Skip to main content
Log in

Detecting heterogeneous risk attitudes with mixed gambles

  • Published:
Theory and Decision Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We propose a task for eliciting attitudes toward risk that is close to real-world risky decisions which typically involve gains and losses. The task consists of accepting or rejecting gambles that provide a gain with probability \(p\) and a loss with probability \(1-p\). We employ finite mixture models to uncover heterogeneity in risk preferences and find that (i) behavior is heterogeneous, with one half of the subjects behaving as expected utility maximizers, (ii) for the others, reference-dependent models perform better than those where subjects derive utility from final outcomes, (iii) models with sign-dependent decision weights perform better than those without, and (iv) there is no evidence for loss aversion. The procedure is sufficiently simple so that it can be easily used in field or lab experiments where risk elicitation is not the main experiment.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Harrison and Rutström (2009) apply finite mixture models too in order to distinguish EU from non-EU behavior. However, they classify decisions instead of subjects. Therefore, their results are not directly comparable to Bruhin et al. (2010) and Conte et al. (2011).

  2. Mixed gambles bring the experimental task closer to real-world risky decisions than most previous experimental work. Real-world decisions typically involve gain–loss gambles, but most prior experimental research on the elicitation of risk attitudes used lotteries involving only gains (e.g., Brunner et al. 2007; Ebert and Wiesen 2009; Deck and Schlesinger 2010) or lotteries involving either only gains or only losses (e.g., Holt and Laury 2002; Fehr-Duda et al. 2010; Bruhin et al. 2010).

  3. Most of prior experimental work on reference-dependent models has been limited to testing a subset of the behavioral features of PT. For example, Abdellaoui (2000) and Bruhin et al. (2010) use lotteries involving either only gains or only losses and estimate probability distortion parameters for the gain and loss domains but do not estimate a loss aversion parameter since that is neither feasible nor meaningful. Tversky and Kahneman (1992) and Abdellaoui et al. (2007) study all features of risk preferences proposed by PT but use hypothetical choices. Abdellaoui et al. (2008) use real incentives for lotteries with only gains but not for lotteries with only losses or with gains and losses. As far as we know, there are only two other studies that analyze all aspects of PT using monetary incentives for all types of lotteries: Harrison and Rutström (2009) and Tanaka et al. (2010).

  4. The regressions reported in Table 5 exclude the eight multiple switchers so that the number of accepted lotteries corresponds to the switching point. The subsequent analysis includes all 109 subjects.

  5. Given that our gambles only have three probability values and that we will measure loss aversion in the PT model, we cannot identify a two-parameter probability weighting function.

  6. The function \(u\) has a kink at \(r\) and is smooth everywhere else. The kink is caused by loss aversion, and does not reflect an intrinsic value of outcomes. That is, it is plausible that the basic utility function is differentiable at \(r\). Thus, they define the loss aversion index as \(\lambda =u_{\uparrow }^{\prime }(x|r)/u_{\downarrow }^{\prime }(x|r),\) where \(u_{\uparrow }^{\prime }(x|r)\) denotes the left, and \(u_{\downarrow }^{\prime }(x|r)\) the right derivative of \(u\) at \(r\) (both derivatives are assumed to exist and be positive and finite). If the loss aversion index is equal to 1, there is no loss aversion. If the index is greater than 1, the agent is loss averse.

  7. Note that the above individual likelihood contribution is highly non-linear even after taking logs. Maximizing the finite mixture model’s likelihood is therefore not trivial and standard numerical maximization techniques, such as the BFGS algorithm for example, will usually fail in finding its global maximum. We therefore apply Dempster et al’s (1977) expectation maximization (EM) algorithm to obtain the model’s maximum likelihood estimates \(\hat{\Psi }\). Instead of maximizing the finite mixture model’s complete log likelihood, the EM algorithm proceeds iteratively in two steps: In the E-step, it computes the individual ex-post probabilities of type-membership given the actual fit of the model. In the subsequent M-step, the EM algorithm updates the model’s fit using these ex-post probabilities to maximize each type’s log likelihood contribution separately.

  8. Lo et al. (2001) proposed a statistical test (LMR-test) to select among finite mixture models with varying numbers of types, which is based on Vuong’s (1989) test for non-nested models. However, the LMR-test is unlikely to be suitable when the alternative is a single-type model with strongly non-normal outcomes (Muthén 2003).

  9. The finding is also consistent with evidence from field studies. For example, both Snowberg and Wolfers (2010) and Jullien and Salanié (2000) find that inverse s-shape probability weighting dominates in explaining why there is overbetting on the long-shot horse while favorites are underbet. In the context of insurance choices, Cohen and Einav (2007) and Barseghyan et al. (2010) find preferences in which inverse s-shape probability weighting plays the most important role.

