Skip to main content
Log in

How to power encultured minds

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Cultural psychologists often describe the relationship between mind and culture as ‘dynamic.’ In light of this, we provide two desiderata that a theory about encultured minds ought to meet: the theory ought to reflect how cultural psychologists describe their own findings and it ought to be thoroughly naturalistic. We show that a realist theory of causal powers—which holds that powers are causally-efficacious and empirically-discoverable—fits the bill. After an introduction to the major concepts in cultural psychology and describing causal power realism, we use a case study—the effects of pathogen prevalence on culture and cognition—to show the explanatory capacities of the powers framework.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Kitayama (2002, p. 90) makes the same point: “What culture is to humans is what water is to fish.”

  2. It’s worth observing that American culture alone makes a separate room for a newborn baby (Burton and Whiting 1961). It’s no coincidence that American culture is also hyper-individualistic (Henrich et al. 2010).

  3. For discussion of Sperber’s influence on the development of cognitive anthropology (and cognitive science more broadly) see Boden (2004). Sperber’s position is developed over many papers and books. But if interested parties were looking for a single source to learn about his views, they could do a lot worse than Sperber (1996). There, he cogently lays out a program for a naturalistic investigation of culture that depends on transmission of representations among individuals in a culture. Other papers flesh out details, like his defense of massive modularity (2001, 2005) and the role of cultural attractors in cultural evolution (Claidière et al. 2014; Claidière and Sperber 2007).

  4. The major competitors are Dawkins’ memetics and Richerson and Boyd’s culture-gene coevolution, though there are plenty of other accounts describing the dissemination of cultural attitudes, including those developed within the relatively recent area of network science (cf. Albert Barabási’s open-source textbook at <http://networksciencebook.com/>) and recently applications of computer simulations to cultural psychology (cf. Kashima 2014). It’s worth noting that Sperber, Dawkins, and Richerson and Boyd have much in common. All attempt to identify the mechanisms that make cultural evolution and transmission possible and all work within naturalistic frameworks. Where they differ is in an account of the mechanisms involved. The man himself has an informative and entertaining interview on this in Edge: <https://www.edge.org/conversation/dan_sperber-an-epidemiology-of-representations>.

  5. For Sperber, cultures are causally efficacious in the sense that cultural information enters into ‘cultural causal cognitive chains’ (Sperber 2006).

  6. Thanks to anonymous reviewers for pressing us to clarify this.

  7. Cf. Buss et al. (1992) and Harris (2003) for criticism.

  8. Even if we think it is.

  9. See note 8.

  10. These cultural-psychological categories have made appearances elsewhere in recent philosophy. Machery et al. (2004) draw on cultural differences to illustrate that causal-historical theories of reference aren’t culturally universal. Sarkissian et al. (2010) show that people tend to believe in free will across the individualist-collectivist divide. Weinberg et al. (2001) show that epistemological intuitions (specifically, Gettier-related intuitions) vary across culture and socio-economic class.

  11. What is information? Cultural psychologists are agnostic on its nature (see Adriaans 2013 for an overview). It seems like they have the sort of thing in mind that Sperber (2006) does when he talks about ‘content’: “…a representation is whatever has meaning or content.”

  12. It’s useful to describe these as ‘categories’ but they’re more like ends on a continuum. Cultures are more or less collectivist or individualist.

  13. One unfortunate vestige of early research on cultural psychology is that the individualism-collectivism split tends to track the geographical West/East split. This is unfortunate because cultural psychologists define culture in terms of information and not in terms of geography. There is, of course, an obvious relationship between the two: if culture is transmitted from agent to agent, then close physical proximity facilitates that. The examples we use in this paper tend to follow the East–West/collectivist–individualist mapping since we rely on well-accepted findings to make our case. Nonetheless, we do a disservice to the notion of ‘culture’ in thinking of it as geographically-bound.

