Skip to main content
Log in

Are causal facts really explanatorily emergent? Ladyman and Ross on higher-level causal facts and renormalization group explanation

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In their Every Thing Must Go, Ladyman and Ross defend a novel version of Neo-Russellian metaphysics of causation, which falls into three claims: (1) there are no fundamental physical causal facts, (2) there are higher-level causal facts of the special sciences, and (3) higher-level causal facts are explanatorily emergent. While accepting claims (1) and (2), I attack claim (3). Ladyman and Ross argue that higher-level causal facts are explanatorily emergent, because (a) certain aspects of these higher-level facts (their universality) can be captured by renormalization group (RG) explanations, and (b) RG explanations are not reductive explanations. However, I argue that RG explanation should be understood as reductive explanations. This result undermines Ladyman and Ross’s RG-based argument for the explanatory emergence of higher-level causal facts.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Alternative ways of spelling out metaphysical dependence are, for instance, the grounding relation (Schaffer 2009) and weak metaphysical emergence (Wilson 2010).

  2. Two clarifications: first, Kim as well as Ladyman and Ross are unclear about whether a fact is emergent or “resultant” if only some but not all criteria for emergence (and, respectively, for reduction) are met—for instance, if one is able to explain but not predict a phenomenon based on lower-level information. Second, Ladyman and Ross do not address metaphysical emergence, in which, for instance, non-reductive physicalists are interested (Loewer 2009; Wilson 2010).

  3. I assume that Kim’s formulations such as “the coming together of lower-level entities” (criterion 1), “properties and relations that characterize their constituent parts” (criterion 2), “lower-level information” (criterion 3), “basal conditions” (criterion 4), and “basal constituents” (criterion 5) are merely stylistic variations of talk about interactions between the components of a system.

  4. Note that Ladyman and Ross’s arguments for the orthodox Russellian claim are independent of whether RG explanations are reductive explanations (cf. Ladyman and Ross 2007, Sects. 5.1 and 5.3).

  5. Ladyman and Ross (2007, Sect. 1.5) also present arguments against (i) (ontological and epistemic versions of) reductionism as the correct characterization of the way fundamental physics and the special sciences are related, against (ii) a particular mereological account of part-whole relations in fundamental physics, and against (iii) the commitment to the existence of a fundamental level of reality. However, these arguments are beyond the scope of this paper.

  6. I do not discuss whether there is a general model of explanation of scientific explanations that subsumes RG explanations. I think that Woodward’s (2003, pp. 220–221) and Strevens’s (2008, pp. 179–180) notions of counterfactual dependence and difference-making can be extended to cover RG explanations (cf. Reutlinger 2014).

  7. Wilson (2010) provides a detailed discussion of the concept of degrees of freedom.

  8. Shimony (1993, p. 208) discusses RG transformations and their applicability conditions in detail.

  9. Hüttemann and Love (2011, Sect. 3) require that reductive explanation draw on components that are “intrinsic” to the system whose behavior is to be explained. Since the explanandum of an RG explanation concerns macroscopic similarities between two (or more) microscopically different systems, the requirement of intrinsicness has to be amended: the reductive explanation of macroscopic similarities between two microscopically different systems is reductive if it refers to components that are “intrinsic” to the systems (and do not belong to the environments of the two systems).

  10. Thanks to a referee and to Margie Morrison for raising this point.

References

  • Batterman, R. (2000). Multiple realizability and universality. British Journal for Philosophy of Science, 51, 115–145.

  • Batterman, R. (2002). The devil in the details. Asymptotic reasoning in explanation, reduction and emergence. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R. (2010). On the explanatory role of mathematics in empirical science. British Journal for Philosophy of Science, 61, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butterfield, J. (2011). Less is different: Emergence and reduction reconciled. Foundations of Physics, 41, 1065–1135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. (2007). Explaining the brain. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J. (2004). Curie’s principle and spontaneous symmetry breaking. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 18, 173–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farr, M., Reutlinger, A. (2013). A relic of a bygone age? Causation, time symmetry and the directionality argument. Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-013-9510-z.

  • Fisher, M. (1982). Scaling, university and renormalization group theory. In F. Hahne (Ed.), Critical phenomena: Lecture notes in physics (Vol. 186, pp. 1–139). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1997). Special sciences. Still autonomous after all these years. Philosophical Perspectives, 11, 149–163.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franklin-Hall, L. (manuscript). The causal economy account of scientific explanation. unpublished.

  • Frisch, M. (2007). Causation, counterfactuals, and entropy. In H. Price & R. Corry (eds), Causation, physics, and the constitution of reality. Russell’s republic revisited (pp. 351–95). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Hüttemann, A., & Love, A. (2011). Aspects of reductive explanation in biological science: Intrinsicality, fundamentality, and temporality. British Journal for Philosophy of Science, 62, 519–549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hüttemann, A., Reimer K., & Orestis, T. (forthcoming). Stability, emergence and part-whole reduction. In B. Falkenburg & M. Morrison (Eds.), Why more is different philosophical issues in condensed matter physics and complex systems. New York: Springer.

  • Kim, J. (1999). Making sense of emergence. Philosophical Studies, 95, 3–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, James, & Ross, Don. (2007). Every thing must go. Metaphysics naturalized. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. (2007). In H. Price & R. Corry (Eds.), Counterfactuals and the second law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. (2009). Why is there anything except physics? Synthese, 170, 217–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, M. (2012). Emergent physics and micro-ontology. Philosophy of Science, 79, 141–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. (2012). Approximation and Idealization: Why the difference matters. Philosophy of Science, 79, 207–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. (2014). Infinite idealizations. In European Philosophy of Science. Philosophy of Science in Europe and the Viennese Heritage: Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook (Vol. 17, pp. 197–210). Springer: Dordrecht.

  • Price, H., & Corry, R. (Eds.). (2007). Causation, physics, and the constitution of reality. Russell’s republic revisited. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Reutlinger, Alexander. (2013). Can interventionists be neo-Russellians? Interventionism, the open systems argument and the arrow of entropy. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 27(3), 275–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reutlinger, A. (2014a). Why is there universal macro-behavior? Renormalization group explanation as non-causal explanation. Philosophy of Science. http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/677887.

  • Reutlinger, A. (2014b). Explanation beyond causation.

  • Ross, D., & Spurrett, D. (2007). Notions of cause. Russell’s thesis revisited. British Journal for Philosophy of Science, 58(1), 45–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1912/13). On the notion of cause. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 13, 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2009). On what grounds what. In D. Chalmers, M. David, & W. Ryan (Eds.), Metametaphysics. New essays on the foundations of ontology (pp. 347–383). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shimony, A. (1993). Search for a naturalistic world view. Natural science and metaphysics (Vol. II). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2002). Review of Robert W. Batterman: The devil in the details. Philosophy of Science, 69, 654–657.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2003). Bigger than chaos. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2008). Depth. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. (2010). Non-reductive physicalism and degrees of freedom. British Journal for Philosophy of Science, 61, 279–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Woodward, J. (2007). Causation with a human face. In H. Price & R. Corry (Eds.), Causation, physics, and the constitution of reality. Russell’s republic revisited (pp. 66–105). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Woodward, J. (2010). Causation in biology: Stability, specificity, and the choice of levels of explanation. Biology and Philosophy, 25, 287–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Laura Franklin-Hall, Andreas Hüttemann, James Ladyman, Barry Loewer, Margaret Morrison, John Norton, Michael Strevens, Karim Thebault, and Jessica Wilson for helpful discussions. I acknowledge support by the Humboldt Foundation at the MCMP.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alexander Reutlinger.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Reutlinger, A. Are causal facts really explanatorily emergent? Ladyman and Ross on higher-level causal facts and renormalization group explanation. Synthese 194, 2291–2305 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0530-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0530-2

Keywords

Navigation