Skip to main content
Log in

A new argument for skepticism

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The traditional argument for skepticism relies on a comparison between a normal subject and a subject in a skeptical scenario: because there is no relevant difference between them, neither has knowledge. Externalists respond by arguing that there is in fact a relevant difference—the normal subject is properly situated in her environment. I argue, however, that there is another sort of comparison available—one between a normal subject and a subject with a belief that is accidentally true—that makes possible a new argument for skepticism. Unlike the traditional form of skeptical argument, this new argument applies equally well to both internalist and externalist theories of knowledge.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. First Meditation; Descartes (1984, p. 14).

  2. Though it falls outside the scope of this paper, I believe that a similar structure can be shown to be at work in the other main arguments in the skeptical tradition, including Descartes’s dreaming argument, the Modes of Pyrrhonism, and the problem of the criterion.

  3. That is, externalists reject epistemic internalism. There are various ways in which internalism has been characterized; for a helpful discussion, see Fumerton (1995, pp. 60–69). One of the most widely shared is Chisholm’s characterization of epistemic justification as “internal and immediate in that one can find out directly, by reflection, what one is justified in believing at any time” (Chisholm 1989, p. 7).

  4. See Goldman (1979) for a statement of basic reliabilism.

  5. Moreover, even if a particular subject does have some awareness of the reliability of her faculties or belief-forming processes, the justification for her beliefs is independent of that awareness.

  6. See Sosa (1991) and Greco (2000) for two of the central defenses of virtue epistemology. See Zagzebski (1996) for a different type of virtue epistemology, grounded in the Aristotelian tradition.

  7. See Nozick (1981). Sosa (1999) defends the requirement of a modal connection between belief and the purportedly known fact in addition to the other elements of his virtue epistemology, though he appears to abandon this requirement in his (2007). See also Williamson (2000). Nozick argues on behalf of sensitivity (if p were not true, one would not believe p), where Sosa and Williamson defend safety (if one were to believe that p, it would be true that p).

  8. This is compatible with a view such as Sosa’s, which takes the awareness of one’s fit in one’s environment to yield a better epistemic status for one’s belief than it would have had in the absence of that awareness. See his distinction between animal and reflective knowledge (2007, p. 24).

  9. For one example of this strategy, see Van Cleve (1979) on epistemic circularity.

  10. This has been one of the primary motivations for contextualism; see Cohen (1988, 1998) and DeRose (1995).

  11. For externalist responses to this problem, see, e.g., Nozick (1981) and Sosa (2007).

  12. See, e.g., Williams (1999) and Feldman (2003). Although Feldman thinks that fallibilism is an adequate response to some forms of skepticism, he does acknowledge that there are skeptical arguments which do not rely on the impossibility of certainty; see p. 128.

  13. See my (Reed 2002) for an account of fallibilism.

  14. Russell (1948, p. 154).

  15. See Edmund Gettier’s classic paper (1963). Though Russell’s brief example was earlier, proper focus on the problematic nature of cases of that sort begins with Gettier.

  16. I should emphasize, however, that neither Gettier nor any of the other philosophers who have proposed similar cases involving accidentally true justified beliefs have suggested a comparison of the sort that I will be making. See my (2007) for a different sort of presentation of the new argument for skepticism; there, I also defend the new argument against some popular anti-skeptical strategies, including contextualism and Moorean common sense.

  17. This and the following case are modifications of one of the two examples in Gettier (1963). I shall use “B” names to refer to subjects in normal situations and “C” names to refer to those whose beliefs are accidentally true.

  18. This and the following case are modifications of an example that appears in Goldman (1976), to whom it was suggested by Carl Ginet.

  19. Hetherington (1999) is an exception. He regards Gettier cases as borderline instances of knowledge. Sosa (2007) agrees that Connor does not have knowledge in Car Possession 2, but he thinks that Cassandra’s belief should count as knowledge in Barn Sighting 2. I shall return to this claim below.

  20. If we like, we can even make the epistemic performance of the C subjects better than that of the B subjects. For example, we could allow Connor’s belief to be grounded in a more extensive range of evidence (including, perhaps, a look at an affidavit signed by Lee stating that he will never sell his car) and Cassandra’s belief to be grounded in a better perceptual experience (e.g., she sees the barn from a closer vantage point and in better light). Still, the beliefs of the C subjects would be accidentally true.

  21. For more on this distinction, see my (Reed 2007).

  22. Nozick (1981, pp. 173–175).

  23. For cases like Barn Sighting 3, see Lackey (2008).

  24. Given this way of thinking of the traditional argument for skepticism, we can see why externalism provides a plausible reply to it. If externalists are correct about what is required for knowledge (and justification or warrant), Betty’s justification is appropriately connected to the truth. She could not have the justification she does unless her beliefs were probably true.

  25. See Riggs (2002) and (Riggs, W., unpublished, "Two problems of easy credit"), Greco (2003, 2007), Sosa (2003, 2007), and Zagzebski (2003).

  26. See Greco (2003).

  27. See Sosa (2007, pp. 79 and 97).

  28. Sosa says that, in a Gettier case, the subject’s competence may be the explanation for why she has the belief in question, but it does not explain why it is true—in other words, the competence accounts for the belief’s existence but not for its correctness (2007, pp. 95–96).

  29. I am grateful to Jennifer Lackey for discussion of this point.

  30. See Lackey (2007) for this argument. See Greco (2007), Sosa (2007), and Riggs (Riggs, W., unpublished, "Two problems of easy credit") for responses to Lackey and Lackey (forthcoming) for her further defense of the argument.

  31. This case is drawn from Lackey (2007). She also there presents cases in which a subject apparently has knowledge but without deserving much credit for it, where the purported knowledge in question is not testimonial.