References

  • Abdellaoui, M. (2000). Parameter-free elicitation of utility and probability weighting functions. Management Science, 46, 1497–1512.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Abdellaoui, M., Bleichrodt, H., & Paraschiv, C. (2007). Loss aversion under prospect theory: A parameter-free measurement. Management Science, 53, 1659–1674.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abdellaoui, M., Bleichrodt, H., & L’Haridon, O. (2008). A tractable method to measure utility and loss aversion under prospect theory. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 36, 245–266.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Barseghyan, L., Molinari, F., O’Donoghue, T., & Teitelbaum, J. (2010). The nature of risk preferences: Evidence from insurance choices, Working paper, SSRN.

  • Biernacki, C., Celeux, G., & Govaert, G. (2000). Assessing a mixture model for clustering with the integrated completed likelihood. IEEE Transactions on Pattern Analysis and Machine Intelligence, 22(7), 719–725.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bordalo, P., Gennaioli, N., & Shleifer, A. (2012). Salience theory of choice under risk. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 127(3), 1243–1285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brunner, T., Levinsky, R., & Qiu, J., (2007). A note on skewness seeking: An experimental analysis,” Jena Economic Research Papers, 079.

  • Bruhin, A., Fehr-Duda, H., & Epper, T. (2010). Risk and rationality: Uncovering heterogeneity in probability distortion. Econometrica, 78(4), 1375–1412.

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, A., & Einav, L. (2007). Estimating risk preferences from deductible choice. The American Economic Review, 97(3), 745–788.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conte, A., Hey, J., & Moffat, P. (2011). Mixture models of choice under risk. Journal of Econometrics, 162(1), 79–82.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Deck, C., & Schlesinger, H. (2010). Exploring higher-order risk effects. Review of Economic Studies, 77, 1403–1420.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Dempster, A. P., Laird, N. M., & Rubin, D. B. (1977). Maximum likelihood from incomplete data via the EM Algorithm. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society Series B, 39, 1–38.

    MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Ebert, S., & Wiesen, D. (2009). An experimental methodology for testing for prudence and third-order preferences, Bonn Econ Discussion Papers, 21.

  • El-Gamal, M., & Grether, D. (1995). Are people Bayesian? Uncovering behavioral strategies. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 90, 1137–1145.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Ert, E., & Erev, I. (2010). On the descriptive value of loss aversion under risk, Working paper, Harvard Business School.

  • Falk, A., & Heckman, J. (2009). Lab experiments are a major source of knowledge in the social sciences. Science, 326(5952), 535–538.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  ADS  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr-Duda, H., Bruhin, A., Epper, T., & Schubert, R. (2010). Rationality on the rise: Why relative risk aversion increases with stake size. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 40(2), 147–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gächter, S., Johnson, E., & Herrmann, A. (2007). Individual-level loss aversion in riskless and risky choices, Centre for Decision Research and Experimental Economics Discussion Paper Series, ISSN 1749–3293.

  • Goldstein, W., & Einhorn, H. (1987). Expression theory and the preference reversal phenomena. Psychological Review, 94, 236–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greiner, B. (2004). An online recruiting system for economic experiments. In K. Kremer & V. Macho (Eds.), Forschung und wissenschaftliches Rechnen 2003. GWDG Bericht 63 (pp. 79–93). Göttingen: Ges. für Wiss.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrison, G., & Rutström, E. (2009). Expected utility theory and prospect theory: One wedding and a decent funeral. Experimental Economics, 12, 133–158.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Hey, J., & Orme, C. (1994). Investigating generalizations of expected utility theory using experimental data. Econometrica, 62(6), 1291–1326.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Holt, C., & Laury, S. (2002). Risk aversion and incentive effects. American Economic Review, 92(5), 1644–1655.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hong, C. S. (1983). A generalization of the quasilinear mean with applications to the measurement of income inequality and decision theory resolving the Allais Paradox. Econometrica, 51(4), 1065–1092.

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Houser, D., & Winter, J. (2004). How do behavioral assumptions affect structural inference? Journal of Business and Economic Statistics, 22, 64–79.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Houser, D., Keane, M., & McCabe, K. (2004). Behavior in a dynamic decision problem: An analysis of experimental evidence using a Bayesian type classification algorithm. Econometrica, 72, 781–822.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Jullien, B., & Salanié, B. (2000). Estimating preferences under risk: The case of racetrack bettors. Journal of Political Economy, 108(3), 503–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision making under risk. Econometrica, 47, 263–292.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Köbberling, V., & Wakker, P. (2005). An index of loss aversion. Journal of Economic Theory, 122, 119–131.

