Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

A dilemma for Epicureanism

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Perhaps death’s badness is an illusion. Epicureans think so and argue that agents cannot be harmed by death when they’re alive (because death hasn’t happened yet) nor when they’re dead (because they do not exist by the time death comes). I argue that each version of Epicureanism faces a fatal dilemma: it is either committed to a demonstrably false view about the relationship between self-regarding reasons and well-being or it is involved in a merely verbal dispute with deprivationism. I first provide principled reason to think that any viable view about the badness of death must allow that agents have self-regarding reason to avoid (or seek) death if doing so would increase their total well-being. I then show that Epicurean views which do not preserve this link are subject to reductio arguments and so should be rejected. After that, I show that the Epicurean views which accommodate this desideratum are involved in a merely verbal dispute with deprivationism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This view and argument originates with Epicurus and was rigorously defended by Lucretius in his epic poem De Rerum Natura. I take all contemporary Epicureans to endorse this argument in one form or another.

  2. For the purposes of this paper, this phrasing should be understood as the equivalent of “Deprivationism is involved in a merely verbal dispute with Epicurean views developed to accommodate such claims.” In arguing that one view is involved in a merely verbal dispute with another view, I am not claiming that one view is getting something correct in some way that the other view is not. Rather, I am merely claiming that proponents of the views appear to disagree about some subject matter, but that the appearance of disagreement is illusory. In sections three and four, I address the question of whether Epicureans or deprivationists are getting something right in a way their supposed opponents are getting wrong. Those claims, however, are logically independent of my argument that Epicureanism and deprivationism are involved in a merely verbal dispute about the central issues over which they purportedly disagree.

  3. I am using the term ‘self-regarding reasons’ in a stipulative sense. Self-regarding reasons are the genuinely normative reasons one has to act in light of considerations about one’s well-being. Self-regarding reasons may just be prudential reasons, but without the conceptual baggage. It is sometimes assumed, if only implicitly, that prudential reasons concern only what is good for and bad for persons. But, given Epicureans’ and deprivationists’ divergent uses of terms such as good for and bad for, no such assumption should be made.

  4. Comparativism can be formulated as follows: For any person S and event E, E is extrinsically bad (good) for S if and only if, and to the extent that, S’s total net receipt of intrinsic goods over intrinsic evils would have been greater (or smaller) if E had not occurred. See Ekendahl and Johansson (2016: 40). For other formulations of comparativism, see Feldman (1992), Feit (2002), Johansson (2005), and Luper (2009: 86–87). Many deprivationists accept comparativism, while Epicureans often deny it. According to Ekendahl and Johansson, to avoid absurdity, Epicureans should accept that death can reduce a person’s net receipt of intrinsic goods, but deny that such a death would be extrinsically bad (2016: 40–41). Severing the connection between extrinsic goods and the receipt of intrinsic goods seems no more plausible to me than denying that death can reduce a person’s net receipt of intrinsic goods. At any rate, PL and PD are weaker than comparativism and consistent with either accepting or rejecting it.

  5. For more on narrative structure, see Jones (2012). These principles also allow for other potentially relevant considerations, such as one’s reasonable attachment to the actual Harman (2011), fission cases Parfit (1984: §90), considerations of autonomy, and any other potentially relevant features.

  6. In certain cases, death may benefit a person, yet be part of a larger series of events that collectively harm a person. PD entails that this person has some self-regarding reason to seek death, but still allows that the individual has most reason, all things considered, to prevent the collective harm, which requires avoiding death. For more on plural harm and death, see Feit (2015, 2016).

  7. In his (1970), Nagel argues that the badness of death is determined by how one’s life could have gone, not would have gone. However, every subsequent form of deprivationism is formulated in terms of how one’s life would have gone had the person’s actual death not occurred.

  8. See, for instance, Brueckner and Fischer (1986), Feldman (1992), Luper (2009), and Bradley (2009). Note also that Bradley’s view is contextualist, so the nearest possible world is picked out relative to similarity relation R, which is determined by context.

