Skip to main content
Log in

What are cognitive processes? An example-based approach

  • S.I.: Cognition
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The question “What are cognitive processes?” can be understood variously as meaning “What is the nature of cognitive processes?”, “Can we distinguish epistemically cognitive processes from physical and biochemical processes on the one hand, and from mental or conscious processes on the other?”, and “Can we establish a fruitful notion of cognitive process?” The present aim is to deliver a positive answer to the last question by developing criteria for what would count as a paradigmatic exemplar of a cognitive process, and then to offer the comparator (or feedforward) mechanism as a convincing paradigmatic example. Thus, the paper argues, given the current state of science, we can indeed establish a fruitful scientific notion of a cognitive process. Nevertheless, it is left open whether the example-based characterization ends up as merely highlighting a fruitful convention within the early-twentyfirst century interdisciplinary investigation of intelligent behaviour in humans, animals, and robots, or whether the examples determine a natural kind or a property cluster.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Language documentation is an important endeavour in times in which dialects and whole languages are rapidly dying out. An example is the Berkeley documentation: http://linguistics.berkeley.edu/research/field/index.

  2. A description of this moving house can be found at: http://www.drehhaus.de/de/zweite-generation.php.

  3. This illustrates Wittgenstein’s thoughts about concept expressed by the word “game”: “Consider for example the proceedings that we call ‘games’. I mean board-games, card-games, ball-games, Olympic games, and so on. [...] Look at the parts played by skill and luck; and at the difference between skill in chess and skill in tennis. Think now of games like ring-aring-a-roses; here is the element of amusement, but how many other characteristic features have disappeared! And we can go through the many, many groups of games in the same way; can see how similarities crop up and disappear. And the result of this examination is: we see a complicated network of similarities overlapping and criss-crossing: sometimes overall similarities, sometimes similarities of detail” (Wittgenstein 1967, PU § 66).

  4. This implies that if we have a mechanism which only explains very rigid behavior without playing any role in producing more complex flexible behaviour, then it is not fruitful to count it as a cognitive mechanism.

  5. This claim is defended together with the background theory that social cognition is mainly mental simulation as described in simulation theory (Goldman 2006); but it is criticized by alternative accounts such as theory-theory (Baron-Cohen 1995; Gopnik 1993), interaction theory (Gallagher 2001; Gallagher and Hutto 2008), and person model theory (Newen and Schlicht 2009; Newen 2015).

References

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2008). The bounds of cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Baron-Cohen, S. (1995). Mindblindness. An essay on autism and theory of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blakemore, S. J., Goodbody, S. J., & Wolpert, D. M. (1998). Predicting the consequences of our own actions: The role of sensorimotor context estimation. Journal of Neuroscience, 18(18), 7511–7518.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blakemore, S. J., Frith, C., & Wolpert, D. M. (1999). Spatio-temporal prediction modulates the perception of self-produced stimuli. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 11(5), 551–559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blakemore, S. J., Smith, J., Steel, R., Johnstone, C. E., & Frith, C. D. (2000). The perception of self-produced sensory stimuli in patients with auditory hallucinations and passivity experiences: Evidence for a breakdown in self-monitoring. Psychological Medicine, 30(5), 1131–1139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1999). Kinds, complexity and multiple realization. Philosophical Studies, 95(1), 67–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, R. A. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47, 139–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckner, C. (2015). A property cluster theory of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 28, 307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. (1999). Schizophrenia, the space of reasons, and thinking as motor process. The Monist, 84, 609–625.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58, 10–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cook, R., Bird, G., Catmur, C., Press, C., & Heyes, C. (2014). Mirror neurons: From origin to function. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 37, 177–241. doi:10.1017/S0140525X13000903.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, M., Coltheart, M., Langdon, R., & Breen, N. (2001). Monothematic delusions: Towards a two-factor account. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology, 8, 133–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DelRose, M., Wagner, C., & Frederick, P. (2011). Evidence feed forward hidden Markov model: A new type of hidden Markov model. International Journal of Artificial Intelligence and Applications, 2(1), 1–19. doi:10.5121/ijaia.2011.2101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eichenbaum, H. (2013). Memory on time. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 17(2), 8–81. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2012.12.007. Epub 2013 Jan 12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frith, C. D., Blakemore, S., & Wolpert, D. M. (2000). Explaining the symptoms of schizophrenia: Abnormalities in the awareness of action. Brain Research Review, 31(2–3), 357–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2001). The practice of mind: Theory, simulation, or interaction? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8(5–7), 83–107.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Hutto, D. D. (2008). Understanding others through primary interaction and narrative practice. In J. Zlatev, T. Racine, C. Sinha, & E. Itkonen (Eds.), The shared mind: Perspectives on intersubjectivity (pp. 17–38). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., & Rizzolatti, G. (1996). Action recognition in the premotor cortex. Brain, 119, 593–609.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., & Goldman, A. (1998). Mirror neurons and the simulation theory of mind-reading. Trends in Cognitive Science, 1/2(12), 493–501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (2006). Simulating minds: The philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience of mindreading. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Gopnik, A. (1993). How we know our minds: The illusion of first-person knowledge of intentionality. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 16(1), 1–15, 90–101. doi:10.1017/S0140525X00028636.

