Skip to main content
Log in

Basic social cognition without mindreading: minding minds without attributing contents

  • S.I. : Future of Social Cognition
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

“Think left and think right and think low and think high. Oh, the things you can think up if only you try!”

Dr. Seuss.

Abstract

This paper argues that mind-reading hypotheses (MRHs), of any kind, are not needed to best describe or best explain basic acts of social cognition. It considers the two most popular MRHs: one-ToM and two-ToM theories. These MRHs face competition in the form of complementary behaviour reading hypotheses (CBRHs). Following Buckner (Mind Lang 29:566–589, 2014), it is argued that the best strategy for putting CBRHs out of play is to appeal to theoretical considerations about the psychosemantics of basic acts of social cognition. In particular, need-based accounts that satisfy a teleological criterion have the ability to put CBRHs out of play. Yet, against this backdrop, a new competitor for MRHs is revealed: mind minding hypothesis (MMHs). MMHs are capable of explaining all the known facts about basic forms of social cognition and they also satisfy the teleological criterion. In conclusion, some objections concerning the theoretical tenability of MMHs are addressed and prospects for further research are canvassed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Carruthers (2015) has argued that the concepts and principles MinToM employs are not up to empirical scratch—that they don’t adequately explain all of the infant data easily. Even if this is so, an obvious way of addressing these concerns would be to update and augment MinToM in certain key respects, while still ensuring that differed in relevant ways from MaxToM that enables the ascription of propositional attitudes. Butterfill and Apperly (2013) make clear that they are prepared for some revisions: “Registration has been defined as a relation between agents, objects and locations. This definition could be extended to include other types of property as relata in addition to locations” (Butterfill and Apperly 2013, p. 620).

  2. Lurz (2009) coined this term.

  3. Lurz (2009, 2011) has tried harder than most to settle the on-going debates about whether some animals mindread by devising cunning new experimental designs. For full details see (Buckner 2014).

  4. As committed explanatory naturalists, Carruthers, Fodor and other classical cognitivists, are meant to provide explanatory theories that are empirically substantial—thus risky and provisional. Such theories are to be assessed in the light of the full range of available empirical evidence as well as their fit with “surrounding theories of cognitive science” (Carruthers 2011, p. xiii). All the same, reminiscent of Gilbert and Sullivan’s Captain of the Pinafore, Carruthers (2011) tells us of his book the Opacity of Mind that “hardly any of it its claims are intended to be a priori” (Carruthers 2011, p. xiii, emphasis added). It may be suspected that unless they are given further substantive backing and justification the main working assumptions of classical cognitivism (e.g. about the need to posit structured conceptual representations) fall into the class of a priori framework assumptions that are taken to be true without argument.

  5. Pressing for thoroughgoing non-representationalism also protects the MMH against the sort of objections Carruthers raises against the two-ToMH: “if we assume, as we surely should, that infants are capable of propositional thought s such as THE RED BALL IS IN THE BOX, and if we allow that infants at least possess a concept like REGISTERS, then all the infant needs to do is embed that very representation into the scope of an attribution, thinking, THE AGENT REGISTERS: THE RED BALL IS IN THE BOX. The result is that the infant has attributed a propositional content to the agent” (Carruthers 2015, p. 17, emphasis added).

  6. As Price (2013) observes, we should not be tricked by the fact that the label ‘representation’ is used when talking both about ways of responding to covariant information and those that involve truth-conditional content. Rather, “these two notions of representation should properly be kept apart, not clumsily pushed together. It takes some effort to see that the two notions of representation might float free of one another, but I think it is an effort worth making. ... Once the distinction between these two notions of representation is on the table, it is open to us to regard the two notions as having different applications, for various theoretical purposes” (Price 2013, p. 37).

  7. De Bruin and Kästner (2012) propose a way of developing this idea that retains some role for minimal representations. But see Ciaunica (2014) for a radically enactive reply that attempts to show why such conversativism is unnecessary and unhelpful.

  8. For example, Lavelle (2012) is right when it comes to understanding social cognition focusing on “Innate sensitivities alone do not seem up to the explanatory task” (p. 468). As Buckner (2014) recommends theories of social cognition need to focus more on learning and integration. That suggestion is, however, wholly compatible with radically enactive MMHs. Lavelle (2012) is also right that a very simple natural signs account is limited in important respects when it comes to understanding human social cognition. The point is well taken. But MMHs can be augmented and extended, see for example Medina’s (2013) discussion of how natural signs might be traded for expressive natural signs in an enactivist-friendly way, in line with Bar-On’s (2013a, b) proposals.

