Skip to main content
Log in

A defense of intuitions

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Radical experimentalists argue that we should give up using intuitions as evidence in philosophy. In this paper, I first argue that the studies presented by the radical experimentalists in fact suggest that some intuitions are reliable. I next consider and reject a different way of handling the radical experimentalists’ challenge, what I call the Argument from Robust Intuitions. I then propose a way of understanding why some intuitions can be unreliable and how intuitions can conflict, and I argue that on this understanding, both moderate experimentalism and the standard philosophical practice of using intuitions as evidence can help resolve these conflicts.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, e.g., Weinberg et al. (2001); Machery et al. (2004); Knobe (2003a); Nadelhoffer (2004).

  2. Harman (1994); Jackson (1998).

  3. See their blog at http://www.experimentalphilosophy.typepad.com/

  4. See, e.g., Goldman (1986, p. 66).

  5. Weinberg et al. call this “Intuition-Driven Romanticism” (2001, pp. 430–436). See also Pust (2000).

  6. Weinberg et al. (2001). See also Nichols et al. (2003).

  7. Swain et al. (forthcoming). For other research to which radical experimentalists have appealed to support their thesis, see, e.g., Machery et al. (2004); Nichols and Knobe (forthcoming).

  8. Weinberg et al. (2001, p. 434).

  9. Swain et al. (forthcoming, p. 19). In an earlier version of this paper, SAW’s claim is even more explicit. They say that their research entails that “philosophers should consider putting their intuitions in escrow.”

  10. Alexander and Weinberg (2007, p. 63). In this paper, Alexander and Weinberg have, as far as I am aware, independently introduced a distinction between the ‘‘proper foundation view’’ and the ‘‘restrictionist view,’’ which seems to correspond to my distinction between moderate and radical experimentalism. Their distinction is not quite my distinction though because they attribute the ‘‘proper foundation view’’ the position that ‘‘Only the results of such research can deliver the intuitions that can serve as evidential basis for or against philosophical claims’’ (2007, p. 61). On my distinction, this position would fall under radical experimentalism. Also, the ‘‘restrictionist’’ in the ‘‘restrictionist view’’ may not be discriminating enough because even philosophers of traditional approaches would accept that there should be some restrictions to the use of intuitions. For example, intuitions elicited under biases, mistaken heuristics and so on, should not count.

  11. Williamson (2004, p. 114).

  12. Williamson (2004, p. 118).

  13. Williamson (2004, pp. 118–122).

  14. Williamson (2004, pp. 121).

  15. Sosa (2005).

  16. Nichols et al. (2003, footnote 2); Weinberg et al. (2001).

  17. Audi (2004).

  18. Swain et al. (forthcoming).

  19. Weinberg et al. (2001).

  20. See, e.g., Sosa (2006); Lynch (2006), for such positive accounts.

  21. Initially, I was attracted to this approach. See also Kauppinen (2007), for a good exposition of this position. The terms ‘‘surface intuitions’’ and ‘‘robust intuitions’’ are from Kauppinen. WNS call robust intuitions ‘‘Austinian intuitions,’’ following a suggestion by Philip Kitcher.

  22. Lehrer (1990).

  23. See Gettier (1963), which inspired these cases.

  24. See, e.g., Dretske (1970).

  25. Weinberg et al. (2001, p. 445).

  26. Weinberg et al. (2001, p. 445).

  27. Weinberg et al. (2001, p. 450).

  28. Alexander and Weinberg (2007, p. 63).

  29. Swain et al. (forthcoming); See also Sinnott-Armstrong (2006), for a helpful example that illustrates this point.

  30. Sosa (2006); Williamson (2004); Lynch (2006).

  31. Sosa (2007, p. 105).

  32. See, e.g., Swain et al. (forthcoming).

  33. I thank an anonymous reviewer for pressing this point.

  34. Sosa (2006).

  35. Goldman (2007, p. 15).

  36. Sosa (2006, p. 225).

  37. See, e.g., Alexander and Weinberg (2007, p. 60), for the former idea.

  38. Williamson (2004).

  39. Alexander and Weinberg (2007, p. 72).

  40. Sosa (2006).

  41. Lynch (2006, p. 236).

  42. Williamson (2004, pp. 121).

  43. See, e.g., Kauppinen (2007).

  44. Weinberg et al. (2001).

  45. For a good discussion of some of these biases, see Sinnott-Armstrong (2006).

  46. There may be other ways by which intuitions can conflict, e.g. in their strengths, but I shall not consider them here. See, e.g., Sosa (2005).

