch Ophthalmol 445:53–63

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harrison J (1961) The third dimension. Proc Aristotelian Soc 61:151–168

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Helmholtz H (1961) Helmholtz’s treatise on physiological optics. Dover, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Herbert N (1993) Elemental mind: human consciousness and the new physics. Dutton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hillebrand F (1929) Lehre von den Gesichtsempfindungen: Auf Grund Hinterlassener Aufzeichnungen. Springer, Vienna

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hinckfuss I (1975) The existence of space and time. Clarendon, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hochberg J (1959) Spatial representation. Acta Psychol 15:265–267

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hochberg J (1971) Perception II. Space and movement. In: Kling J, Riggs L (eds) Woodworth and Schlosberg’s experimental psychology. Holt, Rinehart and Winston, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Holton G (1952) Introduction to concepts and theories in physical science. Addison-Wesley, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins J (1973) Visual geometry. Philos Rev 82:3–34

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hubel D, Wiesel T (1979) Brain mechanisms of vision. Sci Am 214:150–162

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Indow T (1994) Metrics in color spaces: Im kleinen und in großen. In: Fisher G, Laming D (eds) Contributions to mathematical psychology, psychometrics, and methodology. Springer, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • James W (1879) The spatial quale. J Specul Philos 13:64–87

    Google Scholar 

  • James W (1890) Principles of psychology. Henry Holt and Co., New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • James G, James R, Alchian A (1976) Mathematics dictionary, 4th edn. Van Nostrand Reinhold, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Jefferson G (1960) Selected papers. Thomas, Springfield

    Google Scholar 

  • Julesz B (1971) Foundations of cyclopean perception. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Jung C (1972) The structure and dynamics of the psyche. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Katz D (1911) Die Erscheinungsweisen der Farben und ihre Beeinflussung durch die individuelle Erfahrung. Z Psychol 7:1–425

    Google Scholar 

  • Katz D (1935) The world of colour. Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner and Co., London

    Google Scholar 

  • Kenny A (1984) The legacy of Wittgenstein. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Klauder J (ed) (1972) Magic without magic: John Archibald Wheeler, a collection of essays in honor of his 60th birthday. Freeman, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Koffka K (1935) Principles of Gestalt psychology. Harcourt, Brace and Co, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Köhler W (1947) Gestalt psychology. Liveright, New York

  • Köhler W (1971) Selected papers of Wolfgang Köhler. Liveright, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn T (1962) The structure of scientific revolutions. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Lanczos C (1965) Albert Einstein and the cosmic world order. Interscience, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Lietzmann W (1965) Visual topology. American Elsevier, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Luneburg R (1947) Mathematical analysis of binocular vision. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Luneburg R (1950) The metric of binocular visual space. J Opt Soc Am 40:627–642

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mach E (1894) Popular scientific lectures. Open Court, La Salle

    Google Scholar 

  • Mach E (1906a) The analysis of sensations and the relation of the physical to the psychical. Open Court, La Salle

    Google Scholar 

  • Mach E (1906b) Space and geometry. Open Court, La Salle

    Google Scholar 

  • Mach E (1911) History and root of the principle of the conservation of energy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Mach E (1919) The science of mechanics. Open Court, La Salle

    Google Scholar 

  • Mach E (1976) Knowledge and error. Reidel, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Martin M (1922) Film, surface, and bulky colors and their intermediates. Am J Psychol 33:451–480

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthiessen H (2015) Empirical conditions for a Reidean geometry of visual experience. Topoi. doi:10.1007/s11245-015-9318-3

  • Misner C, Thorne K, Wheeler J (1973) Gravitation. Freeman, San Francisco

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan M (1979) The two spaces. In: Bolton N (ed) Philosophical problems in psychology. Methuen, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan M (1980) Phenomenal space. In: Josephson BD, Ramachandran B (eds) Consciousness and the physical world. Pergammon, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Nakatani H, van Leeuwen C (2007) EEG and eye-events relating to perceptual switching in the Necker cube. In: Proceedings of Fechner Day 23

  • Necker L (1832) Observations on some remarkable optical phenomena seen in Switzerland; and on an optical phenomenon which occurs on viewing a figure of a crystal or geometrical solid. Lond Edinb Philos Mag J Sci 1:329–337

    Google Scholar 

  • Nerlich G (1976) The shape of space. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Pastore N (1971) Selective history of theories of visual perception: 1650–1950. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Penrose L, Penrose R (1958) Impossible objects: a special type of visual illusion. Br J Psychol 49:31–33

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petzoldt J (1922) Mach und die Atomistik. Naturwissenschaften 10:230–231

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petzoldt J (1926) Komplex und Begriff I. Z Psychol 99:74–103

