Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Automatically minded

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is not rare in philosophy and psychology to see theorists fall into dichotomous thinking about mental phenomena. On one side of the dichotomy there are processes that I will label “unintelligent.” These processes are thought to be unconscious, implicit, automatic, unintentional, involuntary, procedural, and non-cognitive. On the other side, there are “intelligent” processes that are conscious, explicit, controlled, intentional, voluntary, declarative, and cognitive. Often, if a process or behavior is characterized by one of the features from either of the above lists, the process or behavior is classified as falling under the category to which the feature belongs. For example, if a process is implicit this is usually considered sufficient for classifying it as “unintelligent” and for assuming that the remaining features that fall under the “unintelligent” grouping will apply to it as well. Accordingly, if a process or behavior is automatic, philosophers often consider it to be unintelligent. It is my goal in this paper to challenge the conceptual slip from “automatic” to “unintelligent”. I will argue that there are a whole range of properties highlighted by the existing psychological literature that make automaticity a much more complex phenomenon than is usually appreciated. I will then go on to discuss two further important relationships between automatic processes and controlled processes (C-processes) that arise when we think about automatic processes in the context of skilled behavior. These interactions should add to our resistance to classifying automaticity as unintelligent or mindless. In Sect. 1, I present a few representative cases of philosophers classifying automatic processes and behaviors as mindless or unintelligent. In Sect. 2, I review trends in the psychology of automaticity in order highlight a complex set of features that are characteristic, though not definitive, of automatic processes and behaviors. In Sect. 3, I argue that at least some automatic processes are likely cognitively penetrable. In Sect. 4, I argue that the structure of skilled automatic processes is shaped diachronically by practice, training and learning. Taken together, these considerations should dislodge the temptation to equate “automatic” with “unintelligent”.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For similar claims see Logan (1985), Karmiloff-Smith (1994), Tzelgov (1997a, b), Hommel (2007).

  2. Philosophers and psychologists use the labels “cognitive” and “noncognitive” in different ways: for psychologists and cognitive scientists “cognitive” usually means something like “mental.” In this way, perception, memory, learning, etc. are all cognitive phenomena. Philosophers, on the other hand, use “cognitive” to mean something like “intelligent” such that it makes sense to ask whether perception is cognitive or cognitively penetrable as does Fodor (1983), Pylyshyn (2000), Prinz (2006), Siegel (2010). It is in order to avoid confusion, that I use “intelligent” and “unintelligent” instead of “cognitive” and noncognitive” as my general categories of classification above.

  3. This kind of move is not altogether accidental since one of the most influential theories in the philosophy of mind, Fodor’s (1983) Modularity of Mind, is committed to precisely this clustering of features. A hallmark of modularity is that a certain class of processes exhibit a suite of characteristics are indicative of their modularity. I will not argue against modularity in this article but, in focusing on automaticity, I will show that dual-mode theories often overlook the complexity of the relationships between various often but not always co-occurring features.

  4. Ryle writes, “The consideration of propositions is itself an operation the execution of which can be more or less intelligent, less or more stupid. But if, for any operation to be intelligently executed, a prior theoretical operation had first to be performed and performed intelligently, it would be a logical impossibility for anyone ever to break into the circle (1949, p. 30).”

  5. Intellectualism is the view that the cognitive or intelligent aspects of skill or know how are reducible to knowing an appropriate proposition governing that skill.

  6. Stanley writes, “[T]riggering representations is something done by an input systems rather than a central system, by a module rather than a central processor. Such triggering is something we do automatically” (2011, p. 16).

  7. As Dreyfus and Dreyfus (1986) write, “competent performance is rational; proficient is transitional; experts act arationally” (p. 36, emphasis in original).

  8. See Logan (1985), Tzelgov (1999), Moors and Houwer (2006), Di Nucci (2013), Wu (2013a), for similar claims.

  9. In order to identify a process or behavior as potentially automatic in the first place, I think that the best we can do is to begin with the processes and behaviors that psychologists have generally studied as automatic.

  10. “Effortless” refers to the subjective, qualitative feeling that accompanies a task that does not require attention.

  11. The Stroop task tests for effects of non-target features on the understanding of a word. E.g., reading the word “red” when the letters R-E-D are purple in color results in a slower reaction time.

  12. Sheets-Johnstone writes, “when Luria speaks of the automatization of movement, it is important to point out that he is describing the way in which a single impulse is sufficient to activate a kinetic melody, and not asserting that one is unaware of writing one’s name, that one is unconscious of doing so, or that one can nod off while the process continues by itself” (p. 52).

  13. See Montero (2010) for a defense of this position and a critique of the empirical evidence that is usually appealed to in order to support the view that attention and skill are incompatible.