  14. The literature on cultural and cognitive patterns associated with individualist and collectivist cultures is vast. Further, there are many differences among individualist and collectivist cultures. Individualism looks different when comparing American and British culture; and collectivism manifests itself differently when comparing Japanese and Latin American cultures. For an overview, see Triandis (1995), Kim et al. (1996) and Oyserman et al. (2002).

  15. Rowlands (2003, 2010) offers something of a Sartrean view in which consciousness is mirror-like. We don’t mean anything like that here. Cultural psychologists will sometimes talk about “representing” cultural information internally, but that doesn’t square with their rejection of the computational-representational framework. A charitable interpretation would be that minds represent information but without containing representations. But to avoid stacking the deck in favor of or against our proposed explanatory framework, we’ll stick with the mirror-metaphor since it gets the empirical insights without the ontological baggage.

  16. The coding system used was developed, in part, by Ekman and Friesen (1978): the Facial Action Coding System. The system involves relativizing the facial features to the dimensions of the face. So an excited smile (for example) will have greater width and depth relative to that face than a calm smile. The resulting ratios of smile-size to face-size provide a basis of comparison for faces of different sizes and shapes.

  17. Even though the information is present, one might wonder, do the children pick up on it? The answer is “yes.” Taiwanese children preferred images of children with calm smiles and European-American children preferred images with big smiles. Also, both sets of children were presented with stories in which the characters engaged in calm activities (e.g. floating on an inner tube) or rambunctious activities (e.g. splashing in the water). Taiwanese children preferred calm-activity stories and European-American children preferred the rambunctious-activity stories.

  18. Though they’d be ok with late-1980s-and-beyond-Putnam.

  19. See, for example, Dewey (1896). Another important connection to make in this regard is between ecological psychology and cultural psychology. Ecological psychologists posit affordances (i.e. opportunities for action in an organism’s environment) as a key theoretical entity. Cultural psychologists likewise talk about socio-cultural affordances: e.g. Costall (1995), Reitveld and Kiverstein (2014). Ecological psychologists also trace their intellectual lineage to the American naturalists, cf. Heft 2001. So cultural psychologists borrow conceptual resources from ecological psychologists, who often cite American naturalists as their intellectual parents.

  20. Oyserman’s position is an important exception. She argues that culturally-influenced cognition is a kind of situated cognition. She discusses ‘cultural mindsets’ in terms of representations and schema (e.g. Oyserman 2011, p. 165). Even so, Oyserman is keen to note the back-and-forth causal influence of mind and culture.

  21. The computationalist response here is (to paraphrase Haugeland 1985): take care of the syntax and the semantics will take care of themselves. As long as the contents of the incoming information are in some way reflected in the syntax of the tokened representations, then the computationalist avoids the cultural psychologist’s worry.

  22. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for bringing this to our attention.

  23. We want to stress that Sperber (2006) believes this too. But the mechanisms he invokes for providing a naturalistic explanation are taken from computational strains in cognitive science, which as we saw puts Sperber in tension with most cultural psychologists.

  24. Sperber uses findings like these to bolster his case for massive modularity and against a ‘blank slate’ view of mind that he finds in Dawkins. See Sperber (2011).

  25. Norenzayan and Heine (2005) sketches a framework for this research.

  26. See footnote 27.

  27. Based on the way we have defined causal power realism, the position is widespread. In fact, the positions defended in all of the following would count as causal power realism: Prior et al. (1982), Armstrong (1983, 1996a, b, c, 1997, 2004, 2005, 2010), Lewis (1986), Martin (1996, 1997, 2007), Martin and Heil (1998, 1999), Ellis (2001, 2002), Molnar (2003), Heil (2003, Heil 2005), Mumford (2004), Psillos (2006), Bird (2007), Marmodoro (2009), Jacobs (2011) and Jaworski (2016). Those familiar with this literature will recognize that the positions defended in this list differ from each other significantly. Still, all are united in rejecting the idea that powers are reducible to counterfactuals.

  28. Martin (2007, Chapter 3) calls them “reciprocal disposition partners.”

  29. Mumford and Anjum (2010) model the causal stew by means of vectors. For a causal power C, there are some powers that promote C’s manifestation and others that inhibit. When there are sufficiently many promoters—and sufficiently few inhibitors—for C, then it manifests its effects.

