Skip to main content
Log in

Taste uncertainty and status quo effects in consumer choice

  • Published:
Journal of Risk and Uncertainty Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We use reference-dependent expected utility theory to develop a model of status quo effects in consumer choice. We hypothesise that, when making their decisions, individuals are uncertain about the utility that will be yielded by their consumption experiences in different ‘taste states’ of the world. If individuals have asymmetric attitudes to gains and losses of utility, the model entails acyclic reference-dependent preferences over consumption bundles. The model explains why status quo effects may vary substantially from one decision context to another and why some such effects may decay as individuals gain market experience.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Sileo (1995) proposes a rather similar hypothesis about the relationship between loss aversion and taste uncertainty, but develops it in a theoretical direction very different from that of the present paper.

  2. In a private communication, Kahneman has confirmed that, in constructing their theory, he and Tversky used (1) as their starting point.

  3. For example: ‘Loss aversion implies that the impact of a difference on a dimension is generally greater when that difference is evaluated as a loss than when the same difference is evaluated as a gain’ (p. 1040). For more on the role of the basic model in TK’s theory, see Munro and Sugden (2003).

  4. KR’s model might be amended by defining a separate gain-loss function μ i (with corresponding parameter γ i ) for each characteristic i. But even with this amendment, the model’s additively separable structure has restrictive implications for exchange aversion. For example, suppose characteristics are identified with goods. Let goods 1 and 2 be very similar brands of chocolate, and goods 3 and 4 be very similar brands of wine. Intuitively, one might expect Q 12 and Q 34 to be close to zero. In the amended model, that would be possible only with \( {\gamma_1} \approx {\gamma_2} \approx {\gamma_3} \approx {\gamma_4} \approx 1 \), which would imply very low exchange aversion between either brand of chocolate and either brand of wine.

  5. In an earlier version of their paper, Kőszegi and Rabin (2004) develop this approach in more detail.

  6. If characteristics are identified with goods, (WTP – WTA)/WTA = γ2 – 1 if trades are anticipated and (WTA – WTP)/WTP = γ2 – 1 if they are unanticipated.

  7. We treat ‘consequences’ as descriptions of subjective experiences, not tied by definition to any particular bundle or state. Thus, a proposition of the form c(x, s h ) = c(y, s g ) indicates that consuming bundle x in state s h leads to the same subjective experience as consuming y in s g .

  8. RDSEUT is not the only theory of reference-dependent choice under uncertainty which allows uncertain reference points. Schmidt et al. (2008) propose a generalisation of RDSEUT which incorporates rank-dependent decision weights. Kőszegi and Rabin (2007) propose a theory that is similar to RDSEUT, but which takes no account of the state-contingent juxtaposition of consequences. This feature of Kőszegi and Rabin’s theory has the paradoxical implication that there can be lotteries x for which x \( \succ \) x | x (Schmidt et al. 2008; De Giorgi and Post 2008).

  9. To guarantee the uniqueness properties of the three functions, some structure has to be imposed on S and C, and preferences have to have appropriate continuity properties. Sugden (2003) proves the representation theorem for the case in which C is the non-negative real line; consequences are interpreted as levels of wealth. Some technical modifications are needed in order for the theorem to apply to the case in which C is the set of possible subjective experiences.

  10. In regret theory, preferences between acts are defined relative to the set of feasible acts that constitutes the choice problem, while in RDSEUT, preferences between acts are defined relative to a fixed reference act. However, the regret-theoretic concept of a preference between x and y, conditional on the feasible set being {x, y, z}, is in important respects isomorphic with the concept of a reference-dependent preference between x and y, conditional on the reference act being z.

  11. In standard consumer theory, preferences are ordinal, and so strict convexity of preferences corresponds with strict quasi-concavity of utility. Because the RDSEUT framework uses cardinal utility, we have to ‘translate’ strict convexity of preferences as strict concavity of utility.

  12. Some such kink is consistent with the observed degrees of loss aversion for very small changes in wealth or consumption (see Rabin 2000). For this reason, prospect theory needs to allow value functions to be kinked at zero (Kahneman and Tversky 1979; Tversky and Kahneman 1992).

