Skip to main content
Log in

Moral uncertainty and fetishistic motivation

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Sometimes it’s not certain which of several mutually exclusive moral views is correct. Like almost everyone, I think that there’s some sense in which what one should do depends on which of these theories is correct, plus the way the world is non-morally. But I also think there’s an important sense in which what one should do depends upon the probabilities of each of these views being correct. Call this second claim “moral uncertaintism”. In this paper, I want to address an argument against moral uncertaintism offered in the pages of this journal by Brian Weatherson, and seconded elsewhere by Brian Hedden, the crucial premises of which are: (1) that acting on moral uncertaintist norms necessarily involves motivation by reasons or rightness as such, and (2) that such motivation is bad. I will argue that (1) and (2) are false, and that at any rate, the quality of an agent’s motivation is not pertinent to the truth or falsity of moral uncertaintism in the way that Weatherson’s and Hedden’s arguments require.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The useful locution “It’s not certain” (as opposed to “S is not certain”) expresses a claim about epistemic probabilities—specifically, the claim that no spoken-of proposition has an epistemic probability of 1. Statements about epistemic probabilities express, rather than report, credences, and as such epistemic probabilities may well diverge from credences. Meta-semantic views about epistemic probability statements are a big deal in the philosophy of language (Yalcin 2007; Moss 2013), but this work is just starting to penetrate the ethical literature on action under uncertainty. In my opinion, someone sympathetic to the view I defend in this paper avoids several pitfalls by focusing on epistemic probabilities of moral propositions, rather than subjective or objective probabilities thereof. I argue for this in Sepielli 2012 and 2014a. At any rate, the reader of this paper should understand “probabilities” and “chances” as referring to epistemic probabilities; by implication, the reader should not make the mistake of understanding such talk as referring to the agent’s own credences.

  2. I also think that that what we should do depends on the probabilities of various non-moral propropositions being true. In so saying, I’m using another, probably more familiar, “subjective” sense of “should”. To be clear: I am not simply defining the various senses of “should” here, but rather making stronger claims about how, as a matter of substantive moral theory, these senses apply.

  3. It is only fair to mention that this insistence on “guidance” in the face of uncertainty introduces the threat of a regress. This is noted in passing in Sepielli 2012 and in Weatherson (2014). I sketch a solution to this regress problem in Sepielli 2014b and (ms).

  4. Harman argues that moral ignorance (of which moral uncertainty is one variety) does not exculpate, and so there is no important sense in which what I ought to depends on the probabilities of moral propositions. My reply to Harman may be found in Sepielli (ms).

  5. Terminating a pregnancy is probably not the best example of something that might be wrong to do but is certainly permissible not to do; after all, there are plausible arguments that carrying a pregnancy to term is the riskier option. See, e.g., Harman (1999).

  6. Weatherson uses “rational” rather than “subjectively prudent”. Since “rational” is used by different philosophers in different ways, I prefer to stick with the neologism. Nothing of significance rides on this choice, though.

  7. Similarly, someone who executes a material inference does not employ as premises the claims that would transform her inference into a formally valid one. But she is rationally committed to them all the same.

  8. One might similarly ask, “Would Martha drive all the way to the grocery store if she doesn’t believe it’s open?”, which may well elicit a negative answer. But if we fill in the story a bit more, and say that she nonetheless has some credence that the store is open, her driving there is perfectly intelligible.

  9. In any case, the claim that one cannot be motivated by F unless one values F simpliciter does not entail that no one uncertain about the value of F can be motivated by it. For one can value F simpliciter while being uncertain about just how valuable it is relative to other features. And indeed, many cases of moral uncertainty are of just this type -- e.g. a medical review board is uncertain of how considerations of patient autonomy trade off against considerations of patient well-being. It is not clear from Weatherson's paper why an uncertaintist agent in such a case could not be correctly described as motivated by autonomy and well-being, rather than by the prospect of rightness. Thanks to a referee for this suggestion.

  10. The contrast at work here is between the second-personal notion of “wronging” someone and the third-personal notion of “doing wrong”. See, e.g., Darwall (2006).

  11. Thanks to a referee for help here.

  12. (Weatherson’s focus on certain class of uncertaintist norms (i.e. those enjoining moral recklessness) may lead some readers to think that other uncertaintist norms (e.g. those prescribing action in cases where there is no morally “safe” option) are beyond the reach of his argument. But it is a mistake to think this. His argument applies to all uncertaintist norms that we can use to guide action. As such, if his motivational arguemnt were correct, the only alternative to fetishism would be what I’ve called a “leap of faith”.

  13. I owe this astute point to an anonymous referee.

  14. I argue for this in Sepielli 2010; in doing so, I draw on arguments in Good (1967) and Skyrms (1990, chapter 3).

References

  • Darwall, S. L. (2006). The second-person standpoint: Morality, respect, and accountability. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Good, I. J. (1967). On the principle of total evidence. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 17(4), 319–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gracely, E. J. (1996). On the noncomparability of judgments made by different ethical theories. Metaphilosophy, 27(3), 327–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gustafsson, J. E., & Torpman, O. (2014). In defence of my favourite theory. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 95(2), 159–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, E. (1999). Creation ethics: The moral status of early fetuses and the ethics of abortion. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 28(4), 310–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, E. (2015). The irrelevance of moral uncertainty. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics (Vol. X). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hedden, B. (2015). Does MITE make right: On decision-making under normative uncertainty. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics (Vol. XI). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hudson, J. L. (1989). Subjectivization in ethics. American Philosophical Quarterly, 26(3), 221–229.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonsen, A., & Toulmin, S. (1988). The abuse of casuistry. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moss, S. (2013). Epistemology formalized. Philosophical Review, 122(1), 1–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, T. (2015) Desire. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/desire/. Accessed September 18, 2015.

  • Sepielli, A. (2010). ‘Along an imperfectly-lighted path’: Practical rationality and normative uncertainty. New Brunswick: Ph.D. Dissertation. Rutgers University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sepielli, A. (2012). Subjective normativity and action guidance. In M. Timmons (Ed.), Oxford studies in normative ethics (Vol. II). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sepielli, A. (2014a). What to do when you don’t know what to do when you don’t know what to do…. Nous, 48(3), 521–544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sepielli, A. (2014b). Should you look before you leap? The Philosophers’ Magazine, 66, 89–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sepielli, A. (ms). How moral uncertaintism can be both true and interesting.

  • Skyrms, B. (1990). The dynamics of rational deliberation. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (1994). The moral problem. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (2002). Evaluation, uncertainty and motivation. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice: An International Forum, 5(3), 305–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. J. (1990). The realm of rights. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weatherson, B. (2014). Running risks morally. Philosophical Studies, 167(1), 141–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yalcin, S. (2007). Epistemic modals. Mind, 116(464), 983–1026.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

This research was funded by a University of Toronto Connaught Junior Researcher Award.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrew Sepielli.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The researcher declares that he has no conflicts of interest.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sepielli, A. Moral uncertainty and fetishistic motivation. Philos Stud 173, 2951–2968 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0645-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0645-z

Keywords

Navigation