Skip to main content
Log in

Recovering Thomas Kuhn

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The interpretive plasticity of Kuhn’s philosophical work has been reinforced by readings informed by other philosophical, historiographic or sociological projects. This paper highlights several aspects of Kuhn’s work that have been neglected by such readings. First, Kuhn’s early contribution to several subsequent philosophical developments has been unduly neglected. Kuhn’s postscript discussion of “exemplars” should be recognized as one of the earliest versions of a conception of theories as “mediating models.” Kuhn’s account of experimental practice has also been obscured by readings that assimilate his views to Quinean holism. Second, three distinctive Kuhnian themes have been insufficiently recognized. Kuhn’s challenge to received philosophical views has been domesticated by reading him as offering an alternative conception of scientific knowledge. Kuhn is better understood as rejecting knowledge-centric accounts altogether, in favor of understanding the practice of research. Kuhn’s conception of that activity, as conceptual “articulation,” has accordingly also not been given its due. Finally, Kuhn’s career-long insistence on the mutual accountability of philosophy of science and the philosophy of mind and language calls attention to the extent to which these fields have now drifted apart.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. None of these texts cites or indexes Kuhn.

  2. Hence, the infamous quotation about Lavoisier, for which commentators have usually given insufficient emphasis or comprehension to the verb: “after discovering oxygen, Lavoisier worked in a different world” (1970, 118, my emphasis).

  3. The classic introduction of this phrase was in Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind: “in characterizing an episode or a state as one that of knowing, we are not giving an empirical description of that episode or state; we are placing it in the logical space of reasons, of justifying and being able to justify what one says” (1997, 76).

  4. Oreskes and Conway 2010 show how the strategic political uses of manufactured “controversy” have been integral to conservative resistance to environmental and health regulations in the United States for the past four decades. Similar strategies have also informed the post-1960 s renewal of efforts to restrict the teaching of evolutionary biology in American public schools.

  5. The problem with lowest-common-denominator formulations, e.g., that species evolve in part by natural selection over a multi-billion year history of the earth or that there has been significant and growing anthropogenic climate change since the beginnings of the Industrial Revolution, is not that they are false, but that they understate the sophisticated and detailed articulation of scientific understanding in these domains, even though more specific formulations would yield dissent on details within a common space of scientific reasoning.

References

  • Carnap R (1950) Empiricism, semantics and ontology. Rev Int de Philos 11:20–40

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright N (1983) How the laws of physics lie. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Conant JB (1961) Science and common sense. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend P (1962) Explanation, reduction, and empiricism. In: Feigl H, Maxwell G (eds) Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, vol 3. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp 28–97

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend P (1975) Against method. New Left Books, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller S (2000) Thomas Kuhn. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere R (1979) Understanding scientific reasoning. Holt, Rinehart & Winston, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere R (1988) Explaining science. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking I (1983) Representing and intervening. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanson NR (1958) Patterns of discovery. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland J (1998) Having thought. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn T (1970) The structure of scientific revolutions, 2nd edn. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn T (1977) The essential tension. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn T (2000) The road since structure. In: Conant J, Haugeland J (eds) University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Lakatos I (1970) Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In: Lakatos I, Musgrave A (eds) Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 91–196

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre A (1971) Against the self-images of the age. Duckworth, London

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre A (1980) Epistemological crises, dramatic narrative and the philosophy of science. In: Gutting G (ed) Paradigms and revolutions. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, pp 54–74

    Google Scholar 

  • Merton R (1973) The sociology of science. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan M, Morrison M (eds) (1999) Models as mediators. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Oreskes N, Conway E (2010) Merchants of doubt. Bloomsbury Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi M (1958) Personal knowledge. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper K (1970) Normal science and its dangers. In: Lakatos I, Musgrave A (eds) Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 51–58

    Google Scholar 

  • Price DS (1963) Big science, little science. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Price D (1965) The scientific estate. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine WVO (1953) From a logical point of view. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Rouse J (1998) Kuhn and scientific practices. Configurations 6:33–51

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rouse J (2003) Kuhn’s philosophy of scientific practice. In: Nickles T (ed) Thomas Kuhn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 101–121

    Google Scholar 

  • Rouse J (Forthcoming) Articulating the world: conceptual understanding and the scientific image

  • Scheffler I (1967) Science and subjectivity. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Scriven M (1962) Explanations, predictions and laws. In: Feigl H, Maxwell G (eds) Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, vol 3. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp 170–230

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars W (1997) Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars W (2007) In the space of reasons. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapere D (1964) The structure of scientific revolutions. Philos Rev 73:383–394

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stegmüller W (1976) The structure and dynamics of theories. Springer, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppe F (1977) The structure of scientific theories. University of Illinois Press, Urbana

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P (1967) What is a scientific theory? In: Morgenbesser S (ed) Philosophy of science today. Basic Books, London, pp 55–67

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor C (1971) Interpretation and the sciences of man. Rev Metaphys 25:3–51

    Google Scholar 

  • Teller P (2001) Twilight of the perfect model model. Erkenntnis 55:393–415

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin S (1961) Foresight and understanding. Indiana University Press, Bloomington

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin S (1972) Human understanding. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen B (1980) The scientific image. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson B (1970) Rationality. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch P (1958) The idea of a social science. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joseph Rouse.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Rouse, J. Recovering Thomas Kuhn. Topoi 32, 59–64 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-012-9143-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-012-9143-x

Keywords

Navigation