  14. See Logan (1985) for similar considerations.

  15. Bargh (1992) has proposed that the central feature that all automatic processes and behaviors share is autonomy. “He defined an autonomous process as one that, once started (and irrespective of whether it was started intentionally or unintentionally), runs to completion with no need for conscious guidance or monitoring” (Moors and Houwer 2006, p.301). But, as I argued above in reference to Wu (2013a), and as Moors and DeHouwer make clear, it isn’t clear why any one feature, as opposed to any other feature, should have priority as being definitive of automaticity.

  16. See Wu (2013a) for a report that Shiffrin has since given up on the possibility of any feature list as definitive of automaticity.

  17. To operationalize this concept, one would have to select the processes or features of automaticity that one was most interested in investigating. By combining various processes and features, one could investigate their overlap. This would make the concept of automaticity operationalizable according to various dimensions depending on the concerns of the researcher.

  18. See Pylyshyn (2000) and Stokes (2013) for elucidation of this point.

  19. See also Sutton (2007).

  20. For similar claims see Wu (2011, 2013b).

  21. “We have seen ample reason to think that top-level batting is more like an automatic reflex than any consciously controlled sequence of movements” (Papineau 2013, p.184).

  22. For more, see Sect. 4 below. Also, see Todorov and Jordan (2002), Todorov (2004), Liu and Todorov (2007), Deidrichsen (2007).

  23. See Fridland (2013a) for more on the problem of selecting between many fine-grained action routines.

  24. See Pylyshyn (2003), Wu (2011, forthcoming), and Fridland (2014a) for more on this kind of automatic, selective attention.

  25. “Such anticipation is based, for example, on observing initial segments of the motion of a ball or puck or the opponent’s gestures. Except for a finding of generally better attention-orientation abilities visual expertise in sports, like the expertise found in the Chase and Simon studies of chess skill, appears to be based on the nonvisual abilities related to the learned skills of identifying, predicting and therefore attending to the most relevant places” (2003, p. 85).

  26. See Wu (2011, forthcoming) for more on the automaticity of selective attention.

  27. As Wu has said, “Attention in the form of eye movements tracks intention, even where the intention is not explicitly to attend in that way. It won’t be strange, colloquially, to say that once the person starts looking, a pattern of eye movements happens automatically which makes perfect sense given what the person is looking for. The specific pattern of the movements is a feature of the subject’s attention, one that is not represented in the content of the intention...At the same time, this automatic feature is clearly influenced by the goals we have, for the pattern of movements makes sense given the intention, so it is top-down influenced (personal communication).

  28. See Fridland (2013b, 2014b), Fridland and Moore (2014c). Montero (forthcoming) for more on practice.

  29. See Christensen et al. (in progress) for a defense of this claim.

  30. In emphasizing that expert skills are automatic, I do not mean to endorse a position that excludes the possibility of experts occasionally performing the automatic components of their skill in non-automatic ways. This may occur, perhaps, when experts deliberately practice and refine particular aspects of a skill.

  31. “At the heart of the framework is the relationship between high-level goals, and the real-time sensorimotor control strategies most suitable for accomplishing those goals” (Todorov 2004, p. 907).

  32. This body of evidence [supporting optimal control theory] is fundamentally incompatible, with models that enforce a strict separation between trajectory planning and trajectory execution. In such serial models, the planning stage resolves the redundancy inherent in the musculoskeletal system by replacing the behavioral goal (achievable via infinitely many trajectories) with a specific ‘desired trajectory’. Accurate execution of the desired trajectory guarantees achievement of the goal, and can be implemented with relatively simple trajectory-tracking algorithms. Although this approach is computationally viable (and often used in engineering), the many observations of task-constrained variability and goal-directed corrections indicate that online execution mechanisms are able to distinguish, and selectively enforce, the details that are crucial for goal achievement. This would be impossible if the behavioral goal were replaced with a specific trajectory (Todorov and Jordan 2002, p. 1226).

  33. Though, some would disagree (See Stanley 2011).

References

  • Bargh, J. (1989). Conditional automaticity: Varieties of automatic influence in social perception and cognition. In J. S. Uleman & J. A. Bargh (Eds.), Unintended thought. New York: Guilford Press.

