Skip to main content
Log in

Distributed selves: personal identity and extended memory systems

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper explores the implications of extended and distributed cognition theory for our notions of personal identity. On an extended and distributed approach to cognition, external information is under certain conditions constitutive of memory. On a narrative approach to personal identity, autobiographical memory is constitutive of our diachronic self. In this paper, I bring these two approaches together and argue that external information can be constitutive of one’s autobiographical memory and thus also of one’s diachronic self. To develop this claim, I draw on recent empirical work in human-computer interaction, looking at lifelogging technologies in both healthcare and everyday contexts. I argue that personal identity can neither be reduced to psychological structures instantiated by the brain nor by biological structures instantiated by the organism, but should be seen as an environmentally-distributed and relational construct. In other words, the complex web of cognitive relations we develop and maintain with other people and technological artifacts partly determines our self. This view has conceptual, methodological, and normative implications: we should broaden our concepts of the self as to include social and artifactual structures, focus on external memory systems in the (empirical) study of personal identity, and not interfere with people’s distributed minds and selves.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The terms “self”, “personhood”, and “personal identity” are used interchangeably throughout this essay.

  2. Sometimes the phrase “4e cognition” is used, which is an acronym for embodied, embedded, extended, and enactive cognition.

  3. I am using the phrases “extended cognition” and “distributed cognition” more or less interchangeably in this paper, as both approaches claim that informational artifacts can be constitutive of a wider cognitive system, but there are differences between the two approaches. See Hutchins (2014) for an analysis of some of these differences in terms of examples, method, and explanatory scope.

  4. A reviewer pointed out that Locke’s original memory criterion focused on consciousness too. In fact, memory was Locke’s way of explaining the notion of temporally extended consciousness; memory makes the idea of a temporally extended consciousness fall within the experience-centered empiricist outlook. Many neo-Lockeans, including Schechtman, include non-occurrent states in their notion of psychological continuity.

  5. There are, of course, other capacities that are important for our practical identity such as our capacity for consciousness and emotions.

  6. If, for example, someone has a stroke or other kind of brain injury and loses part of one’s memory or language capacity, that would surely be a change to the person.

  7. A reviewer pointed out that emphasizing control over the contents of one’s lifelog can be interpreted as claiming that the locus of personhood is still brain-based. My view is that agency and the locus of personhood can be distributed across humans and cognitive artifacts such as SenseCam-generated lifelogs. I think agency is distributed because the SenseCam automatically takes pictures whose content we typically cannot change, but the human agent often has to edit the lifelog. So both components in the larger systems have some form of agency and the equilibrium may shift between the artifactual and biological components, depending on each specific case. Furthermore, in the typical extended mind cases (Clark and Chalmers 1998), agency is largely located in the biological organism. However, in larger distributed cognitive systems, for example Hutchins’ (1995) example of ship navigation, humans may not necessarily be the center and controller of distributed systems. For more discussion on this topic see Hutchins (2014).

  8. This is related to the problem of q-memory as outlined in Parfit (1984).

  9. These are important epistemological issues to further explore. They also tie in with the extended knowledge debate (e.g., Michaelian 2014), which has to do in part with the possibility of assigning credit to agents who rely on external cognitive resources for their epistemic accomplishments, including those are false.

References

  • Addis, D. R., & Tippett, L. J. (2004). Memory of myself: Autobiographical memory and identity in Alzheimer’s disease. Memory, 12(1), 56–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, J. (2008). Neuro-prosthetics, the extended mind, and respect for persons with disability. In M. Düwell, C. Rehmann-Sutter, & D. Mieth (Eds.), The contingent nature of life: Bioethics and limits of human existence (pp. 259–274). Heidelberg: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Baker, L. R. (2009). Persons and the extended mind thesis. Zygon, 44(3), 642–658.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beach, K. (1988). The role of external mnemonic symbols in acquiring an occupation. In M. M. Gruneberg, P. E. Morris, & R. N. Sykes (Eds.), Practical aspects of memory (pp. 342–346). Chichester: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, G. M., & Gemmell, J. (2009). Total recall: How the e-memory revolution will change everything. New York: Dutton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berry, E., et al. (2007). he use of a wearable camera, SenseCam, as a pictorial diary to improve autobiographical memory in a patient with limbic encephalitis: A preliminary report. Neuropsychological Rehabilitation, 17(4—-5), 582–601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buller, T. (2013). Neurotechnology, invasiveness and the extended mind. Neuroethics, 6(3), 593–605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bush, V. (1945). As we may think. The Atlantic, 176(1), 101–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, and world together again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2005). Intrinsic content, active memory and the extended mind. Analysis, 65(285), 1–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2007). Re-inventing ourselves: The plasticity of embodiment, sensing, and mind. Journal of Philosophy and Medicine, 32(3), 263–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clowes, R. W. (2012). Hybrid memory, cognitive technology and self. In Y.J. Erden & J.M. Bishop (Eds.),Proceedings of AISB/IACAP world Congress (pp. 4–13).

  • Crete-Nishihata, M., et al. (2012). Reconstructing the past: Personal memory technologies are not just personal and not just for memory. Human-Computer Interaction, 27(1–2), 92–123.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1996). Kinds of minds: Towards an understanding of consciousness. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doherty, A. R., et al. (2012). Experiences of aiding autobiographical memory using the SenseCam. Human-Computer Interaction, 27(1–2), 151–174.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donald, M. (1991). Origins of the modern mind: Three stages in the evolution of our cognitive system. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Floridi, L. (2011). The informational nature of personal identity. Minds and Machines, 21, 549–566.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harris, C. .B, Keil, P. G., Sutton, J. & Barnier, A. J. (2010). Collaborative remembering: When can remembering with others be beneficial? In W. Christensen, E. Schier & J. Sutton (Eds.), Proceedings of the 9th conference of the Australasian Society for Cognitive Science (pp. 131–134).