  13. Strictly, there is one case in which (7) cannot be derived by rearranging (6). If, for all \( h = 1,\,...,m,{U_h}/{V_h} = {r_{21}}^{\text{WTA}} \), then (6) reduces to 0 = 0. But in this case, (7) is trivially true.

  14. We do not know of any evidence that bears directly on this hypothesis. Georgantzís and Navarro-Martínez (2008) find that, in cross-individual comparisons, WTA/WTP disparities are positively associated with risk aversion; but risk aversion is measured using individuals’ (hypothetical) choices among lotteries which offer gains but not losses.

  15. There would be a circularity if similarity was assessed in terms of consumers’ attitudes to exchanging one good for the other. This problem is avoided by making similarity comparisons in the gain domain.

  16. This suggestion is due to an anonymous referee.

  17. Shogren et al. interpret this as evidence of Hicksian substitution effects, as analysed by Hanemann (1991). However, WTA/WTP disparities of the magnitudes observed (WTA is three to five times higher than WTP, even after repeated market experience) cannot be reconciled with Hicksian theory under plausible assumptions (Sugden 1999; Horowitz and McConnell 2003).

References

  • Becker, G., DeGroot, M., & Marschak, J. (1963). Stochastic models of choice behavior. Behavioral Science, 8, 41–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butler, D., & Loomes, G. (2007). Imprecision as an account of the preference reversal phenomenon. American Economic Review, 97, 277–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Giorgi, E., & Post, T. (2008). Loss aversion with a state-dependent reference point. Working paper, University of Lugano and Erasmus University Rotterdam.

  • Georgantzís, N., & Navarro-Martínez, D. (2008). Understanding the WTA-WTP gap through attitudes, feelings, risk preferences and personality. Paper presented at CREED/ CEDEX/UEA Conference, University of Amsterdam, June 2008.

  • Hanemann, W. M. (1991). Willingness to pay and willingness to accept: how much can they differ? American Economic Review, 81, 635–647.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horowitz, J., & McConnell, K. (2002). A review of WTA/WTP studies. Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 44, 426–447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horowitz, J., & McConnell, K. (2003). Willingness to accept, willingness to pay and the income effect. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organisation, 51, 537–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: an analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47, 263–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Varey, C. (1991). Notes on the psychology of utility. In J. Elster & J. Roemer (Eds.), Interpersonal comparisons of well-being (pp. 127–163). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knetsch, J. (1989). The endowment effect and evidence of nonreversible indifference curves. American Economic Review, 79, 1277–1284.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knetsch, J. L., Tang, F.-F., & Thaler, R. H. (2001). The endowment effect and repeated market trials: is the Vickrey auction demand revealing? Experimental Economics, 4, 257–269.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kőszegi, B., & Rabin, M. (2004). A model of reference-dependent preferences. Working paper E04 337, Institute of Business and Economic Research, University of California at Berkeley.

  • Kőszegi, B., & Rabin, M. (2006). A model of reference-dependent preferences. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 121, 1133–1166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kőszegi, B., & Rabin, M. (2007). Reference-dependent risk attitudes. American Economic Review, 97(4), 1047–1073.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • List, J. A. (2003). Does market experience eliminate market anomalies? Quarterly Journal of Economics, 118(1), 41–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, G., & Sugden, R. (1987). Some implications of a more general form of regret theory. Journal of Economic Theory, 41, 270–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, G., & Sugden, R. (1995). Incorporating a stochastic element into decision theories. European Economic Review, 39, 641–648.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, G., Starmer, C., & Sugden, R. (2003). Do anomalies disappear in repeated markets? Economic Journal, 113, C 153–166.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCrimmon, K., & Smith, M. (1986). Imprecise equivalences: Preference reversals in money and probability. University of British Columbia Working Paper #1211.