References

  • Apperly, I. (2011). Mindreaders: The cognitive basis of “theory of mind”. Hove: Psychological Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Apperly, I. (2013). Can theory of mind grow up? Mindreading in adults, and its implications for the development and neuroscience of mindreading. In S. Baron-Cohen, H. Tager-Flusberg, & M. V. Lombardo (Eds.), Understanding other minds: Perspectives from developmental social neuroscience (pp. 72–92). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Apperly, I., & Butterfill, S. (2009). Do humans have two systems to track beliefs and belief-like states? Psychological Review, 116, 953–970.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Araújo, D. (2009). Ecological approaches to cognition in sport and exercise. International Journal of Sport Psychology, 40, 1–227.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baillargeon, R., Scott, R., & He, Z. (2010). False-belief understanding in infants. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14, 110–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S., Tager-Flusberg, H., & Lombardo, M. V. (2013). Understanding other minds: What’s new. In S. Baron-Cohen, H. Tager-Flusberg, & M. V. Lombardo (Eds.), Understanding other minds: Perspectives from developmental social neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bar-On, D. (2013a). Expressive communication and continuity skepticism. Journal of Philosophy, CX(6), 293–330.

  • Bar-On, D. (2013b). Origins of meaning: Must we ‘go Gricean? Mind and Language, 28(3), 342–375.

  • Bermúdez, J. L. (2011). The force-field puzzle and mindreading in non-human primates. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2(3), 397–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brincker, M. (2014). Navigating beyond ‘here & now’ affordances: On sensorimotor maturation and ‘false belief’ performance. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 1433. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckner, C. (2014). The semantic problem(s) with research on animal mind-reading. Mind and Language, 29(5), 566–589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (2010). The origins of objectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Buttelmann, D., Carpenter, M., & Tomasello, M. (2009). Eighteen-month-old infants show false belief understanding in an active helping paradigm. Cognition, 112, 337–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butterfill, S., & Apperly, I. (2013). How to construct a minimal theory of mind. Mind and Language, 28(5), 606–637.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2009a). Mindreading underlies metacognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32, 121–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2009b). Invertebrate concepts confront the generality constraint (and win). In R. Lurz (Ed.), The philosophy of animal minds (pp. 89–107). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2011). The opacity of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Carruthers, P. (2013). Mindreading in infancy. Mind and Language, 28(2), 141–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2015). Two systems for mindreading? Review of Philosophy and Psychology. doi:10.1007/s13164-015-0259-y.

  • Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ciaunica, A. (2014). Under pressure: processing representational decoupling in false-belief tasks. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 5(4), 527–542.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1984). Inquiries into truth and interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1990). The structure and content of truth. Journal of philosophy LXXXVIII, 6, 279–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Bruin, L. C., & Kästner, L. (2012). Dynamic embodied cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 11(4), 541–563.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Bruin, L. C., & Newen, A. (2014). The developmental paradox of false belief understanding: A dual-system solution. Synthese, 191(3), 297–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davids, K., & Araújo, D. (2010a). The concept of ‘Organismic Asymmetry’ in sport science. Journal of Science and Medicine in Sport, 13, 633–640.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davids, K., & Araújo, D. (2010b). Perception of affordances in multi-scale dynamics as an alternative explanation for equivalence of analogical and inferential reasoning in animals and humans. Theory and Psychology, 20(1), 125–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fenici, M. (2013). Social cognitive abilities in infancy: Is mindreading the best explanation? Philosophical Psychology,. doi:10.1080/09515089.2013.865096.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fenici, M. (2014). A simple explanation of apparent early mindreading: infants’ sensitivity to goals and gaze direction. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences,. doi:10.1007/s11097-014-9345-3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher, L., & Carruthers, P. (2013). Behavior-reading versus mentalizing in animals. Agency and joint attention (pp. 82–99). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1995). A theory of the child’s theory of mind. In M. Davies & T. Stone (Eds.), Mental simulation. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (2003). Hume variations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (2007). The revenge of the given. In B. McLaughlin & J. Cohen (Eds.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of mind (pp. 105–116). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A., & Pylyshyn, Z. (2015). Minds without meanings. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallistel, C. R. (1998). Symbolic processes in the brain: The case of insect navigation. In D. Scarborough & S. Sternberg (Eds.) Methods, models, and conceptual issues (vol. 4, pp. 1-51). Invitation to cognitive science. (D. Osherson, series Ed.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press

