Skip to main content
Log in

Assessing theories, Bayes style

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The problem addressed in this paper is “the main epistemic problem concerning science”, viz. “the explication of how we compare and evaluate theories [...] in the light of the available evidence” (van Fraassen, BC, 1983, Theory comparison and relevant Evidence. In J. Earman (Ed.), Testing scientific theories (pp. 27–42). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press). Sections 1– 3 contain the general plausibility-informativeness theory of theory assessment. In a nutshell, the message is (1) that there are two values a theory should exhibit: truth and informativeness—measured respectively by a truth indicator and a strength indicator; (2) that these two values are conflicting in the sense that the former is a decreasing and the latter an increasing function of the logical strength of the theory to be assessed; and (3) that in assessing a given theory by the available data one should weigh between these two conflicting aspects in such a way that any surplus in informativeness succeeds, if the shortfall in plausibility is small enough. Particular accounts of this general theory arise by inserting particular strength indicators and truth indicators. In Section 4 the theory is spelt out for the Bayesian paradigm of subjective probabilities. It is then compared to incremental Bayesian confirmation theory. Section 4 closes by asking whether it is likely to be lovely. Section 5 discusses a few problems of confirmation theory in the light of the present approach. In particular, it is briefly indicated how the present account gives rise to a new analysis of Hempel’s conditions of adequacy for any relation of confirmation (Hempel, CG, 1945, Studies in the logic of comfirmation. Mind, 54, 1–26, 97–121.), differing from the one Carnap gave in § 87 of his Logical foundations of probability (1962, Chicago: University of Chicago Press). Section 6 adresses the question of justification any theory of theory assessment has to face: why should one stick to theories given high assessment values rather than to any other theories? The answer given by the Bayesian version of the account presented in section 4 is that one should accept theories given high assessment values, because, in the medium run, theory assessment almost surely takes one to the most informative among all true theories when presented separating data. The concluding section 7 continues the comparison between the present account and incremental Bayesian confirmation theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Bar-Hillel, Y. (1952). Semantic information and its measures. In Transactions of the tenth conference on cybernetics (pp. 33–48). New York: Josiah Macy, Jr. Foundation. (Reprinted in Bar-Hillel (1964), 298-310.)

  • Bar-Hillel, Y. (1955). An examination of information theory. Philosophy of Science, 22, 86–105. (Reprinted in Bar-Hillel (1964), 275–297.)

  • Bar-Hillel Y. (1964). Language and information Selected essays on their theory and application. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley

    Google Scholar 

  • Bar-Hillel Y., & Carnap R. (1953). Semantic information. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 4:147–157

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap R. (1952). The continuum of inductive methods. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap R. (1962). Logical foundations of probability (2nd ed). University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R., & Bar-Hillel, Y. (1952). An outline of a theory of semantic information. Technical Report No. 247 of the Research Laboratory of Electronics, MIT. (Reprinted in Bar-Hillel (1964), 221–274.)

  • Christensen D. (1999). Measuring confirmation. Journal of Philosophy, 96: 437–461

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earman J. (1992). Bayes or bust? A critical examination of Bayesian confirmation theory, MA: MIT Press. Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitelson B. (1999). The plurality of Bayesian measures of confirmation and the problem of measure sensitivity. Philosophy of Science, 66: S362–S378

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitelson B. (2001). Studies in Bayesian confirmation theory. University of Wisconsin-Madison, Madison, WI

    Google Scholar 

  • Flach P. A. (2000). Logical characterisations of inductive learning. In D. M. Gabbay, R. Kruse (Eds.), Abductive reasoning and learning, (pp. 155–196). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaifman H., Snir M. (1982). Probabilities over rich languages, testing, and randomness. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 47: 495–548

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel C.G. (1943). A purely syntactical definition of confirmation. Journal of Symbolic Logic 8: 122–143

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel C.G. (1945). Studies in the logic of confirmation. Mind, 54, 1–26, 97–121. (Reprinted in Hepel(1965), 3–51.)

  • Hempel, C. G. (1960). Inductive inconsistencies. Synthese, 12, 439–469. (Reprinted in Hempel(1965), 53–79.)

  • Hempel, C. G. (1962). Deductive-nomological vs. statistical explanation. In H. Feigl & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (vol. 3., pp. 98–169). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

  • Hempel C.G. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science. The Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel C.G., Oppenheim P. (1945). A definition of “degree of confirmation”. Philosophy of Science 12: 98–115

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G., & Oppenheim, P. (1948). Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science, 15, 135–175. (Reprinted in Hempel(1965), 245–295.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hendricks V.F. (2006). Mainstream and formal epistemology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J., & Pietarinen, J. (1966), Semantic information and inductive logic. In J. Hintikka & P. Suppes (Eds.), Aspects of inductive logic. Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huber, F. (2004). Assessing theories. The problem of a quantitative theory of confirmation. PhD Dissertation. Erfurt: University of Erfurt.

  • Huber F. (2005). What is the point of confirmation?. Philosophy of Science 72: 1146–1159

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huber, F. (2007a). The logic of theory assessment. Journal of Philosophical Logic.

  • Huber, F. (2007b). The plausibility-informativeness theory. In V. F. Hendricks & D. Pritchard (Eds.), New waves in epistemology. Aldershot: Ashgate.

  • Joyce J.M. (1999). The foundations of causal decision theory. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly K.T. (1996). The logic of reliable inquiry. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly K.T. (1999). Iterated belief revision, reliability, and inductive amnesia. Erkenntnis, 50:11–58

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levi I. (1961). Decision theory and confirmation. Journal of Philosophy 58:614–625

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levi I. (1963). Corroboration and rules of acceptance. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 13:307–313

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levi I. (1967). Gambling with truth. An essay on induction and the aims of science. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Levi I. (1986). Probabilistic pettifoggery. Erkenntnis, 25: 133–140

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipton P. (2004). Inference to the best explanation 2nd ed. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Milne P. (2000). Is there a logic of confirmation transfer? Erkenntnis, 53: 309–335

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spohn, W. (1988). Ordinal conditional functions: A dynamic theory of epistemic states. In W. L. Harper & B. Skyrms (Eds.), Causation in decision, belief change, and statistics II (pp. 105–134). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spohn, W. (1990). A general non-probabilistic theory of inductive reasoning. In R. D. Shachter et al. (Eds.), Uncertainty in artificial intelligence 4 (pp. 149–158). Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1983). Theory comparison and relevant Evidence. In J. Earman (Ed.), Testing scientific theories (pp. 27–42). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zwirn D., Zwirn H.P. (1996). Metaconfirmation. Theory and Decision, 41:195–228

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Franz Huber.

Additional information

A precursor of this paper appears as “The Plausibility-Informativeness Theory” in V. F. Hendricks & D. Pritchard (eds.), New Waves in Epistemology. Aldershot: Ashgate, 2007.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Huber, F. Assessing theories, Bayes style. Synthese 161, 89–118 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-006-9141-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-006-9141-x

Keywords

Navigation