  • Munro, A., & Sugden, R. (2003). On the theory of reference-dependent preferences. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 50, 407–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plott, C. R. (1996). Rational individual behaviour in markets and social choice processes: The discovered preference hypothesis. In K. J. Arrow, E. Colombatto, M. Perlman & C. Schmidt (Eds.), The rational foundations of economic behaviour (pp. 225–250). Basingstoke: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plott, C. R., & Zeiler, K. (2005). The willingness to pay—willingness to accept gap, the ‘endowment effect’, subject misconceptions, and experimental procedures for eliciting valuations. American Economic Review, 95, 530–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rabin, M. (2000). Risk aversion and expected-utility theory: a calibration theorem. Econometrica, 68, 1281–1292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savage, L. (1954). The foundations of statistics. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, U., Starmer, C., & Sugden, R. (2008). Third-generation prospect theory. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 36, 203–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shogren, J., Shin, S. Y., Hayes, D., & Kliebenstein, J. B. (1994). Resolving differences in willingness to pay and willingness to accept. American Economic Review, 84, 255–270.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sileo, P. (1995). Intransitivity of indifference, strong monotonicity and the endowment effect. Journal of Economic Theory, 66, 198–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (1993). An axiomatic foundation for regret theory. Journal of Economic Theory, 60, 159–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (1999). Alternatives to the neoclassical theory of choice. In I. Bateman & K. Willis (Eds.), Valuing environmental preferences: Theory and practice of the contingent valuation method in the US, EC and developing countries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2003). Reference-dependent subjective expected utility. Journal of Economic Theory, 111, 172–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1991). Loss aversion in riskless choice: a reference-dependent model. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 106, 1039–1061.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1992). Advances in prospect theory: cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5, 297–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This research was carried out as part of the Programme in Environmental Decision Making, organised through the Centre for Social and Economic Research on the Global Environment, and supported by the Economic and Social Research Council of the UK (award nos. M 535 25 5117 and RES 051 27 0146). We thank Andrea Isoni, Peter Wakker and an anonymous referee for comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Robert Sugden.

Appendix: Proofs

Appendix: Proofs

1.1 Proof of Result 1

Suppose that, for all states s h , u h (.) is continuous, strictly increasing and strictly concave. It is straightforward to show that these assumptions imply that v(x, z) is continuous in x and z, strictly increasing in x, strictly decreasing in z, and strictly concave in x, thus satisfying Well-Behavedness. We now prove that Acyclicity is satisfied.

We define a function w(.) in the following way: for all bundles \( x,w(x) = \sum\nolimits_h {\pi \left( {s_h} \right){u_h}(x)} \). Thus w(x) can be interpreted as the expected value of the subjective experience of consuming x. Notice that this value is independent of the reference point. Thus, w(.) determines a reference-independent ordering of bundles.

We fix a parameter r such that r > 0 and, for all real numbers q, rq ≥ φ(q). Since φ(0) = 0 and φ(.) is weakly concave, such a parameter must exist. (If φ(.) is differentiable, r must equal φ′(0).) Hence, for all bundles x and z, \( v\left( {x,z} \right) = \sum\nolimits_h {\pi \left( {s_h} \right)\varphi \left[ {{u_h}(x) - {u_h}(z)} \right]} \leqslant r\sum\nolimits_h {\pi \left( {s_h} \right)\left[ {{u_h}(x) - {u_h}(z)} \right] = r\left[ {w(x) - w(z)} \right]} \). Thus, v(x, z) ≥ 0 implies w(x) ≥ w(z), and v(x, z) > 0 implies w(x) > w(z). However, \( v\left( {x,z} \right) \succ 0 \Leftrightarrow x \geqslant z\left| z \right. \), and \( v\left( {x,z} \right) > 0 \Leftrightarrow x > z\left| z \right. \). Thus, xz | z implies w(x) ≥ w(z), and xz | z implies w(x) > w(z). So, if the move from z to x is weakly choosable, x is ranked at least as highly as z in the reference-independent ordering defined by w(.), while if the move is strictly choosable, x is ranked above z. It follows immediately from this result that Acyclicity is satisfied.