  • Bargh, J. (1992). The ecology of automaticity: Toward establishing the conditions needed to produce automatic processing effects. American Journal of Psychology, 105(2), 181–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bargh, J. (1994). The four horsemen of automaticity: Awareness, intention, efficiency, and control in social cognition. In R. S. Wyer & T. K. Srull (Eds.), Handbook of social cognition (Vol. 1, pp. 1–40). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bargh, J., & Chatrand, T. (1999). The unbearable automaticity of being. American Psychologist, 53(7), 462–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bargh, J., Schwader, K., Hailey, S., Dyer, R., & Boothby, E. (2012). Automaticity in social-cognitive processes. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 16(12), 593–605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beilock, S. (2010). Choke: What the secrets of the brain reveal about getting it right when you have to. New York: Free Press.

  • Bernstein, N. I. (1967). The coordination and regulation of movements. Oxford: Pergamon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berry, D., & Broadbent, D. (1984). On the relationship between task performance and associated verbalizable knowledge. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 36(A), 209–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blair, I. V., Ma, J. E., & Lenton, A. P. (2001). Imagining stereotypes away: The moderation of implicit stereotypes through mental imagery. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 81(5), 828–841.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boutin, A., Blandin, Y., Massen, C., Heuer, H., & Badets, A. (2014). Conscious awareness of action potentiates sensorimotor learning. Cognition, 133, 1–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brehmer, B., Hagafors, R., & Johansson, R. (1980). Cognitive skills in judgment: Subjects’ ability to use information about weights, function forms, and organizing principles. Organizational Behavior and Human Performance, 26, 373–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cheng, P. W. (1985). Restructuring versus automaticity: Alternate accounts of skill acquisition. Psychological Review, 92, 414–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, W., Sutton, J., & McIlwain, D. (in progress). Cognitive control in skilled action.

  • Cole, K. J., & Abbs, J. H. (1986). Coordination of three-joint digit movements for rapid finger-thumb grasp. Journal of Neurophysiology, 55, 1407–1423.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deidrichsen, J. (2007). Optimal task-dependent changes of bimanual feedback control and adaptation. Current Biology, 17, 1675–1679.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devine, P. G. (1989). Stereotypes and prejudice: Their automatic and controlled components. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 56, 680–690.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Nucci, E. (2013). Mindlessness. Cambridge: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Domkin, D., Laczko, J., Jaric, S., Johansson, H., & Latash, M. L. (2002). Structure of joint variability in bimanual pointing tasks. Experimental Brain Research, 143, 11–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H., & Dreyfus, S. (1986). Mind over machine. Mumbai: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. (2007). The return of the myth of the mental. Inquiry, 50(4), 352–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. (2002). Intelligence without representation: Merleau Ponty’s critique of representation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 367–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunton, B. C., & Fazio, R. H. (1997). An individual difference measure of motivation to control prejudiced reactions. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 23, 316–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ericsson, A. K., & Charness, N. (1994). Expert performance: Its structure and acquisition. American Psychologist, 49, 725–774.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fazio, R. H., Jackson, J., Dunton, B., & Williams, C. (1995). Variability in automatic Activation as an unobtrusive measure of racial attitudes: A bona fide pipeline? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 69, 1013–1027.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (1978). The problem of action. American Philosophical Quarterly, 15(2), 157–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M. (1982). Responsibility and control. Journal of Philosophy, 89, 24–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M., & Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and control: An essay on moral responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fiske, S. T. (1989). Examining the role of intent: Toward understanding its role in stereotyping and prejudice. In S. Uleman & A. Bargh (Eds.), Unintended thought (pp. 253–283). New York: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1983). The modularity of mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Francolini, C. M., & Egeth, H. (1980). On the automaticity of “Automatic” activation: Evidence of selective seeing. Perception & Psychophysics, 27, 331–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fridland, E. (2013a). Problems with intellectualism. Philosophical Studies, 165(3), 879–891.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fridland, E. (2013b). Imitation, skill learning, and conceptual thought: An embodied, developmental approach. In L. Swan (Ed.), The origins of mind: Springer book series in biosemantics.: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fridland, E. (2014). They’ve lost control: Reflections on skill. Synthese, 91(12), 2729–2750.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fridland, E. (2014b). Skill learning and conceptual thought: Making our way through the wilderness. In B. Bashour & H. Muller (Eds.), Philosophical naturalism and its implications. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fridland, E., & Moore, R. (2014). Imitation reconsidered. Philosophical Psychology,. doi:10.1080/09515089.2014.942896.

  • Haith, A., & Krakauer, J. (2013). Theoretical models of motor control and motor learning. In A. Gollhofer, W. Taube, & J. B. Nielsen (Eds.), Routledge handbook of motor control and motor learning (pp. 1–28). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hasher, L., & Zacks, R. T. (1979). Automatic and effortful processes in memory. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 108, 356–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, J. E., Nelson, B., & Houck, M. R. (1983). The role of attentional resources in automatic detection. Cognitive Psychology, 51, 379–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hommel, B. (2007). Consciousness and control: Not identical Twins. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 14(1–2), 155–176.