  9. See also Draper (2004), Hetherington (2013), Olson (2013), and Suits (2001). I do not discuss ancient Epicureans, such as Lucretius or Epicurus, since historical interpretations of their work are contentious and because I do not need to take a stand on the correct interpretation of their positions for the purposes of my argument. That being noted, I am inclined to interpret Lucretius and Epicurus as attempting to assuage worries that death is intrinsically bad. Consequently, ancient Epicureanism can be seen as consistent with deprivationism without succumbing to anachronism. But whatever the correct historical interpretation, Epicurus’ and Lucretius’ version of Epicureanism is still subject to my dilemma. For a compelling historical interpretation of ancient Epicureanism, see Warren (2001).

  10. Hershenov (2007: 176).

  11. Hershenov appears to assume that accepting the deprivation account of the badness of death requires assuming that the deceased have well-being levels of 0 (2007: 177). But, as was later shown in the literature, this isn’t the case. See Bradley (2009: 98–105) and Purves (2016).

  12. Smuts (2012: 211–213).

  13. Taylor (2012: 44) Taylor’s distinction between harms to and harms for persons is a bit under-described. As I understand him, harms for persons can affect a person’s total well-being (i.e. the net total non-instrumental good accrued in one’s lifetime), but cannot affect a person’s momentary well-being (i.e. the net non-instrumental good possessed at any moment in time). I take this to be the charitable interpretation of Taylor. If, contrary to my interpretation, Taylor suggests that harms for persons cannot even affect one’s total well-being, then Taylor would either be committed to holding that (i) death can be a harm to persons, thereby giving up his Epicureanism or holding that (ii) death can never affect one’s total well-being. I find (ii) wildly implausible and presume Taylor would not want to accept (i). See chapter five of Taylor (2012) for an extended discussion of this distinction.

  14. Rosenbaum (1986: 218).

  15. More precisely, Rosenbaum writes that death “is roughly the time at which a person becomes dead…Several facts should be noted about death, in this sense. It is not clearly a part of a person's lifetime, although it may be a (very) small part. Also, it is not clear that it takes time or, if so, how much time it takes. It may be a mere moment in time separating being alive from being dead.” Rosenbaum (1986: 217–218).

  16. Green (1982: 100).

  17. Green might actually understand any event that impedes normal functioning to be an objective evil regardless of how the event affects a person’s total well-being. If so, then Green’s view can be precisified to either accommodate or reject ED. If it is precisified to be incompatible with ED, it should be rejected. If it is precisified to accommodate ED, then as I argue in the next section, Green will be involved in a merely verbal dispute with deprivationism.

  18. More broadly, (i) should be read to encompass any closely related evaluative claims about death (e.g. Death can be good for a person). For ease of the dialectic, however, I will focus on the question of whether death can be bad for a person.

  19. This is drawn from Jenkins (2014: 16).

  20. As Jenkins (2014: 21) uses the term, a prima face dispute is anything that, at first glance, has the appearance of a real dispute.

  21. Jenkins (2014: 20).

  22. In addition to Jenkins (2014), see Hirsch (2005), Bennett (2009) and Chalmers (2011).

  23. Epicureans usually argue that death is not to be feared. Some deprivationists have argued that fear is a fitting attitude, while others deny this. See Scheffler (2013: 87) and Draper (1999). To be clear, Epicureans and deprivationists can consistently accept or reject the claim that people should fear deaths that are bad forD them. So, debates about fitting attitudes toward death cut across debates about the badness of death. See Bradley (2015) and Timmerman (2016) for recent deprivationist discussions of fitting attitudes toward death.

  24. Jenkins (2014: 21).

  25. Again, they may still disagree about which of the specific senses of bad for, harm, and so on are the correct senses of these terms. That could be a substantive dispute, but that is a substantive dispute over an issue that cuts across the prima facie dispute over D.

  26. See Ben Bradley’s (2012) for a more detailed discussion of this issue.

References

  • Bennett, K. (2009). Composition, colocation, and metaontology. In D. Chalmers, D. Manley, & R. Wasserman (Eds.), Metametaphysics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, B. (2009). Well-being and death. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, B. (2012). Doing away with harm. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85(2), 390–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, B. (2015). How should we feel about death? Philosophical Papers, 44(1), 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brueckner, A., & Fischer, J. M. (1986). Why is death bad? Philosophical Studies, 50(2), 213–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2011). Verbal disputes. The Philosophical Review, 120(4), 515–556.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Draper, K. (1999). Disappointment, sadness, and death. The Philosophical Review, 108(3), 387–414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Draper, K. (2004). Epicurean equanimity towards death. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 69(1), 92–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ekendahl, K., & Johansson, J. (2016). Epicureanism, extrinsic badness and prudence. In M. Cholbi (Ed.), Immortality and the philosophy of death. Rowman and Littlefield: Lanham.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feit, N. (2002). The time of death’s misfortune. Noûs, 36(3), 359–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feit, N. (2015). Plural harm. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 90(2), 361–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feit, N. (2016). Comparative harm, creation and death. Utilitas, 2, 1–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, F. (1992). Confrontations with the reaper. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, O. H. (1982). Fear of death. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 43(1), 99–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, E. (2011). Fischer and lamenting non-existence. Social Theory and Practice, 37(1), 129–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hershenov, D. (2007). A more palatable Epicureanism. American Philosophical Quarterly, 44(2), 171–180.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (2013). Where is the harm in dying prematurely? An Epicurean answer. Journal of Ethics, 17(1–2), 79–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hirsch, E. (2005). Physical-object ontology, verbal disputes, and common sense. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 70(1), 99–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jenkins, C. (2014). Merely verbal disputes. Erkenntnis, 79(1), 11–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johansson, J. (2005). Mortal beings. Stockholm: Almqvist & Wiksell International.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, W. (2012). The art of dying. Philosophical Papers, 41(3), 435–454.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lucretius. (2001/50 B.C.E.). On the nature of things. Trans. Martin Ferguson Smith. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

  • Luper, S. (2009). The philosophy of death. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1970). Death. Noûs, 4(1), 73–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olson, E. (2013). The Epicurean view of death. The Journal of Ethics, 17(1–2), 65–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and persons. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Purves, D. (2016). Accounting for the harm of death. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 97(1), 89–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenbaum, S. (1986). How to be dead and not care: A defense of Epicurus. American Philosophical Quarterly, 23(2), 217–225.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler, S. (2013). Death and the after life. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smuts, A. (2012). Less good but not bad: In defense of Epicureanism about death. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 93(2), 197–227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suits, D. (2001). Why death is not bad for the one who died. American Philosophical Quarterly, 38(1), 69–84.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, J. S. (2012). Death, posthumous harm, and bioethics. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Timmerman, T. (2016). Your death might be the worst thing to ever happen to you (but maybe you shouldn’t care). Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 46(1), 18–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warren, J. (2001). Lucretius, symmetry arguments, and fearing death. Phronesis, 46(4), 466–491.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

For helpful feedback on earlier versions of this paper, I am very grateful to Per Algander, Gregory Antill, Sophie Ban, Kurt Blankschaen, Ben Bradley, Erik Carlson, Jason Chen, Yishai Cohen, Mark Couch, Kirsten Egerstrom, Karl Ekendahl, Neil Feit, Daniel Fogal, David Hershenov, Jens Johansson, Robert Kelly, Vicente Medina, David O’Connor, Steve Kershnar, David Limbaugh, Hille Paakkunainen, Michael Rabenberg, Stewart Shapiro, Nate Sharadin, David Sobel, Rhys Southan, Steve Steward, James Stacey Taylor, Yvonne Unna, Rodrigo Valencia, Jeff Watson, the anonymous referees at this journal, and audiences at the University at Buffalo, Stockholm University, the National Autonomous University of Mexico, the University of Tampa, and the 2015 Pacific American Philosophical Association meeting.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Travis Timmerman.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Timmerman, T. A dilemma for Epicureanism. Philos Stud 176, 241–257 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-1014-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-1014-2

Keywords

Navigation