  • Grotjahn, M. (2002). Model-based feedforward control in industrial robotics. The International Journal of Robotics Research, 21, 45–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heyes, C. (2010). Where do mirror neurons come from? Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 34, 575–583.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hofmann, V., Sanguinetti-Scheck, J. I., Künzel, S., Geurten, B., Gómez-Sena, L., & Engelman, J. (2013). Locomotion and sensing of weakly electric fish: Sensory flow shaped by active sensing: Sensorimotor strategies in electric fish. Journal of Experimental Biology, 216, 2487–2500. doi:10.1242/jeb.082420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hübener, M., & Bonhoeffer, T. (2014). Neuronal plasticity: Beyond the critical period. Cell, 159(4), 727–737. doi:10.1016/j.cell.2014.10.035.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. (1998). Consciousness in action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchison, W., Davis, K., Lozano, A., Tasker, R., & Dostrovxky, J. (1999). Pain related neurons in the human cingulate cortex. Nature Neuroscience, 2, 403–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, P. (2008). What do mirror neurons contribute to human social cognition? Mind & Language, 23(2), 190–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jabbi, M., Swart, M., & Keysers, C. (2007). Empathy for positive and negative emotions in the gustatory cortex. NeuroImage, 34(4), 1744–1753.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kästner, L., & Walter, S. (2009). What is cognition?—functionalism and extended cognition. In V. A. Munz, K. Puhl, & J. Wang (Eds.), Language and world. Preproceedings of the 32nd International Wittgenstein Symposium. Kirchberg am Wechsel, Österreich: Ontos.

  • Kern, R., Egelhaaf, M., & Srinivasan, M. V. (1997). Edge detection by landing honeybees: Behavioural analysis and model simulations of the underlying mechanism. Vision Research, 37(15), 2103–2117.

  • Keysers, C., & Gazzola, V. (2010). Social neuroscience: Mirror neurons recorded in humans. Current Biology, 20(8), R353–R354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macnab, R. M., & Koshland, D. E. (1972). The gradient-sensing mechanism in bacterial chemotaxis. PNAS, 69, 2509–2512.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2010). The extended mind. Cambridge: M.I.T. Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, G. A. (2003). The cognitive revolution: A historical perspective. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7(3), 141–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milner, A. D., & Goodale, M. A. (1995). The visual brain in action. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newen, A. (2015). Understanding others: The person model theory. In T. Metzinger, & J. M. Windt (Eds). Open MIND. Frankfurt a.M.: MIND Group, article 26, 1–28.

  • Newen, A., & Schlicht, T. (2009). Understanding other minds. A criticism of Goldman’s simulation theory and an outline of the person model theory. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 79(1), 209–242.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noe, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poulet, J. F. A., & Hedwig, B. (2006). The cellular basis of a corollary discharge. Science, 311, 518–522.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of ‘meaning’. In H. Putnam (Ed.), Mind, language and reality. Philosophical Papers (Vol. 2, pp. 215–271). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1951). Two dogmas of empiricism. Philosophical Review, 60(1), 20–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rescorla, R. A. (1988). Pavlovian conditioning. It’s not what you think it is. American Psychologist, 43(3), 151–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., & Craighero, L. (2004). The mirror neuron system. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 27, 169–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robbins, P., & Aydede, M. (2009). The Cambridge Handbook of Situated Cognition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spaulding, S. (2013). Mirror neurons and social cognition. Mind and Language, 28(2), 233–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Synofzik, M., Vosgerau, G., & Newen, A. (2008a). Beyond the comparator model: A multifactorial two-step account of agency. Consciousness & Cognition, 17, 219–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Synofzik, M., Vosgerau, G., & Newen, A. (2008b). I move, therefore I am: A new theoretical framework to investigate agency and ownership. Consciousness & Cognition, 17, 411–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (2010). Cognitive science. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2012 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2012/entries/cognitive-science.

  • Tsakiris, M., Haggard, P., Franck, N., Mainy, N., & Sirigu, A. (2005). A specific role for efferent information in self-recognition. Cognition, 96, 215–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Holst, E., & Mittelstaedt, H. (1950). Das Reafferenzprinzip. Naturwissenschaften, 37, 464–476.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vosgerau, G., & Newen, A. (2007). Thoughts, motor actions, and the self. Mind and Language, 22, 22–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wells, R., Schueller, J. K., & Tlusty, J. (1990). Feedforward and feedback control of a flexible robotic arm. IEEE Control Systems Magazine, 10, 9–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wicker, B., Keysers, C., Plailly, J., Royet, J. P., Gallese, V., & Rizzolatti, G. (2003). Both of us disgusted in my insula: The common neural basis of seeing and feeling disgust. Neuron, 40(3), 655–664.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1967). Philosophical Investigations (G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell (original in German from 1953).

Download references

Acknowledgments

For helpful comments, I would like to thank Francesco Marchi, Pascale Willemsen, and two anonymous referees.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Albert Newen.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Newen, A. What are cognitive processes? An example-based approach. Synthese 194, 4251–4268 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0812-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0812-3

Keywords

Navigation