    Google Scholar 

  • Izawa, J., Rane, T., Donchin, O., & Shadmehr, R. (2008). Motor adaptation as a process of reoptimization. The Journal of Neuroscience, 28(11), 2883–2891.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Chajczyk, D. (1983). Test of the automaticity of reading: Dilution of stroop effects by color-irrelevant stimuli. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 9, 497–509.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Henik, A. (1981). Perceptual organization and attention. In M. Kubovy & J. Pomerantz (Eds.), Perceptual organization (pp. 181–212). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karmiloff-Smith, A. (1994). Précis of beyond modularity: A developmental perspective on cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 17(4), 693–735.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kawakami, K., Dovidio, J. F., Moll, J., Hermsen, S., & Russin, A. J. (2000). Just say no (to stereotyping): Effects of training in the negation of stereotypic associations on stereotype activation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 78(5), 871–888.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • LaBerge, D., & Samuels, S. J. (1974). Toward a theory of automatic information processing in reading. Cognitive Psychology, 6, 293–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liu, D., & Todorov, E. (2007). Evidence for the flexible sensorimotor strategies predicted by optimal feedback control. The Journal of Neuroscience, 27(35), 9354–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Logan, G. D. (1979). On the use of concurrent memory load to measure attention and automaticity. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 5, 189–207.

    Google Scholar 

  • Logan, G. D. (1980). Attention and automaticity in stroop and priming tasks: Theory and cata. Cognitive Psychology, 12, 523–553.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Logan, G. (1985). Skill and automaticity: Relations, implications, and future directions. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 39(2), 367–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macpherson, F. (2012). Cognitive penetration of colour experience: Rethinking the issue in light of an indirect mechanism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 84(1), 24–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milner, D., & Goodale, M. A. (2006). The visual brain in action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Montero, B. (2010). Does bodily awareness interfere with highly skilled movement? Inquiry, 53(2), 105–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moors, A., & De Houwer, J. (2006). Automaticity: A theoretical and conceptual analysis. Psychological Bulletin, 132(2), 297–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagengast, A. J., Braun, D. A., & Wolpert, D. M. (2009). Optimal control predicts human performance on objects with internal degrees of freedom. PLoS Computational Biology, 5(6), e1000419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neumann, O. (1984). Automatic processing: A review of recent findings and a plea for an old theory. In W. Prinz & F. Sanders (Eds.), Cognition and motor processes (pp. 255–293). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Norman, D. A., & Shallice, T. (1986). Attention to action: Willed and automatic control of behaviour. In R. J. Davidson, G. E. Schwartz, & D. Shapiro (Eds.), Consciousness and self-regulation (Vol. 4, pp. 1–18). New York: Plenum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson, M. A., & Fazio, R. H. (2004). Trait inferences as a function of automatically-activated racial attitudes and motivation to control prejudiced reactions. Basic and Applied Social Psychology, 26, 1–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palmeri, T. J. (2002). Automaticity. In L. Nadel, et al. (Eds.), Encyclopedia of cognitive science (pp. 390–401). London: Nature Publishing Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2013). In the Zone. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 73, 175–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Posner, M. I., & Snyder, C. R. R. (1975a). Attention and cognitive control. In R. L. Solso (Ed.), Information processing and cognition: The Loyola symposium (pp. 153–175). Hillsdale: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner, M. I., & Snyder, C. R. R. (1975b). Facilitation and inhibition in the processing of signals. In P. M. A. Rabbit & S. Dornic (Eds.), Attention and performance V (pp. 669–682). Waltham: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2006). Beyond appearances : The content of sensation and perception. In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience (pp. 434–460). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. W. (2000). Is vision continuous with cognition? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22(3), 341–365.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (2003). Seeing and visualizing. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reber, A., & Lewis, S. (1977). Implicit learning: An analysis of the form and structure of a body of tacit knowledge. Cognition, 5, 333–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reed, N., McLeod, P., & Dienes, Z. (2010). Implicit knowledge and motor skill: What people who know how to catch don’t know. Consciousness and Cognition, 19, 63–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenbloom, P. S., & Newell, A. (1986). The chunking of goal hierarchies: A generalized model of practice. In R. S. Michaliski, J. G. Carbonell, & T. M. Mitchell (Eds.), Machine learning: An artificial intelligence approach (Vol. 2, pp. 247–288). Los Altos, CA: Morgan Kaufmann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saling, L., & Philips, J. G. (2007). Automatic behavior: Efficient not mindless. Brain Research Bulletin, 73, 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scholz, J. P., & Schoner, G. (1999). The uncontrolled manifold concept: Identifying control variables for a functional task. Experimental Brain Research, 126, 289–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schneider, W., & Chein, J. (2003). Controlled & automatic processing: Behavior, theory, and biological mechanisms. Cognitive Science, 27, 525–559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schneider, W., & Shiffrin, R. M. (1977). Controlled and automatic human information processing. I. Detection, search, and attention. Psychological Review, 84(1), 1–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schneider, W., Dumais, S. T., & Shiffrin, R. (1984). Automatic and control processing and attention. In R. S. Parasuraman & D. R. Davies (Eds.), Varieties of attention (pp. 1–27). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shiffrin, R. M., & Schneider, W. (1977). Controlled and automatic human information processing: II. Perceptual learning, automatic attending and a general theory. Psychological Review, 84(2), 127–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shiffrin, R. M. (1988). Attention. In R. C. Atkinson, R. J. Hernstein, G. Lindzey, & R. D. Luce (Eds.), Stevens’ handbook of experimental psychology (Vol. 2, pp. 739–811). Hoboken: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2010). The contents of visual experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2011). Know how. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone, M. (2012). Kinesthetic memory: Further critical reflections and constructive analyses. In S. C. Koch, T. Fuchs, M. Summa, & C. Müller (Eds.), Body, metaphor, memory and movement (pp. 43–72). Amsterdam: John Benhamins Publishing.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stokes, D. (2013). Cognitive penetrability of perception. Philosophy Compass, 8(7), 646–663.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J. (2007). Batting, habit and memory: The embodied mind and the nature of skill. Sport in Society, 10(5), 763–786.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J., McIlwain, D., Christensen, W., & Geeves, A. (2011). Applying intelligence to the reflexes: Embodied skills and habits between Dreyfus and Descartes. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology, 42(1), 78–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, J. A., Krakauer, J. W., & Ivry, R. B. (2014). Explicit and implicit contributions to learning in a sensorimotor adaptation task. Journal of Neuroscience, 34, 3023–3032.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Todorov, E. (2004). Optimality principles in sensorimotor control. Nature Neuroscience, 7(9), 907–915.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Todorov, E., & Jordan, M. I. (2002). Optimal feedback control as a theory of motor coordination. Nature Neuroscience, 5(11), 1226–1235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tzelgov, J. (1997a). Specifying the relations between automaticity and consciousness: A theoretical note. Consciousness and Cognition, 6, 441–451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tzelgov, J. (1997b). Automatic but conscious: That is how we act most of the time. In R. S. Wyer Jr (Ed.), Advances in social cognition (Vol. 10, pp. 217–230). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tzelgov, J. (1999). Automaticity and processing without awareness. Psyche, 5(3), 18–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tzelgov, J., Ganor, D., & Yehene, V. (1999). Automatic processing results in conscious representations. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22(5), 786–787.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tzelgov, J., Henik, A., & Porat, Z. (1997). Automaticity and consciousness: Is perceiving the word necessary for reading it? American Journal of Psychology, 3, 429–448.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wallis, C. (2008). Consciousness, context and know-how. Synthese, 160, 123–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wu, W. (2011). Confronting many-many problems: Attention and agentive control. Noûs, 45(1), 50–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wu, W. (2013a). Mental action and the threat of automaticity. In A. Clark, J. Kiverstein, & T. Vierkant (Eds.), Decomposing the will (pp. 244–261). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wu, W. (2013b). Visual spatial constancy and modularity: Does intention penetrate vision? Philosophical Studies, 165(2), 647–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wu, W. (2014). Attention: New problems of philosophy series. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wu, W. (forthcoming). Shaking up the Mind’s ground floor: The cognitive penetration of visual attention.

  • Yarbus, A. (1967). Eye movements and vision. New York: Plenum Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Yarrow, K., Brown, P., & Krakauer, J. W. (2009). Inside the brain of an elite athlete: The neural processes that support high achievement in sports. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 10, 585–596.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank the Naturalistic Approaches to Mind reading Group at King’s College London for numerous helpful comments and suggestions. I would like to thank, especially, David Papineua, Nick Shea, Alexander Clark, Natalie Gold, Matteo Mameli, Karen Neander and Stephen Mann. I would also like to thank Jennifer Corns, David Lowenstein, John Michael, Eliot Michaelson, Micheal Brownstein and Matt Parrott for their thoughtful comments. Lastly, I would like to thank the two anonymous reviewers for their probing and insightful feedback.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ellen Fridland.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Fridland, E. Automatically minded. Synthese 194, 4337–4363 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0617-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0617-9

Keywords

Navigation