  • Henkel, L. A. (2014). Point-and-shoot memories: The influence of taking photos on memory for a museum tour. Psychological Science, 25(2), 396–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heersmink, R. (2015). Extended mind and cognitive enhancement: Moral aspects of cognitive artifacts. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. doi:10.1007/s11097-015-9448-5.

  • Hodges, S., Berry, E., & Wood, K. (2011). SenseCam: A wearable camera that stimulates and rehabilitates autobiographical memory. Memory, 19(7), 685–696.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hollan, J., Hutchins, E., & Kirsh, D. (2000). Distributed cognition: Toward a new foundation for human-computer interaction research. Transactions on Computer-Human Interaction, 7(2), 174–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins, E. (2014). The cultural ecosystem of human cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 27(1), 34–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacquemard, T., Novitzky, P., O’Brolchain, F., Smeaton, A. F., & Gordijn, B. (2014). Challenges and opportunities of lifelog technologies: A literature review and critical analysis. Science and Engineering Ethics, 20(2), 379–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirsh, D. (1995). The intelligent use of space. Artificial Intelligence, 73(1–2), 1–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, N. (2007a). Rethinking neuroethics in the light of the extended mind thesis. American Journal of Bioethics, 7(9), 3–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, N. (2007b). Neuroethics: Challenges for the \(21{st}\) century. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Loveday, C., & Conway, M. (2011). Using SenseCam with an amnesic patient: Accessing inaccessible everyday memories. Memory, 19(7), 697–704.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, C. (2008). Introduction: Practical identity and narrative agency. In C. Mackenzie & K. Atkins (Eds.), Practical identity and narrative agency (pp. 1–28). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, C., & Walker, M. (2015). Neurotechnologies, personal identity, and the ethics of authenticity. In J. Clausen & N. Levy (Eds.), Handbook of neuroethics (pp. 373–392). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayer-Schonberger, V. (2011). Delete: The virtue of forgetting in the digital age. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2007). Cognitive integration: Mind and cognition unbound. London: Palgrave McMillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, K. (2014). JFGI: From distributed cognition to distributed reliabilism. Philosophical Issues, 24(1), 314–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, K., & Sutton, J. (2013). Distributed cognition and memory research: History and current directions. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 4(1), 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norman, D. (1993). Things that make us smart: Defending human attributes in the age of the machine. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Hara, K., Tufflied, M. M., & Shadbolt, N. (2008). Lifelogging: Privacy and empowerment with memories for life. Identity in the Information Society, 1(1), 155–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olsen, E. T. (2011). The extended self. Minds and Machines, 21(4), 481–495.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (1999). The body in mind: Understanding cognitive processes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schechtman, M. (1994). The truth about memory. Philosophical Psychology, 7(1), 3–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schechtman, M. (1996). The constitution of selves. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schechtman, M. (2008). Diversity in unity: Practical unity and personal boundaries. Synthese, 162(3), 405–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schechtman, M. (2012). The story of my (second) life: Virtual worlds and narrative identity. Philosophy and Technology, 25(3), 329–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smart, P., Heersmink, R., & Clowes, R. (2016). The cognitive ecology of the internet. In S. Cowley & F. Vallée-Tourangeau (Eds.), Cognition beyond the brain: Computation, interactivity and human artifice (2nd ed.). Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Sparrow, B., Liu, J., & Wegner, D. M. (2011). Google effects on memory: Cognitive consequences of having information at our fingertips. Science, 333(6043), 776–778.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J. (2009). The feel of the world: Exograms, habits, and the confusion of types of memory. In A. Kania (Ed.), Philosophers on Memento (pp. 65–86). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J. (2010). Exograms and interdisciplinarity: History, the extended mind, and the civilizing process. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind (pp. 189–225). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J., Harris, C. B., Keil, P., & Barnier, A. J. (2010). The psychology of memory, extended cognition, and socially distributed remembering. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9(4), 521–560.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Theiner, G. (2013). Transactive memory systems: A mechanistic analysis of emergent group memory. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 4(1), 65–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turkle, S. (2011). Alone together: Why we expect more from technology and less from each other. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • van den Hoven, E. (2014). A future-proof past: Designing for remembering experiences. Memory Studies, 7(3), 373–387.

    Google Scholar 

  • van den Hoven, E., Cas, C., & Whittaker, S. (2012). Introduction to this special issue on designing for personal memories: Past, present, and future. Human-Computer Interaction, 27(1–2), 1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, D. M. (1995). A computer network model of human transactive memory. Social Cognition, 13(3), 319–339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, D. M., Giuliano, T., & Hertel, P. T. (1985). Cognitive interdependence in close relationships. In W. J. Ickes (Ed.), Compatible and incompatible relationships (pp. 253–276). New York: Springer-Verlag.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R., & Lenart, B. (2014). Extended mind and identity. In J. Clausen & N. Levy (Eds.), Handbook of neuroethics (pp. 423–439). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Neil Levy for helpful advice, Paul Smart and Robert Clowes for discussion on embodiment and the self, and two anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments and suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Richard Heersmink.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Heersmink, R. Distributed selves: personal identity and extended memory systems. Synthese 194, 3135–3151 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1102-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1102-4

Keywords

Navigation