  • Heyes, C. M., & Frith, C. D. (2014). The cultural evolution of mind reading. Science, 244(6190), 1243091-1–1243091-6. doi:10.1126/science.1243091.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. (2004). The limits of spectatorial folk psychology. Mind and Language, 19, 548–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. (2005). Starting without theory. In B. Malle & S. Hodges (Eds.), Other minds (pp. 56–72). New York: Guilford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. (2008). Folk psychological narratives: The sociocultural basis of understanding reasons. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. (2011). Elementary mind minding, enactivist-style. In A. Seemann (Ed.), Joint attention: New developments in philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience (pp. 307–341). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. (2013). Why believe in contentless beliefs? In N. Nottelmann (Ed.), New essays on belief: Structure, constitution and content (pp. 55–74). London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., Herschbach, M., & Southgate, V. (2011). Mindreading and its alternatives. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2(3), 375–395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D.D., Kirchhoff, M. D. (forthcoming). Social neuroscience in context: narrative practices, niche construction and neural patterns. Cognitive Systems Research.

  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knudsen, B., & Liszkowski, U. (2012). 18-month-olds predict specific action mistakes through attribution of false belief, not ignorance, and intervene accordingly. Infancy, 17, 672–691.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lavelle, J. S. (2012). Two challenges to Hutto’s enactive account of pre-linguistic social cognition. Philosophia, 40, 459–472.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A., Friedman, O., & German, T. P. (2004). Core mechanisms in ’theory of mind’. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8, 528–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lurz, R. (2009). If chimpanzees are mindreaders, could behavioral science tell? Toward a solution of the logical problem. Philosophical Psychology, 22(3), 305–28. doi:10.1080/09515080902970673.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lurz, R. (2011). Mindreading animals: The debate over what animals know about other minds. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Medina, J. (2013). An enactivist approach to the imagination: Embodied enactments and fictional emotions. American Philosophical Quarterly, 50(3), 317–335.

    Google Scholar 

  • Onishi, K., & Baillargeon, R. (2005). Do 15-month-old infants understand false beliefs? Science, 308, 255–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Overgaard, S., & Michael, J. (2015). The interactive turn in social cognition research: A critique. Philosophical Psychology, 28(2), 160–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. (2013). Expressivism, pragmatism and representationalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, W. M. (2007). Representation reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rescorla, M. (2013). Millikan on honeybee navigation and communication. In J. Kingsbury, D. Ryder, & K. Williford (Eds.), Millikan and her critics (pp. 87–102). Oxford: Wiley Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rupert, R. (2011). Embodiment, consciousness, and the massively representational mind. Philosophical Topics, 39(1), 99–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Segal, G. (1996). The modularity of theory of mind. In P. Carruthers & P. Smith (Eds.), Theories of theories of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Southgate, V. (2013). Early manifestations of mindreading. In S. Baron-Cohen, H. Tager-Flusberg, & M. V. Lombardo (Eds.), Understanding other minds: Perspectives from developmental social neuroscience (pp. 3–18). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Southgate, V., Chevallier, C., & Csibra, G. (2010). Seventeen-month-olds appeal to false beliefs to interpret others’ referential communication. Developmental Science, 13, 907–912.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Southgate, V., Senju, A., & Csibra, G. (2007). Action anticipation through attribution of false belief by 2-year-olds. Psychological Science, 18, 587–592.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spaulding, S. (2011). Embodied social cognition. Philosophical Topics, 39(1), 141–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, J. R. (2014). Signature limits in mindreading systems. Cognitive Science, 38(7), 1432–1455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warren, W. H. (2006). The dynamics of perception and action. Psychological Review, 113(2), 358–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weast, J. A., Shockley, K., & Riley, M. A. (2011). The influence of athletic experience and kinematic information on skill-relevant affordance perception. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 64(4), 689–706.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, A. D., & Golonka, S. (2013). Embodied cognition is not what you think it is. Frontiers in Psychology, 4(58), 1–13. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00058.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zawidzki, T. W. (2013). Mindshaping: A new framework for understanding human social cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniel D. Hutto.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hutto, D.D. Basic social cognition without mindreading: minding minds without attributing contents. Synthese 194, 827–846 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0831-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0831-0

Keywords

Navigation