1.2 Proof of Result 3

Let \( U = \left( {{U_{1}},\,...,{U_m}} \right) \) and V = (V 1 , ..., V m ) be vectors of state-conditional marginal utilities for goods 1 and 2 respectively, such that \( {U_1}/{V_1} \geqslant {U_2}/{V_2} \geqslant ... \geqslant {U_m}/{V_m} \). Units of the two goods are normalised so that \( \sum\nolimits_h {\pi \left( {s_h} \right){U_h}} = \sum\nolimits_h {\pi \left( {s_h} \right){V_h} = 1} \). Let \( U\prime = \left( {U{\prime_1},\,...,U{\prime_m}} \right) \) be an alternative vector for good 1, such that the switch from U to U′ is a mean-preserving disalignment of u(.) with respect to v(.). Let z be any bundle, and let x be the bundle which differs from z by containing one less marginal unit of good 1 and q additional units of good 2. Set the value of q so that, when marginal utilities are given by U and V, x ~ z | z (i.e. q = r WTA21 ). For each state h = 1, ..., m, we define \( {A_h} = { \max }\left[ {\pi \left( {s_h} \right)\left( {{U_h} - {V_h}q} \right),\,0} \right] \), \( {B_h} = { \max }\left[ {\pi \left( {s_h} \right)\left( {{V_h}q - {U_h}} \right),\,0} \right] \), \( A{\prime_h} = { \max }\left[ {\pi \left( {s_h} \right)(U{\prime_h} - {V_h}q),\,0} \right] \), and \( B{\prime_h} = { \max }\left[ {\pi \left( {s_h} \right)\left( {{V_h}q - U\prime h} \right),\,0} \right] \). Notice that because of our normalisations, and because of the definition of ‘mean-preserving disalignment’, \( \sum\nolimits_h {\left( {{B_h} - {A_{h}}} \right)} = \sum\nolimits_h {\left( {B{\prime_h} - A{\prime_{h}}} \right) = q - 1} \). (In terms of the notation in Fig. 1, the areas A and B are equal to \( \sum\nolimits_h {A_h} \,{\text{and}}\,\sum\nolimits_h {B_h} \) respectively.)

Because states are indexed in descending order of U h /V h , we can define an integer K such that, for each \( h = 1,\,...K,{U_h}/{V_h} \geqslant q \), while for each \( h = K + 1,\,...,m,{U_h}/{V_h} < q \). Since x ~ z | z, there must be at least one state in which U h /V h q; thus 1 < Km. It follows from the definitions of \( {A_{h}} \) and B h that for each h = 1, ..., K, A h ≥ 0 and B h = 0, while for each \( h = K + 1,\,...,m,{A_h} = 0\,{\text{and}}\,{B_h} > 0 \). (In terms of Fig. 1, in which K = 3, the whole of area A lies to the left of the cumulative probability of states 1 to 3, while the whole of area B lies to the right.) It follows from the definition of ‘mean-preserving disalignment’ that \( \sum\nolimits_{h = 1} {^K\pi \left( {s_h} \right)(U{\prime_{h}} - {U_h}) > 0} \). But, for all h, \( \pi \left( {s_h} \right)\left( {U{\prime_{h}} - {V_h}q} \right) \equiv \left( {A{\prime_h} - B{\prime_h}} \right) - \left( {{A_h} - {B_h}} \right) \). For all h = 1, ..., K, B h = 0 (see above) and B′ h ≥ 0 (by definition). Thus, we have \( \sum\nolimits_{h = 1} {^K} \left( {A{\prime_h} - {A_h}} \right) > 0 \). For all \( h = K + 1,\,...,m,{A_h} = 0 \) (see above) and A′ h 0 (by definition). Thus, \( \sum\nolimits_{h} {\left( {A{\prime_h} - {A_h}} \right) > 0} \). Recall that \( \sum\nolimits_{h} {\left( {A{\prime_h} - {A_h}} \right)} = \sum\nolimits_{h} {\left( {B{\prime_h} - {B_h}} \right)} \). So the expected value of utility loss in states in which z gives weakly more utility than x (and, equivalently, the expected value of utility gain in states in which z gives strictly less than x) is greater in absolute value when marginal utilities are given by U′ than when they are given by U. Thus if β > 1, the change from U to U′ implies a change in preference from x ~ z | z to zx | z. To restore indifference, there must be an increase in q. Thus, the change induces an increase in r WTA21 .

A symmetrical argument shows that (with β > 1) the same change in marginal utilities induces an increase in r WTA12 . Thus, it induces an increase in Q 21.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Loomes, G., Orr, S. & Sugden, R. Taste uncertainty and status quo effects in consumer choice. J Risk Uncertain 39, 113–135 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-009-9076-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-009-9076-y

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation