Skip to main content
Log in

An Information Packaging Approach to Presuppositions and Conventional Implicatures

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Within the relevant semantics and pragmatics literature the terms “presupposition” and “conventional implicature” are used in a variety of different, but frequently overlapping, ways. The overlaps are perhaps not surprising, given that the two categories of conveyed meaning share the property of remaining constant in the scope of other operators—the property (Tonhauser et al. in Language 89:66–109, 2013) usefully characterize as projectivity. One of my purposes in this paper will be to try to clarify these different usages. In addition to that we will explore two additional properties which are shared by some of these projective contents—strong contextual felicity (Tonhauser et al. in Language 89:66–109, 2013), and neutralizability (Abbott in Drawing the boundaries of meaning: Neo-Gricean studies in pragmatics and semantics in honor of Laurence R. Horn. John Benjamins, Philadelphia, 2006). The idea is to try to explain all three properties by taking into account information packaging.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Or necessitated. If presupposition failure results in lack of a truth value for the presupposing sentence (as believed by many people, in addition to Frege and Strawson), then the relation between that sentence and its presuppositions can’t be classical entailment, since modus tollens would no longer hold in this case. I will continue to use the terms “entail” and “entailment”, assuming this proviso.

  2. The useful term “at-issue”, in this sense, originated with Bill Ladusaw in classes he taught at UC Santa Cruz in the 1990’s. Its spread has been aided by some of his students [e.g. Chris Barker (e.g. 1999) and Chris Potts (e.g. 2005)].

  3. Larry Horn has reminded me that a number of scholars (e.g. Neale 1999, Predelli 2003) have argued that what is conveyed by therefore may indeed be at-issue in some cases, but I don’t know that I am convinced. I will continue to use therefore as one example of a conventional implicature, and hope that it does not affect any of my important claims in this paper.

  4. There is another proposition associated with definite descriptions, and that is that their descriptive content applies uniquely to an entity in the relevant universe of discourse. Horn and Abbott (2012) argue that this proposition is not entailed, and is thus a conventional implicature rather than a presupposition. We will return to the uniqueness implicature briefly below.

  5. These tables are revised versions of Tables 1 and 2 in Abbott (2006).

  6. Tonhauser et al. investigated another property which they termed “obligatory local effect”, having to do with the preservation of projective content under the scope of other operators. We will not be concerned with that property here.

  7. The ordinary, every day senses of the word “presuppose” are (according to my American Heritage dictionary): “1. To believe or suppose in advance. 2. To require or involve necessarily as an antecedent.” I can’t help but feel that the use of the terms “presuppose” and “presupposition” has encouraged the widespread but obviously false belief that, in order for an utterance to be felicitous, its presuppositions must belong to the common ground. We shall see that this is true for only some cases—definitely not all.

  8. There are, of course, complications for this claim. Conjunctions and disjunctions present two of them. See Abbott (2000), n. 7, p. 1431f, for discussion.

  9. Some comments in Simons et al. (2013) suggest that this view is being revised, by at least some of the authors. Cf. note 9, p. 9. See also Simons et al. (2014).

  10. Perhaps this is a good place to make clear that I have reservations about the QUD approach to discourse, and specifically, any requirement that there always be a QUD. Discourse initial utterances, for example, seem to present a problem for such a requirement.

  11. I have to confess that at times, this explanation seems too hand-wavy to me.

  12. See also some related ideas in Horn (1981), Abusch (2002), and Simons (2003).

  13. Larry Horn (p.c.) has objected to my claim that these pairs are very similar. Once again, I’m not sure that I’m convinced.

References

  • Abbott B (2000) Presuppositions as nonassertions. J Pragmat 32:1419–1437

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abbott B (2006) Where have some of the presuppositions gone? In: Birner BW, Ward G (eds) Drawing the boundaries of meaning: Neo-Gricean studies in pragmatics and semantics in honor of Laurence R. Horn. John Benjamins, Philadelphia

    Google Scholar 

  • Abbott B (2008a) Issues in the semantics and pragmatics of definite descriptions in English. In: Gundel JK, Hedberg N (eds) Reference: interdisciplinary perspectives. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Abbott B (2008b) Presuppositions and common ground. Linguist Philos 31:523–538

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abbott B, Horn LR (2011) Nonfamiliarity and indefinite descriptions. Paper presented at the annual LSA meeting, Pittsburgh, January 2011. Available on line at http://www.msu.edu/~abbottb/Nonfam&Indef.pdf

  • Abusch D (2002) Lexical alternatives as a source of pragmatic presuppositions. SALT 12:1–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bach K (1999) The myth of conventional implicature. Linguist Philos 22:327–366

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beaver D (2010) Have you noticed that your Belly Button Lint colour is related to the colour of your clothing? In: Bäuerle R, Reyle U, Zimmerman TE (eds) Presuppositions and discourse: essays offered to Hans Kamp. Emerald Group Publishing, Bingley

    Google Scholar 

  • Birner BJ, Ward G (1994) Uniqueness, familiarity, and the definite article in English. BLS 20:93–102

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Birner BJ, Ward G (1998) Informational status and noncanonical word order. John Benjamins, Philadelphia

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia G, McConnell-Ginet S (1990) Meaning and grammar. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Delin J, Oberlander J (1995) Syntactic constraints on discourse structure: the case of it-clefts. Linguistics 33:465–500

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fraurud K (1990) Definiteness and the processing of noun phrases in natural discourse. J Semant 7:395–433

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frege G (1892) Über Sinn und Bedeutung. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und Philosophische Kritik 100: 25–50. Trans. as ‘On sense and reference’. In Geach P, Black M (eds) (1952) Translations from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege. Blackwell, Oxford

