Skip to main content
Log in

Free actions as a natural kind

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Do we have free will? Understanding free will as the ability to act freely, and free actions as exercises of this ability, I maintain that the default answer to this question is “yes.” I maintain that free actions are a natural kind, by relying on the influential idea that kinds are homeostatic property clusters. The resulting position builds on the view that agents are a natural kind and yields an attractive alternative to recent revisionist accounts of free action. My view also overcomes difficulties confronted by previous views according to which free actions might be a natural kind. On my view, free actions exist and we often act freely, as long as we possess various features that are related in the right sorts of ways to each other and to the world. In turn, we acquire and retain the concept as long as most of us possess enough of those features.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I will use capitals for concepts (e.g., FREE ACTION) and single quotation marks for terms (e.g., ‘free action’), where relevant.

  2. The move from considerations about reference to conclusions about existence has been challenged (e.g., Mallon et al. 2009).

  3. I follow Nichols (forthcoming) in understanding concepts as mental representations, while avoiding commitment to the idea that they contain descriptions. Instead, like Nichols, I adopt “the deliberately vague characterization on which the descriptive information is ‘associated’ with the concept” (Nichols forthcoming).

  4. Other presuppositions apart from indeterminism might be in error—for example, the presupposition that free actions require conscious or rational control (Levy 2016; Vargas 2017).

  5. I concede that Vargas might adopt a non-descriptivist natural-kind view (see Sect. 8.1); however, his specific proposal about free actions goes against the spirit of such views, which typically permit preserving the concept even without specifying any revision, as I explain below.

  6. These claims are typically made in the first instance about linguistic terms. I follow both descriptivists (e.g., Jackson 1998, p. 33) and non-descriptivists (e.g., Laurence and Margolis 2003, p. 257) in maintaining that semantic claims about terms also apply to concepts.

  7. Salmon (1982, pp. 161–175) denies that essentialism is entailed by the causal-historical view. Even so, those who adopt causal-historical externalism usually also have essentialist intuitions, and arguments for causal-historical externalism can be framed in non-semantic terms that might be used to motivate essentialism more directly.

  8. The mechanisms underlying homeostasis might also be historical. Thus, a biological species (like orangutans) is partly defined in terms of a cluster of properties that is homeostatic due to common evolutionary descent (Boyd 1999, p. 144, pp. 154–156).

  9. I will return to Millikan’s idea of a stabilizing function in Sect. 7, where I say more about why the HPC view cannot appeal to a criterial or descriptive way of identifying the paradigm cases, or generalizing from them to the kind. Moreover, HPC theorists sometimes add another condition to clauses (a) and (b), such that where the relevant features in (a) are unspecified, the kind is identified partly by the criteria we actually use in identifying kinds for use in explanada, i.e., the factor that makes the kind’s members explanatorily interesting, such as the capacity to fulfill a particular functional role (Reydon 2009, pp. 733–744). This extra condition works as a constraint on identifying the (putative) kind in the first place, i.e., on identifying its paradigm cases. For me, the relevant functional role is, as I note, that the behaviors in question seem to be instances of the most sophisticated goal-directed agency typically exercised by humans, often in the context of assigning moral responsibility.

  10. Likewise, many who rely on the HPC account for other purposes use a similar shorthand, e.g., Kumar defines reference for ‘knowledge’ by appeal to “paradigm cases of knowledge” (2014, p. 447, cf. pp. 442–443, 446).

  11. I thank a referee for encouraging me to clarify this point.

  12. There is some disagreement about whether detecting agency is strictly a matter of visual processing or is instead a matter of cognitive judgment. This dispute need not detain us in the present context.

  13. The examples of Romeo and the iron filings are drawn from James (1890, p. 20).

  14. There is emerging evidence that plant behavior is far more strongly equifinal than we previously thought (Maher 2017). Similar findings have emerged regarding purposive agency in bacteria (Fulda 2017).

  15. Deery and Nahmias (2017) explain our ability to distinguish among differing strengths of equifinality in terms of the strength of invariance between variables representing the output of an agent’s cognitive processes and the event of the agent’s obtaining a goal.

  16. In this way, on the HPC account it might additionally be an empirical and a posteriori theoretical question how we track whatever features underpin free actions (cf. Hutto and Myin 2017).

  17. Recall that “paradigm cases of free action” should be read as outlined in Sect. 3.

  18. In fact, it is a hotly debated issue in the free-will literature whether agents who are covertly manipulated can nevertheless act freely, as long as the manipulation unfolds through these agents’ capacities to reason about what to do, reflectively endorse their actions, and so on (e.g., Pereboom 2014; McKenna 2014; Deery and Nahmias 2017).

  19. If the Martians control only some of our actions in this way, then the following considerations apply only to those actions. I thank a referee for prompting me to note this consequence of the view.

  20. For further difficulties with this procedure, see Laurence and Margolis (2003).

  21. McCormick (forthcoming) argues that there is a better case to be made for reference success than reference failure, even for denotational revisionists.

References

  • Andrews, K. (2012). Do apes read minds? Toward a new folk psychology. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arpaly, N. (2003). Unprincipled virtue: An inquiry into moral agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balaguer, M. (2010). Free will as an open scientific problem. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bassili, J. (1976). Temporal and spatial contingencies in the perception of social events. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 33(6), 680–685.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1988). How to be a moral realist. In G. Sayre-McCord (Ed.), Essays on moral realism (pp. 181–228). Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1999). Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In R. A. Wilson (Ed.), Species: New interdisciplinary essays (pp. 141–185). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I. (2011). Natural kinds and concepts: A pragmatist and methodologically naturalistic account. In J. Knowles & H. Rydenfelt (Eds.), Pragmatism, science and naturalism (pp. 171–196). Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bugnyar, T., Reber, S. A., & Buckner, C. (2016). Ravens attribute visual access to unseen competitors. Nature Communications, 7, 10506.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butterfill, S. A., & Apperly, I. A. (2013). How to construct a minimal theory of mind. Mind and Language, 28, 606–637.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caruso, G. (2012). Free will and consciousness: A determinist account of the illusion of free will. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caruso, G. (2015). Free will eliminativism: Reference, error, and phenomenology. Philosophical Studies, 172(10), 2823–2833.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, R. (2003). Libertarian accounts of free will. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daw, R., & Alter, T. (2001). Free acts and robot cats. Philosophical Studies, 102, 345–357.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deery, O. (2015a). The fall from Eden: Why libertarianism isn’t justified by experience. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 93(2), 319–334.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deery, O. (2015b). Why people believe in indeterminist free will. Philosophical Studies, 172(8), 2033–2054.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deery, O., Davis, T., & Carey, J. (2015). The Free-Will Intuitions Scale and the question of natural compatibilism. Philosophical Psychology, 28(6), 776–801.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deery, O., & Nahmias, E. (2017). Defeating manipulation arguments: Interventionist causation and compatibilist sourcehood. Philosophical Studies, 174(5), 1255–1276.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (1981). Natural kinds and biological taxa. The Philosophical Review, 90(1), 66–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M., & Reydon, T. A. C. (2015). Scientific kinds. Philosophical Studies, 172(4), 969–986.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J., & Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (1969). Alternate possibilities and moral responsibility. The Journal of Philosophy, 66(23), 829–839.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (1971). Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. Journal of Philosophy, 68(1), 5–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fulda, F. C. (2017). Natural agency: The case of bacterial cognition. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 3(1), 69–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heider, F., & Simmel, M. (1944). An experimental study of apparent behavior. American Journal of Psychology, 57(2), 243–259.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heller, M. (1996). The mad scientist meets the robot cats: Compatibilism, kinds, and counterexamples. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 56(2), 333–337.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. (2000). Is responsibility essentially impossible? Philosophical Studies, 99(2), 229–268.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D., & Myin, E. (2017). Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ismael, J. (2013). Causation, free will, and naturalism. In H. Kincaid, J. Ladyman, & D. Ross (Eds.), Scientific metaphysics (pp. 208–235). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1998). From metaphysics to ethics: A defence of conceptual analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (2001a). Précis of from metaphysics to ethics. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62(3), 617–624.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (2001b). Responses. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62(3), 653–664.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kane, R. (1996). The significance of free will. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalidi, M. A. (2018). Natural kinds as nodes in causal networks. Synthese, 195(4), 1379–1396.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kumar, V. (2014). ‘Knowledge’ as a natural kind term. Synthese, 191, 439–457.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kumar, V. (2015). Moral judgment as a natural kind. Philosophical Studies, 172(11), 2887–2910.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laurence, S., & Margolis, E. (2003). Concepts and conceptual analysis. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67(2), 253–282.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, N. (2011). Hard luck: How luck undermines free will and moral responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, N. (2016). Implicit bias and moral responsibility: Probing the data. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 94(1), 3–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1972). Psychophysical and theoretical identifications. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 50(3), 249–258.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lombrozo, T. (2010). Causal-explanatory pluralism: How intentions, functions, and mechanisms influence causal ascriptions. Cognitive Psychology, 61(4), 303–332.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maher, C. (2017). Plant minds: A philosophical defense. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mallon, R., Machery, E., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2009). Against arguments from reference. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 79(2), 332–356.

    Google Scholar 

  • May, J. (2014). On the very concept of free will. Synthese, 191(12), 2849–2866.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCormick, K. A. (2016). Revisionism. In K. Timpe, M. Griffith, & N. Levy (Eds.), Routledge companion to free will (pp. 109–120). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCormick, K. A. (forthcoming). Meeting the eliminativist burden. Social Philosophy & Policy, 36(1).

  • McGeer, V. (2007). The regulative dimension of folk psychology. In D. Hutto & M. Ratcliffe (Eds.), Folk psychology reassessed (pp. 137–156). Dordrecht: Kluwer/Springer Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2008). A hard-line reply to Pereboom’s four-case manipulation argument. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 77(1), 142–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2012). Moral responsibility, manipulation arguments, and history: Assessing the resilience of nonhistorical compatibilism. Journal of Ethics, 16, 145–174.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2014). Resisting the manipulation argument: A hard-liner takes it on the chin. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 89(2), 467–484.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (1995). Autonomous agents: From self-control to autonomy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (2006). Free will and luck. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (2013). Manipulation, moral responsibility, and bullet biting. Journal of Ethics, 17(3), 167–184.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (2010). On knowing the meaning; with a coda on Swampman. Mind, 119(473), 43–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nahmias, E. (2018). Free will as a psychological accomplishment. In D. Schmidtz & C. E. Pavel (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of freedom (pp. 492–507). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S. (2015). Free will and error. In S. Nichols (Ed.), Bound: Essays on free will and responsibility (pp. 54–74). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S. (Forthcoming). Free will and reference. In J. Campbell (Ed.), A companion to free will. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Blackwell.

  • Pereboom, D. (2014). Free will, agency, and meaning in life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pober, J. M. (2013). Addiction is not a natural kind. Frontiers in Psychiatry, 4, 123.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of “Meaning”. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 7, 131–193.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reydon, T. A. C. (2009). How to fix kind membership: A problem for HPC theory and a solution. Philosophy of Science, 76(5), 724–736.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rutherford, M. D., & Kuhlmeier, V. A. (Eds.). (2013). Social perception: Detection and interpretation of animacy, agency, and intention. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, N. (1982). Reference and Essence. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schechtman, M. (2014). Staying alive: Personal identity, practical concerns, and the unity of a life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seligman, M., Railton, P., Baumeister, R., & Sripada, C. (2013). Navigating into the future or driven by the past: Prospection as an organizing principle of mind. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8(2), 119–141.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, D. (2015). Responsibility from the margins. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sims, A. (2018). The essence of agency is discovered, not defined: A minimal mindreading argument. Philosophical Studies. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1108-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, I. (2002). Freedom and revision. Southwest Philosophy Review, 18(2), 25–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. (2008). Control, responsibility, and moral assessment. Philosophical Studies, 138(3), 367–392.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sommers, T. (2012). Relative justice: Cultural diversity, free will, and moral responsibility. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spaulding, S. (2018). How we understand others: Philosophy and social cognition. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2001). The evolution of agency and other essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2003). Thought in a hostile world: The evolution of human cognition. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K., & Griffiths, P. (1999). Sex and death. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (1986). Freedom and belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. (1983). An essay on free will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vargas, M. (2006). On the importance of history for responsible agency. Philosophical Studies, 127, 351–382.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vargas, M. (2011). Revisionist accounts of free will: Origins, varieties, and challenges. In R. Kane (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of free will (2nd ed., pp. 457–484). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vargas, M. (2013). Building better beings: A theory of moral responsibility. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vargas, M. (2017). Implicit bias, responsibility, and moral ecology. In D. Shoemaker (Ed.), Oxford studies in agency and responsibility (Vol. 4, pp. 219–247). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vargas, M. (forthcoming). Revisionism. In J. Campbell (Ed.), A companion to free will. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Blackwell.

  • Vihvelin, K. (2004). Free will demystified: A dispositional account. Philosophical Topics, 32(1–2), 427–450.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A., Barker, M. J., & Brigandt, I. (2007). When traditional essentialism fails: Biological natural kinds. Philosophical Topics, 35, 189–215.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, S. (1987). Sanity and the metaphysics of responsibility. In F. Schoeman (Ed.), Responsibility, character, and the emotions: New essays in moral psychology (pp. 46–62). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zawidzki, T. W. (2013). Mindshaping: A new framework for understanding human social cognition. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Versions of this paper were presented at the University of Arizona (January 2016), Florida State University (January 2017), Monash University (September 2017), the Central Division Meeting of the American Philosophical Association (February 2018), the University of Melbourne (May 2018), and the 3rd International Conference on Natural Cognition at the University of Macau (November 2018). Thanks to audiences at those venues for helpful comments. I also thank Terry Horgan, Shaun Nichols, Michael McKenna, Eddy Nahmias, Alfred Mele, Tim Bayne, Gregg Caruso and several anonymous referees for their valuable suggestions. Finally, I thank the students in my seminar on reference and free will at Monash University (2018) for useful discussion.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Oisín Deery.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Deery, O. Free actions as a natural kind. Synthese 198, 823–843 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-02068-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-02068-7

Keywords

Navigation