  32. For example, in the case above, Connor is clearly performing better intellectually than David is. Connor’s disjunctive belief is not only justified, it would count as knowledge if the original disjunct were true. By contrast, David’s belief is not justified, and it would not count as knowledge even if both conjuncts happened to be true.

  33. See Sosa’s discussion of the kaleidoscope believer—a case which is structurally similar to the barn façade case (2007, pp. 31–34, 96 n. 1, 99–101, and 104–109).

  34. Sosa (2007, pp. 23–24). To be precise, Sosa would say that Cassandra’s belief is animal knowledge but not reflective knowledge (pp. 36–37 and 100–109), where reflective knowledge is apt belief aptly noted (p. 32). In what follows, I shall largely ignore the distinction between animal and reflective knowledge, as I shall be objecting to the claim that Cassandra has any sort of knowledge.

  35. One might object here that Cassandra has been given a defeater (counterevidence) for her belief, so her epistemic situation is in fact worse than it was before. But the point can be put in the third-person just as well. An observer who learns that Cassandra has seen only one genuine barn and two barn façades would say that the epistemic basis for her true belief is inadequate. It is not that the belief was well-supported and has since been outweighed by stronger evidence to the contrary. Rather, the epistemic basis for the belief was never good in the first place.

  36. See Plantinga (1993, p. 36), and Williamson (2000).

  37. See Greene and Balmert (1997) and my (2005), respectively.

  38. In the Meno, Plato says that when a subject has knowledge, there is a “tether” for her belief so that it cannot run away.

  39. This is not to say that the subject must deserve credit for the truth of her belief. Rather, the point is merely that the knowledge must be attributable to her, even if someone else is largely responsible for putting the subject in a position to have a true belief. Similarly, an action may be attributable to an agent even in cases where someone else deserves most of the credit for making the action possible—e.g., a ballet instructor may deserve the credit for enabling her pupil to perform a pas de chat, though of course it is the pupil who is actually performing it. For more on attributability, see my (Reed 2007).

  40. For this claim as it relates to freedom of the will, see Frankfurt (1971) and Wolf (1990).

References

  • Chisholm, R. (1989). Theory of knowledge (3rd ed.). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (1988). How to be a fallibilist. Philosophical Perspectives, 2, 91–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (1998). Contextualist solutions to epistemological problems: Skepticism, Gettier, and the Lottery. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 76, 289–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (1995). Solving the skeptical problem. Philosophical Review, 104, 1–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Descartes. (1984). The philosophical writings of Descartes, Vol. II. (J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, & D. Murdoch, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Feldman, R. (2003). Epistemology. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (1971). Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. The Journal of Philosophy, 68, 5–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fumerton, R. (1995). Metaepistemology and skepticism. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gettier, E. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23, 121–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1976). Discrimination and perceptual knowledge. Journal of Philosophy, 73, 771–791.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1979). What is justified belief? In G. Pappas (Ed.), Justification and knowledge (pp. 1–23). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. (2000). Putting skeptics in their place. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. (2003). Knowledge as credit for true belief. In M. DePaul & L. Zagzebski (Eds.), Intellectual virtue: Perspectives from ethics and epistemology (pp. 111–134). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Greco, J. (2007). The nature of ability and the purpose of knowledge. Philosophical Issues, 17, 57–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, R., & Balmert, N. A. (1997). Two notions of warrant and Plantinga’s solution to the Gettier problem. Analysis, 57, 132–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (1999). Knowing failably. The Journal of Philosophy, 96(11), 565–587.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, J. (2007). Why we don’t deserve credit for everything we know. Synthese, 156, 345–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, J. (forthcoming). Knowledge and credit. Philosophical Studies. doi:10.1007/s11098-008-9304-3.

  • Lackey, J. (2008). What luck is not. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 86, 255–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explanations. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1993). Warrant and proper function. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reed, B. (2002). How to think about fallibilism. Philosophical Studies, 107, 143–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reed, B. (2005). Accidentally factive mental states. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 71, 134–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reed, B. (2007). The long road to skepticism. The Journal of Philosophy, 104, 236–262.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riggs, W. (2002). Reliability and the value of knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 64, 79–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1948). Human knowledge: Its scope and limits. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (1991). Knowledge in perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (1999). How must knowledge be related modally to what is known? Philosophical Topics, 26, 373–384.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2003). The place of truth in epistemology. In M. DePaul & L. Zagzebski (Eds.), Intellectual virtue: Perspectives from ethics and epistemology (pp. 155–179). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Sosa, E. (2007). Virtue epistemology: Apt belief and reflective knowledge (Vol. I). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Cleve, J. (1979). Foundationalism, epistemic principles, and the cartesian circle. Philosophical Review, 88, 55–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, M. (1999). Skepticism. In J. Greco & E. Sosa (Eds.), The Blackwell guide to epistemology (pp. 35–69). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, S. (1990). Freedom within reason. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. (1996). Virtues of the mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. (2003). Intellectual motivation and the good of truth. In M. DePaul & L. Zagzebski (Eds.), Intellectual virtue: Perspectives from ethics and epistemology (pp. 135–154). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to audience members at the Midwest Epistemology Workshop—especially E.J. Coffman, Sandy Goldberg, Matt McGrath, Andrew Moon, Ernest Sosa, and John Wynne—for helpful comments on an earlier version of this paper. Most of all, I am very grateful to Jennifer Lackey for her helpful comments on this paper and, even more, for the many, many insights I have gained through our years of discussing the philosophical problems with which it is concerned. I am also thankful that she is not too skeptical of my skepticism.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Baron Reed.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Reed, B. A new argument for skepticism. Philos Stud 142, 91–104 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-008-9299-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-008-9299-9

Keywords

Navigation