  • Frege G (1918–1919) The thought: a logical inquiry. Geach P (trans) (1955) Mind 65:289–311

  • Gauker C (2008) Against accommodation: Heim, van der Sandt, and the presupposition projection problem. Philos Perspect 22:171–205

  • Geurts B (1995) Presupposing. Dissertation, University of Stuttgart

  • Grafton SN (2010) U is for undertow. Berkley Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice HP (1975) Logic and conversation. In: Cole P, Morgan JL (eds) Syntax and semantics: speech acts, vol 3. Academic Press, New York. Reprinted in Grice P (1989)

  • Grice P (1981) Presupposition and conversational implicature. In: Cole P (ed) Radical pragmatics. Academic Press, New York. Reprinted in Grice P (1989)

  • Grice P (1989) Studies in the way of words. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawkins JA (1978) Definiteness and indefiniteness. Humanities Press, Atlantic Highland

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawkins JA (1991) On (in)definite articles: implicatures and (un)grammaticality prediction. J Linguist 27:405–442

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horn LR (1969) A presuppositional analysis of only and even. In: Binnick RI, Davison A, Green GM, Morgan JL (eds) CLS, vol 5. Chicago Linguistic Society, Chicago, IL, pp 98–116

  • Horn LR (1981) A pragmatic approach to certain ambiguities. Linguist Philos 4:321–358

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horn LR (2007) Toward a Fregean pragmatics: Voraussetzung, Nebengedanke, Andeutung. In: Kecskes I, Horn LR (eds) Explorations in pragmatics: linguistic, cognitive and intercultural aspects. Mouton de Gruyter, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn LR (2013) I love me some datives: Expressive meaning, free datives, and F-implicature. In: Gutzmann D, Gärtner H-M (eds) Beyond expressives: explorations in use-conditional meaning. Brill, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn LR, Abbott B (2012) 〈the, a〉: (in)definiteness and implicature. In: Kabasenche WP, O’Rourke M, Slater MH (eds) Reference and referring: topics in contemporary philosophy, vol 10. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 325–355

  • Karttunen L (1974) Presupposition and linguistic context. Theor Linguist 1: 181–194. Reprinted, In: Davis S (ed) (1991) Pragmatics: a reader. Oxford University Press, New York

  • Karttunen L, Peters S (1979) Conventional implicature. In: Oh C-K, Dineen DA (eds) Syntax and semantics 11: presupposition. Academic Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kiparsky P, Kiparsky C (1970) Fact. In: Bierwisch M, Heidolph KE (eds) Progress in linguistics. Mouton, The Hague

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D (1979) Scorekeeping in a language game. J Philos Logic 8:339–359

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neale S (1999) Coloring and composition. In: Stainton R, Murasugi K (eds) Philosophy and linguistics. Westview, Boulder

    Google Scholar 

  • Oberlander J, Delin J (1996) The function and interpretation of reverse wh-clefts in spoken discourse. Lang Speech 39:185–227

    Google Scholar 

  • Poesio M, Vieira R (1998) A corpus-based investigation of definite description use. Comput Linguist 24:183–216

    Google Scholar 

  • Potts C (2005) The logic of conventional implicatures. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Predelli S (2003) Scare quotes and their relation to other semantic issues. Linguist Philos 26:1–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prince EF (1978) A comparison of wh-clefts and it-clefts in discourse. Language 54:883–906

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts C (1996) Information structure in discourse: Toward an integrated formal theory of pragmatics. In: Yoon JH, Andreas Kathol A (eds) Ohio State University working papers in Linguistics, vol 49. The Ohio State University, Columbus, OH, pp 91–136

  • Simons M (2001) On the conversational basis of some presuppositions. In: SALT, vol 11. CLC Publications, Ithaca, NY, pp. 431–448

  • Simons M (2003) Presupposition and accommodation: understanding the Stalnakerian picture. Philos Stud 112:251–278

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simons M, Beaver D, Roberts C, Tonhauser J (2013) Projection as a function of information structuring. Paper presented at the (2013) Workshop in Philosophy and Linguistics. University of Michigan, Ann Arbor

    Google Scholar 

  • Simons M, Tonhauser J, Beaver D, Roberts C (2010) What projects and why. In: SALT, vol 20. CLC Publications, Ithaca, NY, pp 309–327

  • Simons M, Kummerfeld E, Beaver D, Roberts C, Tonhauser J (2014) The best question: explaining the projection behavior of factives. Discourse Process (to appear)

  • Stalnaker RC (1973) Presuppositions. J Philos Logic 2:447–457

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker RC (1974) Pragmatic presuppositions. In: Milton MK, Unger PK (eds) Semantics and philosophy. New York University Press, New York. References are to the reprint in Davis S (ed) (1991) Pragmatics: a reader. Oxford University Press, New York

  • Strawson PF (1950) On referring. Mind 59:320–344

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson PF (1952) Introduction to logical theory. Methuen, London. References are to the 1967 University Paperback edition

  • Tonhauser J, Roberts C, Beaver D, Simons M (2013) Toward a taxonomy of projective content. Language 89:66–109

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

An earlier version of this paper was presented to the Philosophy Department, at the University of Texas, Austin, and I would like to thank that audience for their helpful comments. Larry Horn also read an earlier version, and gave me some very useful comments. This paper draws heavily on prior papers of mine, each of which acknowledges the many comments, suggestions, criticisms, etc. from other people which have improved its content. Probably I should repeat all those acknowledgements here, but I’m not going to.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Barbara Abbott.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Abbott, B. An Information Packaging Approach to Presuppositions and Conventional Implicatures. Topoi 35, 9–21 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-014-9285-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-014-9285-0

Keywords

Navigation