  30. Pearson’s r = − 0.69, p < 0.001.

  31. Fincher, et al also discuss the effect of per capita GDP as a force shaping degree of individualism and, by extension, cognition. We address this in greater detail below.

  32. Work on implicit racial biases has amply illustrated how social structures inform discriminatory judgments (e.g. Gendler 2011; Anderson 2010). But as far as we know, philosophers have yet to consider how the prevalence of disease can do the same.

  33. The careful reader will notice that Oran is the name in the town in Camus’ The Plague. A fitting name for someone in an area with high prevalence of pathogens.

  34. Thanks to two anonymous reviewers for bringing this objection to our attention.

  35. At this point, we pass the ball to social learning theorists for identifying the mechanisms involved with learning from others, cf. Hoppitt and Laland (2013).

  36. This is just what researchers are finding: for example, in both the US and Japan, there has been a notable decrease in the extent to which individuals value social participation and children’s obedience (Hamamura 2012). Also, the use of first-personal pronouns is on the rise globally (Yu et al. 2016), something cultural psychologists use as a marker of individualism.

  37. A question: are cultural powers something over and above the powers of that culture’s members? Put differently: are cultural powers emergent, or are they reducible to some set of lower-level powers?

    That’s an important question, but ultimately an empirical one. We’ve seen that according to causal power realism, powers are empirically-discoverable. So when we are trying to determine which powers there are and which individuals have them, we should look to empirical sources. So just as empirical sources will determine whether (say) biological powers are reducible to chemical powers, so too empirical sources will determine whether cultural powers are reducible to some lower-level set of powers. For our purposes here, it is therefore simply important for us to note that cultures have powers. Whether these powers are emergent is a question that lies beyond our purposes, and indeed, beyond purely philosophical inquiry.

  38. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for bringing this to our attention.

  39. However, per capita GDP doesn’t account for the predictive power of pathogen prevalence on degree of individualism.

  40. Going even further—these last two manifestations (reinforced xenophobic attitudes and transmission of attitudes to children), what do they empower? Nothing other than the maintenance and transmission of cultural attitudes.

  41. Many thanks to Sam Kampa, Anna Marie Medina, Vinai Norasakkunkit, and Peter Seipel for comments on an earlier draft. Thanks also to anonymous reviewers for Synthese for their helpful feedback.

References

  • Adriaans, P. Information. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2013 Edition), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/information/.

  • Al-Olayan, F. S., & Karande, K. (2000). A content analysis of magazine advertisements from the United States and the Arab World. Journal of Advertising,29(3), 69–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • An, D., & Kim, S. (2007). Relating Hofstede’s masculinity dimension to gender role portrayals in advertising. International Marketing Review,24(2), 181–207.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, E. (2010). The imperative of integration. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. (1983). What is a law of nature?. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. (1996a). Dispositions as categorical states. In T. Crane (Ed.), Dispositions: A debate (pp. 15–18). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. (1996b). Place’s and Armstrong’s views compared and contrasted. In T. Crane (Ed.), Dispositions: A debate (pp. 33–48). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. (1996c). Reply to Martin. In T. Crane (Ed.), Dispositions: A debate (pp. 88–104). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. (1997). A world of states of affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. (2004). Truth and truthmakers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. (2005). Four disputes about properties. Synthese,144, 309–320.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. (2010). Sketch for a systematic metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atran, S., & Norenzayan, A. (2004). Religion’s evolutionary landscape: Counterintuition, commitment, compassion, communion. Behavioral and Brain Sciences,27(6), 716–730.

    Google Scholar 

  • Belk, R. W., & Bryce, W. J. (1986). Materialism and individual determinism in US and Japanese print and television advertising. In NA-Advances in Consumer Research (Vol. 13).

  • Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s metaphysics: Laws and properties. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boden, M. (2004). Mind as machine: A history of cognitive science (Vol. 1, 2). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burton, R. V., & Whiting, J. W. (1961). The absent father and cross-sex identity. Merrill-Palmer Quarterly of Behavior and Development,7, 85–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buss, D., Larsen, R., Westen, D., & Semmelroth, J. (1992). Sex differences in jealousy: Evolution, physiology, and psychology. Psychological Science,3, 251–255.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callahan, E. (2005). Cultural similarities and differences in the design of university web sites. Journal of Computer-Mediated Communication,11(1), 239–273.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, T. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. (2009). Human freedom and the self. In D. Pereboom (Ed.), Free will (pp. 172–184). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chua, H. F., Boland, J. E., & Nisbett, R. E. (2005). Cultural variation in eye movements during scene perception. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences,102(35), 12629–12633.

    Google Scholar 

  • Claidière, N., Scott-Phillips, T. C., Sperber, D. (2014). How Darwinian is cultural evolution? Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B. http://rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org/content/royptb/369/1642/20130368.full.pdf.

  • Claidière, N., & Sperber, D. (2007). The role of attraction in cultural evolution. Journal of Cognition and Culture,7, 89–111.

    Google Scholar 

  • Costall, A. (1995). Socializing affordances. Theory and Psychology,5, 467–481.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1896). The reflex arc concept in psychology. Psychological Review,3, 357–370.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. I. (1988). Explaining behavior. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ekman, P., & Friesen, W. V. (1978). Manual for the facial action coding system. n.p.: Consulting Psychologists Pres.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2001). Scientific essentialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2002). The philosophy of nature: A guide to the new essentialism. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fara, M. (2005). Dispositions and habituals. Noûs,39, 43–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fincher, C. L., Thornhill, R., Murray, D. R., & Schaller, M. (2008). Pathogen prevalence predicts human cross-cultural variability in individualism/collectivism. Proceedings of the Royal Society,275, 1279–1285.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, T. S. (2011). On the epistemic costs of implicit bias. Philosophical Studies,156(1), 33–63. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-011-9801-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1954). Fact, fiction, and forecast. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamamura, T. (2012). Are cultures becoming individualistic? A cross-temporal comparison of individualism–collectivism in the United States and Japan. Personality and Social Psychology Review,16(1), 3–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, C. (2003). A review of sex differences in sexual jealousy, including self-report data, psychophysiological responses, interpersonal violence, and morbid jealousy. Personality and Social Psychology Review,7, 102–128.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, J. (1985). Artificial intelligence: The very idea. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heil, J. (2003). From an ontological point of view. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heil, J. (2005). Dispositions. Synthese,144(3), 343–356.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heine, S. (2008). Cultural psychology. New York: W. W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henrich, J. (2008). A cultural species. In M. Brown (Ed.), Explaining culture scientifically (pp. 184–210). Seattle, WA: University of Washington Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henrich, J., Heine, S. J., & Norenzayan, A. (2010). The weirdest people in the world? Behavioral and Brain Sciences,33, 61–83.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofstede, G. (2001). Comparing values, behaviors, institutions, and organizations across nations (2nd ed.). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoppitt, W., & Laland, K. N. (2013). Social learning: An introduction to mechanisms, methods, and models. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, J. D. (2011). Powerful qualities, not pure powers. Monist,94(1), 81–102.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaworski, W. (2016). Structure and the metaphysics of mind: How hylomorphism solves the mind-body problem. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ji, M. F., & McNeal, J. U. (2001). How Chinese children’s commercials differ from those of the United States: A content analysis. Journal of Advertising,30(3), 79–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kashima, Y. (2014). How can you capture cultural dynamics? Frontiers in Psychology, 5. Available https://www.frontiersin.org/article/10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00995.