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Lattimore, P. K., Baker, J. R., & Witte, A. D. (1992). The influence of probability on risky choice. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 17, 377–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levitt, S., & List, J. (2007). What do laboratory experiments measuring social preferences reveal about the real world? The Journal of Economic Perspectives, 21(2), 153–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lo, Y., Mendell, N. R., & Rubin, D. B. (2001). Testing the number of components in a normal mixture. Biometrika, 88, 767–778.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • McFadden, D. (1981). Econometric models of probabilistic choice. In C. Manski & D. McFadden (Eds.), Structural analysis of discrete data with econometric applications. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLachlan, G., & Peel, D. (2000). Finite mixture models., Wiley series in probabilities and statistics New York: Wiley.

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Muthén, B. (2003). Statistical and substantive checking in growth mixture modeling: Comment on Bauer and Curran (2003). Psychological Methods, 8(3), 369–377.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Quiggin, J. (1982). A theory of anticipated utility. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 3, 323–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, U., & Zank, H. (2005). What is loss aversion? Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 30, 157–167.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Schoemaker, P. (1982). The expected utility model: It’s variants purposes, evidence and limitations. Journal of Economic Literature, 20, 529–563.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snowberg, Eric., & Wolfers, Justin. (2010). Explaining the favorite-longshot bias: Is risk love or misperceptions? Journal of Political Economy, 118(4), 723–746.

  • Stahl, D., & Wilson, P. (1995). On players’ models of other players: Theory and experimental evidence. Games and Economic Behavior, 10, 218–254.

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Starmer, C. (2000). Developments in non-expected utility theory: The hunt for a descriptive theory of choice under risk. Journal of Economic Literature, 38, 332–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tanaka, T., Camerer, C. F., & Nguyen, Q. (2010). Risk and time preferences: Experimental and household survey data from Vietnam. The American Economic Review, 100(1), 557–571.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1992). Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5, 297–323.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Vuong, Q. H. (1989). Likelihood ratio tests for model selection and non-nested hypotheses. Econometrica, 57, 307–333.

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P. (2010). Prospect theory for risk and uncertainty. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We thank James Cox, Erik Eyster, Glenn Harrison, Botond Koszegi, and Peter Wakker for various comments and suggestions. We also thank seminar and conference participants at HEC Paris, University of Lausanne, University Jaume I Castellon, Economic Science Association World Meeting in Copenhagen, International Meeting on Behavioral and Experimental Economics in Barcelona, D-TEA Workshop in Paris, and the 68th European Meetings of the Econometric Society in Toulouse. Support from HEC Paris Foundation, Swiss National Science Foundation grant 135602, NOVA FORUM, and Fundação para a Ciência e Tecnologia is gratefully acknowledged.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Luís Santos-Pinto.

Appendices

Appendix

Table 9 reports the parameter estimates of the mixture models where the non-EU have RDU or WU preferences, respectively.

Table 9 Parameter estimates of non-reference-dependent mixture models

Figure 2 displays the probabilities of EU-type-membership for the two models. We see that both models cleanly segregate subjects into the two types. In the model where the non-EU types have WU preferences, we find 58 EU subjects and 51 non-EU subjects. In the model where the non-EU types have RDU preferences, we find 55 EU subjects and 54 non-EU subjects. In contrast to the reference-dependent models, however, the individual classifications of the non-reference-dependent models differ considerably: the RDU and the WU models only classify 54 out of the 109 subjects into the same types. Table 10 reports likelihoods for the BIC and AIC information criteria.

Fig. 2
figure 2

Distribution of individual probabilites of EU-type-membership

Table 10 BIC and AIC

Experimental material: detecting heterogeneous risk attitudes with mixed gambles

Research Study.

Decision Making under Risk.

Instructions.

Read these instructions carefully as your understanding of them will affect your ability to earn money.

Your decision sheet shows a table with ten decisions listed on the left. Each decision is a choice between “Accept” and “Reject” the lottery. If you Accept the lottery you have the chance of either winning or losing some money. If you Reject the lottery, you will not earn anything and you will not lose anything—your payoff will be zero.

You will make ten choices and record these by ten check marks, but only one of them will be used in the end to determine your earnings. Before you start making your ten choices, please let me explain how these choices will affect your earnings for this part of the experiment.

We will use a ten-sided die to determine payoffs; the faces are numbered from 1 to 10 (the “0” face of the die will serve as 10.) After you have made all of your choices, we will throw this die twice, once to select one of the ten decisions to be used, and a second time to determine your payoff if you chose “Accept” for that lottery.

Even though you will make ten decisions, only one of these will end up affecting your earnings, but you will not know in advance which decision will be used. Obviously, each decision has an equal chance of being used in the end.