    Google Scholar 

  • Petzoldt J (1927) Komplex und Begriff II. Z Psychol 102:265–306

    Google Scholar 

  • Pirenne M (1950) Descartes and the body–mind problem in physiology. Br J Philos Sci 1:43–59

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pirenne M (1967) Vision and the eye. Chapman and Hall, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Price H (1996) Time’s arrow and Archimedes’ point. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Prichard H (1907) A criticism of the psychologists' treatment of knowledge. Mind 16:27–53

  • Quinn P (1981) On some possible limits to spatial knowledge. Paper presented at the workshop on spatial cognition, University of California, Irvine, 22–25 March 1981

  • Ranucci E, Rollins W (1977) Curiosities of the cube. Thomas Y. Crowell, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach H (1958) The philosophy of space and time. Dover, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach H (1991) The space problem in the new quantum mechanics. Erkenntnis 35:29–47

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosar W (1985) Visual space as physical geometry. Perception 14:403–425

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosar W, Perrott D (1980) Is the engram a stereogram? Paper presented at the Rocky Mountain Psychological Association, 9–12 April 1980, Tucson, AZ

  • Russell B (1927) The analysis of matter. K. Paul, Trench, Trubner and Co., London

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell B (1959) An essay on the foundations of geometry. Dover, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sanford E (1898) A course in experimental psychology. D. C. Heath and Co., Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Santillana G (1954) Lights and shadows in the philosophy of science. Publ Hum 9:187–195

    Google Scholar 

  • Schilder P (1935) The image and appearance of the human body: studies in the constructive energies of the psyche. K. Paul, Trench, Trubner and Co., London

    Google Scholar 

  • Schrödinger E (1967) What is life? The physical aspect of the living cell and Mind and matter. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Schutz B (1980) Geometrical methods of mathematical physics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sirag S (1984) The physics of hyperspace. Paper presented at the conference Space, time, and mind, 30 June–1 July 1984, University of California, Santa Barbara

  • Smart J (1964) Problems of space and time. Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith B (1988) Foundations of Gestalt theory. Philosophia, Munich

    Google Scholar 

  • Smythies J (1956) The analysis of perception. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Smythies J (1994) The walls of Plato’s Cave. Avebury Press, Aldershot

    Google Scholar 

  • Stebbing L (1937) Philosophy and the physicists. Methuen, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Stout G (1899) A manual of psychology. University Correspondence College Press, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Straus E (1963) The primary world of senses: a vindication of sensory experience. Free Press of Glencoe, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson P (1966) The bounds of sense. Methuen, London

  • Stroll A (1988) Surfaces. University of Minnesota Press, Minnesota

    Google Scholar 

  • Stromberg W (1975) Conceptual confusions in the Gestalt psychology of visual perception. Dissertation, University of California

  • Suppes P (1977) Is visual space Euclidean? Synthese 35:397–421

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Teuber H, Battersby W, Bender M (1960) Visual defects after penetrating missile wounds of the brain. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thom R (1975) Structural stability and morphogenesis: an outline of a general theory of models. W. A. Benjamin, Reading

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomsen D (1983) Many dimensions in gravity theory. Science 124:60–61

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Unruh J (2001) Impossible objects. Sterling, New York

  • Walker E (1970) The nature of consciousness. Math Biosci 7:131–178

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watson A (1978) A Riemannian geometric explanation of the visual illusions and figural after-effects. In: Leeuwenberg E, Buffart H (eds) Formal theories of visual perception. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Wertheimer M (1938) Laws of organization in perceptual forms. In: Ellis W (ed) A source book of Gestalt psychology. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl H (1949) Philosophy of mathematics and natural science. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheatstone C (1838) Contributions to the physiology of vision. Part the first. On some remarkable, and hitherto unobserved, phenomena of binocular rivions. Philos Trans R Soc 128:371–394

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler J (1968) Superspace and the nature of quantum geometrodynamics. In: DeWitt C, Wheeler J (eds) Battelle rencontres: 1967. Mathematics & physics. W.A. Benjamin, New York  

  • Wheeler J (1973) From relativity to mutability. In: Mehra J (ed) The physicist’s conception of nature. Reidel, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler J (1977) Genesis and observership. In: Butts R, Hintikka J (eds) Foundational problems in the special sciences. Reidel, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler J (1980) Beyond the black hole. In: Woolf H (ed) Some strangeness in the proportion: a centennial symposium to celebrate the achievements of Albert Einstein. Addison-Wesley, Reading

    Google Scholar 

  • Zajonc A (1995) Catching the light: the entwined history of light and mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to William H. Rosar.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Rosar, W.H. The Dimensionality of Visual Space. Topoi 35, 531–570 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-016-9385-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-016-9385-0

Keywords

Navigation