  • Keesing, R. M. (1974). Theories of culture. Annual Review of Anthropology,3(1), 73–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, H., & Markus, H. R. (1999). Deviance or uniqueness, harmony or conformity? A cultural analysis. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,77(4), 785–800.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, M.-S., Hunter, J. E., Miyahara, A., Ann-Marie, H., Bresnahan, M., & Hei-Jin, Y. (1996). Individual-vs. culture-level dimensions of individualism and collectivism: Effects on preferred conversational styles. Communication Monographs,63(1), 29–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitayama, S. (2002). Basic psychological processes-toward—A system view of culture: Comment on Oyserman et al. Psychological Bulletin,128, 110–117.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitayama, S., Hyekyung Park, A., Sevincer, T., Karasawa, M., & Uskul, A. K. (2009). A cultural task analysis of implicit independence: Comparing North America, Western Europe, and East Asia. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,97(2), 236–255.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kühnen, U., Hannover, B., & Schubert, B. (2001). The semantic-procedural interface model of the self: The role of self-knowledge for context-dependent versus context-independent modes of thinking. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,80(3), 397.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lande, D., & Downey, G. (2012). The encultured brain: Development, case studies, and methods. In T. Encultured (Ed.), Brain: An introduction to neuroanthropology (pp. 3–22). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1966). An argument for the identity theory. The Journal of Philosophy,63(1), 17–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1997). Finkish dispositions. The Philosophical Quarterly,47, 143–158.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E., Mallon, R., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2004). Semantics, cross-cultural style. Cognition,92(3), 1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malzkorn, W. (2000). Realism, functionalism and the conditional analysis of dispositions. The Philosophical Quarterly,50, 452–469.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manley, D., & Wasserman, R. (2008). On linking dispositions and conditionals. Mind,117, 59–84.

    Google Scholar 

  • Markus, H. R., & Kitayama, S. (2010). Cultures and selves: A cycle of mutual constitution. Perspectives on Psychological Science,5(4), 420–430.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmodoro, A. (2009). Do powers need powers to make them powerful? From pandispositionalism to Aristotle. American Philosophical Quarterly,26(4), 347–352.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C. B. (1994). Dispositions and conditionals. The Philosophical Quarterly, 44(174), 1–8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C. B. (1996). Properties and dispositions. In T. Crane (Ed.), Dispositions: A debate. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C. B. (1997). On the need for properties: The road to pythagoreanism and back. Synthese,112(2), 193–231.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C. B. (2007). The mind in nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C. B., & Heil, J. (1998). Rules and powers. Philosophical Perspectives,12(S12), 283–312.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C. B., & Heil, J. (1999). The ontological turn. Midwest Studies in Philosophy,23(1), 34–60.

    Google Scholar 

  • Masuda, T., Ellsworth, P. C., Mesquita, B., Leu, J., Tanida, S., & Van de Veerdonk, E. (2008). Placing the face in context: Cultural differences in the perception of facial emotion. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,94(3), 365–381.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellor, D. H. (2000). The semantics and ontology of dispositions. Mind,109, 757–780.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miyamoto, Y., Nisbett, R. E., & Masuda, T. (2006). Culture and the physical environment: Holistic versus analytic perceptual affordances. Psychological Science,17(2), 113–119.

    Google Scholar 

  • Molnar, G. (2003). Powers: A study in metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S. (2004). Laws in nature. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S., & Anjum, R. L. (2010). A powerful theory of causation. In A. Marmodoro (Ed.), The metaphysics of powers: Their grounding and their manifestations (pp. 143–159). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norenzayan, A., & Heine, S. J. (2005). Psychological universals: What are they and how can we know? Psychological Bulletin,131(5), 763.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyserman, D. (2011). Culture as situated cognition: Cultural mindsets, cultural fluency, and meaning making. European Review of Social Psychology,22(1), 164–214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyserman, D., Coon, H. M., & Kemmelmeier, M. (2002). Rethinking individualism and collectivism: Evaluation of theoretical assumptions and meta-analyses. Psychological Bulletin,128, 3–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peng, K., & Nisbett, R. E. (1999). Culture, dialectics, and reasoning about contradiction. American Psychologist,54(9), 741.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, E. (1985). Dispositions. Aberdeen: Aberdeen University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, E., Pargetter, R., & Jackson, F. (1982). Three theses about dispositions. American Philosophical Quarterly,19, 251–257.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2006). What do powers do when they are not manifested? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research,72, 137–155.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The mental life of some machines. In Mind, language, and reality: Philosophical papers (Vol. 2). New York: Cambridge University Press.