Now, please look at Decision 1 at the top of Example Problem Set on the next page (Table 11). If you Accept the lottery, you will earn 50.00 CHF if the throw of the ten-sided die is 1, and you will lose 5.00 CHF if the throw is 2–10. The other Decisions are similar, except that as you move down the table, the value of the highest payoff decreases. For each Decision, you are asked to choose whether or not you want to take the gamble by checking the Accept or Reject columns.

This table is just an example and is not to be used to make real decisions. The problems for which you will be asked to make decisions have a similar structure, but the magnitudes of the gains and losses will be different, as well as the numbers on the dies that will determine if you make a gain or a loss.

Your gains—You may win or lose money if you Accept the lottery. If you win, you will be paid the amount won; if you lose you will have to pay the amount lost. The maximum amount that you can lose in the gambles is CHF 65. However, because we do not want you to end with less money than you started out you will be given CHF 65 from which we will deduct any loss that you may experience. In addition, you will be paid an additional CHF 15 as a compensation for your time spent.

Table 11 Example problem set (not to be used for actual decisions)

There will be a total of three problem sets (A B, and C), each composed of ten decisions. In each problem set, the gains, losses and chances to win will be different. In the end, we will only use one of the three problem sets to determine your earnings. The choice of which problem set to use to determine earnings will be made using a six-sided die. Each problem set has the same probability of being chosen. If the outcome of the six-sided die is either 1 or 2, problem set A counts, if the outcome is either 3 or 4 set B counts, and if the outcome is either 5 or 6 set C counts.

To summarize, in each problem set, you will make ten choices: for each choice, you will have to decide between Accept or Reject the lottery. You may choose Accept for some decisions and Reject for other decisions, and you may change your decisions and make them in any order. When you are finished with making all ten choices, you will move on to the next problem set. This will be repeated three times. After the three problem sets are done, we will ask you a few demographic questions about yourself.

At the end, a randomly chosen participant will first cast a six- sided die, numbered from 1 to 6, and then a 10-sided die, numbered 0 to 9 to select the decision which determines your earnings. The 6-sided die will decide which problem will be used, and the 10-sided die will decide which decision will be used to determine your gains or losses. The same participant will then throw the 10-sided die again to choose whether you win or lose on that lottery if you decided to Accept that lottery. You will be paid all earnings in cash when finished.

Are there any questions? Now you may begin making your choices. Please, do not talk with anyone while we are doing this; raise your hand if you have a question.

Problem set A

1.1 Instructions

Your decision sheet shows ten decisions listed on the left (Table 12). Each decision is a choice between “Accept” and “Reject” the lottery. If you Accept the lottery, you have the chance of either winning or losing some money. If you Reject the lottery, you will not earn anything and you will not lose anything—your payoff will be zero.

You will make ten choices and record these by ten check marks, but only one of them will be used in the end to determine your earnings.

In this problem set, the gains and losses associated to each choice is different from before. Also, note that whether there will be gains or losses may be determined by different numbers on the dice. Once you have completed your choices you will move on to the next problem set. Earnings will be determined at the end of the study.

Table 12 Problem set A

Please check whether you Accept or Reject each lottery.

Problem set B

1.1 Instructions

As before, your decision sheet shows ten decisions listed on the left (Table 13). Each decision is a choice between “Accept” and “Reject” the lottery. If you Accept the lottery, you have the chance of either winning or losing some money. If you Reject the lottery you will not earn anything and you will not lose anything—your payoff will be zero.

You will make ten choices and record these by ten check marks, but only one of them will be used in the end to determine your earnings.

In this problem set, the gains and losses associated to each choice is different from before. Also, note that whether there will be gains or losses may be determined by different numbers on the dice. Once you have completed your choices you will move on to the next problem set. Earnings will be determined at the end of the study.

Please check whether you Accept or Reject each lottery.

Table 13 Problem set B

Problem set C

1.1 Instructions

As before, your decision sheet shows ten decisions listed on the left (Table 14). Each decision is a choice between “Accept” and “Reject” the lottery. If you Accept the lottery, you have the chance of either winning or losing some money. If you Reject the lottery, you will not earn anything and you will not lose anything—your payoff will be zero.

You will make ten choices and record these by ten check marks, but only one of them will be used in the end to determine your earnings.

In this problem set, the gains and losses associated to each choice is different from before. Also, note that whether there will be gains or losses may be determined by different numbers on the dice. Once you have completed your choices you will move on to the next problem set. Earnings will be determined at the end of the study.

Please check whether you Accept or Reject each lottery.

Table 14 Problem set C

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Santos-Pinto, L., Bruhin, A., Mata, J. et al. Detecting heterogeneous risk attitudes with mixed gambles. Theory Decis 79, 573–600 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-015-9484-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-015-9484-1

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation