Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Assessing Happiness Inequality in the Welfare State: Self-Reported Happiness and the Rawlsian Difference Principle

  • Published:
Social Indicators Research Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The effect of the size of the welfare state on the average happiness level in a nation has often been discussed—but the same effect on happiness inequality has been explored much less. Rooted in divergent philosophical disciplines, utilitarianism and egalitarianism respectively, scholars have discussed the merits of policies as they effect each of these two criteria for justice. John Rawls’ difference principle, on the other hand, philosophically justifies a limited trade-off, increasing happiness inequality to benefit the over-all happiness level of the least advantaged. The difference principle—that society should allow inequality insofar as it is to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged—has seldom been discussed empirically in the context of the happiness literature. This paper contributes to the ongoing literature evaluating the welfare state in light of happiness indicators by introducing the difference principle and asking whether the welfare state benefits the least advantaged in society. My empirical analysis shows that self-reported life satisfaction of the least advantaged does not improve from an increase in the size of the welfare state more than the self-reported life satisfaction of the average citizen. In short, the welfare state does not benefit the worst-off in a society in terms of happiness more than the average member.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There is debate over what Rawls exactly had in mind when considering social primary goods—whether it be access to resources, utility, or capability (Freeman 2002). I do not intend to address this literature here, but rather use happiness as an indicator of social primary goods, which very well applies to most of these perspectives.

  2. As defined in Appendix A of Veenhoven (2005), in which:

    $$ IAH=100-\frac{100}{(1+0.414/\left(\frac{\rm mean}{\rm std.}\right))} $$
  3. Based on the same motivation, these three measures are used in Pacek and Radcliff (2008).

  4. http://so.uconn.edu/~scruggs/wp.htm.

  5. http://www.oecd.org/dataoecd/25/31/34008592.xls.

  6. http://www.lisproject.org/publications/welfaredata/welfareaccess.htm.

  7. It is plausible that when a negative shock in the economy increases the level of unemployment, the size of the Welfare State may increase in response. If the analysis did not control for the level of unemployment the change in happiness that came from the shift in the economy would be attributed to the change in the size of the Welfare State. On the contrary, it is plausible that the size of the Welfare State may affect unemployment levels, and as such affects happiness through unemployment. My estimates would be biased as a result. Removing unemployment from the analysis does not significantly change the results (all coefficients are of the same significants at a similar magnitude), I discuss this limitation in greater detail in the conclusion.

  8. For example, average happiness is on a scale between 0 and 10 with an observed minimum of 3.72 and maximum of 8.49. But IAH is on a scale 0 to 100 and has an observed minimum of 33.20 and maximum 70.95.

  9. For decommodification there are 3.5 standard deviations between the minimum and maximum values, for social wage there are 4.4 standard deviations, and for left-party score there are 4.3 standard deviations. This means if the “least” Welfare State became the “highest,” the increase in each measure of happiness would not be more than 12 %.

References

  • Alvarez-Diaz, A., Gonzalez, L., & Radcliff, B. (2010). The politics of happiness: On the political determinants of quality of life in the American States. The Journal of Politics, 72(3), 894–905.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bringhouse, H., & Unterhalter, E. (2010). Education for primary goods or for capabilities? In H. Bringhouse & I. Robeyns (Eds.), Measuring justice: Primary goods and capabilities. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Daniels, N. (2010). Norman, capabilities, opportunity, and health. In H. Bringhouse & I. Robeyns (Eds.), Measuring justice: Primary goods and capabilities. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Diener, S. E., & Fujita, F. (1996). Events and subjective well-being: Only recent events matter. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 70(5), 1091–1102.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diener, E., & Suh, E. M. (Eds.). (2000). Culture and subjective well-being. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epsing-Andersen, G. (1985). Politics against markets: The social democratic road to power. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epsing-Andersen, G. (1988). Decommodification and work absence in the welfare state. San Domenico, Italy: European University Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, S. (2002). The Cambridge companion to rawls. New York, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frey, B., & Stuzer, A. (2005). Happiness and economics. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hicks, A. (1999). Social democracy and welfare capitalism. Ithica, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kawachi, I., Kennedy, B. P., Lochner, K., & Prothrow-Stith, D. (1997). Social capital, income inequality, and mortality. American Journal of Public Health, 87(9), 1491–1498.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kenworthy, L. (1999). Do Social-Welfare Policies Reduce Poverty? A cross-national assessment. Social Forces, 77(3), 1119–1139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Layard, R. (2005). Happiness: Lessons from a new science. London: Allen Lane.

    Google Scholar 

  • Messner, S. F., & Rosenfeld, R. (1997). Political restraint of the market and levels of criminal homicide: A cross-national application of institutional-anomie theory. Social Forces, 74(4), 1393–1416.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ott, J. (2005). Level and equality of happiness in nations: Does happiness of a greater number imply greater inequality of happiness? Journal of Happiness Studies, Special Issue on Inequality of Happiness in Nations, 6, 397–420.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pacek, A., & Radcliff, B. (2008). Assessing the welfare state: The politics of happiness. Perspectives on Politics, 6, 267–277.

  • Radcliff, B. (2001). Politics, markets, and life satisfaction: The political economy of human happiness. American Political Science Review, 95(4), 939–952.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1999). A theory of justice, revised edition. Cambridge: The Berlknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robeyns, I. (2010). Gender and the metric of justice. In H. Bringhouse & I. Robeyns (Eds.), Measuring justice: Primary goods and capabilities. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Sen, A. (1999). Commodities and capabilities. Oxford University Press.

  • Sen, A. (2010). The place of capability in a theory of justice. In H. Bringhouse & I. Robeyns (Eds.), Measuring justice: Primary goods and capabilities. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Terzi, L. (2010). What metric of justice for disabled people? Capability and disability. In H. Bringhouse & I. Robeyns (Eds.), Measuring justice: Primary goods and capabilities (p. 150). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Veenhoven, R. (1993). Happiness in nations: Subjective appreciation of life in 56 nations 1946–1992. Rotterdam: Erasmus University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Veenhoven, R. (1994). Is happiness a trait? Test of the theory that a better society does not make people any happier. Social Indicators Research, 32, 101–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Veenhoven, R. (1995). The cross-national pattern of happiness: Test of predictions implied in three theories of happiness. Social Indicators Research, 34, 33–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Veenhoven, R. (1996). Happy life-expectancy. A comprehensive measure of quality-of-life in nations. Social Indicators Research, 39, 1–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Veenhoven, R. (2000). Wellbeing in the welfare state: Level not higher, distribution not more equitable. Journal of Comparative Policy Analysis, 2, 91–125.

    Google Scholar 

  • Veenhoven, R. (2005). Inequality of happiness in nations: Introduction to this special issue. Journal of Happiness Studies, 6, 351–355.

    Google Scholar 

  • Veenhoven, R. (2011). Life satisfaction in nations. Sociale Sicherheit, 6, 298–302.

    Google Scholar 

  • Veenhoven, R., & Kalmijin, W. (2005). Inequality-adjusted happiness in nations: Egalitarianism and utilitarianism married in a new index of societal performance. Journal of Happiness Studies, Special Issue on ’Inequality of Happiness in nations’ 6, 421–455.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mitch Gainer.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Gainer, M. Assessing Happiness Inequality in the Welfare State: Self-Reported Happiness and the Rawlsian Difference Principle. Soc Indic Res 114, 453–464 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11205-012-0155-0

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11205-012-0155-0

Keywords

Navigation