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rietveld, E., & Kiverstein, J. (2014). A rich landscape of affordances. Ecological Psychology,26(4), 325–352.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosman, A., & Rubel, P. (1992). The tapestry of culture: An introduction to cultural anthropology (4th ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2003). Externalism: Putting mind and world back together again. Chesham: Acumen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2010). The new science of the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Santos, H. C., Varnum, M. E. W., & Grossmann, I. (2017). Global increases in individualism. Psychological Science. https://doi.org/10.1177/0956797617700622.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sarkissian, H., Chatterjee, A., de Brigard, F., Knobe, J., Nichols, S., & Sirker, S. (2010). Is belief in free will a cultural universal? Mind and Language,25(3), 346–358.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaller, M., & Park, J. H. (2011). The behavioral immune system (and why it matters). Current Directions in Psychological Science,20(2), 99–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shweder, R. A. (1991). Thinking through cultures: Expeditions in cultural psychology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shweder, R. A., & Bourne, E. J. (1982). Does the concept of the person vary cross-culturally? In J. M. Anthony & W. Geoffrey (Eds.), Cultural conceptions of mental health and therapy (pp. 97–137). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D. (1996). Explaining culture: A naturalistic approach. New York: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D. (2001) Defense of massive modularity. Language, brain and cognitive development: Essays in honor of Jacques Mehler (pp. 47–57). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D. (2005). Modularity and relevance: How can a massively modular mind be flexible and context-sensitive? In P. Carruthers, S. Laurence, & S. Stich (Eds.), The innate mind: Structure and content (pp. 53–68). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D. (2006). Why a deep understanding of cultural evolution is incompatible with shallow psychology. In N. Enfield & S. Levinson (Eds.), Roots of human sociality (pp. 431–449). New York: Berg.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D. (2011). In defense of massive modularity. In E. Dupoux (Ed.), Language, brain and cognitive development: Essays in honor of Jacques Mehler (pp. 47–57). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2006). The evolution and evolvability of culture. Mind and Language,21(2), 137–165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (1999). The cultural origins of human cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Triandis, H. C. (1995). Individualism and collectivism. Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsai, J. L., Louie, J. Y., Chen, E. E., & Uchida, Y. (2007a). Learning what feelings to desire: Socialization of ideal affect through children’s storybooks. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin,33(1), 17–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsai, J. L., Miao, F. F., & Seppala, E. (2007b). Good feelings in christianity and buddhism: Religious differences in ideal affect. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin,33(3), 409–421.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, S. P. (2001). Culture and the human brain. Anthropology and Humanism,26(2), 167–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Twenge, J. M., Abebe, E. M., & Campbell, W. K. (2010). Fitting in or standing out: Trends in American parents’ choices for children’s names, 1880–2007. Social Psychological and Personality Science,1(1), 19–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Twenge, J. M., Keith Campbell, W., & Gentile, B. (2012). Increases in individualistic words and phrases in American books, 1960–2008. PLoS ONE,7(7), e40181.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2001). Normativity and epistemic intuitions. Philosophical Topics,29(1–2), 429–460.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whiting, R. (2004). The meaning of Ichiro: The new wave from Japan and the transformation of our national pastime. New York: Grand Central Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Witkin, H. A., & Berry, J. W. (1975). Psychological differentiation in cross-cultural perspective. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology,6(1), 4–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yu, F., Theodore, P., Kaiping, P., Shi T., Chuan, S. C., Xiaojun, Q., Pei, S., Tingting, H., & Fangyuan, C. (2016). Cultural value shifting in pronoun use. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 47(2), 310–316.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Charles Lassiter.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Vukov, J., Lassiter, C. How to power encultured minds. Synthese 197, 3507–3534 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01899-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01899-8

Keywords

Navigation