  47. Some may notice that I am using moral examples here. Those who are sceptical that intuitions are truth-tracking might be even more sceptical about ‘‘moral’’ intuitions, since it could very well be the case that there is no truth to be tracked in the moral case. Personally, I do think that there are moral truths and that our intuitions can track them. See also Crisp (2006, Chap. 3), for this idea. But nothing that follows turns on this. Readers are free to substitute my examples with non-moral ones.

  48. The Knobe effect could be regarded as another example of an internal conflict of intuitions about different (albeit) similar cases. See, e.g., Knobe (2003b).

  49. Sosa (2007).

  50. Nichols and Ulatowski (forthcoming).

  51. For the latter view, see, e.g., Taurek (1977).

  52. Kelly (2005).

  53. See, e.g., Williamson (2004). For a view that we should adjust our beliefs and intuitions when there is a real disagreement with an “epistemic peer,” see, e.g., Christensen (2007).

References

  • Alexander, J., & Weinberg, J. (2007). Analytic epistemology and experimental philosophy. Philosophy Compass, 2(1), 56–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Audi, R. (2004). The good in the right. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, D. (2007). Epistemology of disagreement: The good news. Philosophical Review, 116, 187–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crisp, R. (2006). Reasons and the good. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1970). Epistemic operators. Journal of Philosophy, 67(24), 1007–1023.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gettier, E. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23, 121–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1986). Epistemology and cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (2007). Philosophical intuitions: Their target, their source, and their epistemic status. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 74, 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1994). Doubts about conceptual analysis. In M. Michael & J. O’Leary-Hawthorne (Eds.), Philosophy in mind. The place of philosophy in the study of mind (pp. 43–48). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1998). From metaphysics to ethics. A defense of conceptual analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauppinen, A. (2007). The rise and fall of experimental philosophy. Philosophical Explorations, 10, 95–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, T. (2005). The epistemic significance of disagreement. In J. Hawthorne & T. Szabo-Gendler (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology (Vol. 1, pp. 167–196). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. (2003a). Intentional action and side effects in ordinary language. Analysis, 63, 190–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. (2003b). Intentional action in folk psychology: An experimental investigation. Philosophical Psychology, 16, 309–324.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. (1990). Theory of knowledge. Boulder and London: Westview Press and Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, M. P. (2006). Trusting intuitions. In P. Greenough & M. P. Lynch (Eds.), Truth and realism (pp. 227–238). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E., Mallon, R., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2004). Semantics cross-cultural style. Cognition, 92, B1–B12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nadelhoffer, T. (2004). The butler problem revisited. Analysis, 64, 277–284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Knobe, J. Moral responsibility and determinism: The cognitive science of folk intuitions. Nous, (forthcoming).

  • Nichols, S., & Ulatowski, J. Intuitions and individual differences: The knobe effect revisited. Mind and Language, (forthcoming).

  • Nichols, S., Stich, S., & Weinberg, J. (2003). Meta-skepticism: Meditations on ethno-epistemology. In S. Luper (Ed.), The skeptics (pp. 227–247). Aldershot, U.K: Ashgate Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pust, J. (2000). Intuitions as evidence. New York: Garland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2006). Moral intuitionism meets empirical psychology. In T. Horgan & M. Timmons (Eds.), Metaethics after Moore (pp. 339–365). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2005). A defense of the use of intuitions in philosophy. In M. Bishop & D. Murphy (Eds.), Stich and his critics. Blackwell.

  • Sosa, E. (2006). Intuitions and truth. In P. Greenough & M. P. Lynch (Eds.), Truth and realism (pp. 208–226). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2007). Experimental philosophy and philosophical intuition. Philosophical Studies, 132, 99–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swain, S., Alexander, J., & Weinberg, J. The instability of philosophical intuitions: Running hot & cold on truetemp. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, (forthcoming).

  • Taurek, J. (1977). Should the numbers count? Philosophy and Public Affairs, 6, 293–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2001). Normativity and epistemic intuitions. Philosophical Topics, 29(1&2), 429–460.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2004). Philosophical ‘Intuitions’ and skepticism about judgment. Dialectica, 58, 109–153, p. 114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Joshua Alexander, Jonathan Weinberg, Roger Crisp, Steve Clarke, Robert Wachbroit, David Wasserman, Guy Kahane, Wibke Gruetjen, Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, Michael Blome-Tillmann, an anonymous reviewer at Philosophical Studies, and the audiences at the 2007 American Philosophical Association Pacific Division Meeting in San Francisco and at the Oxford University James Martin Advance Research Seminar for their very helpful comments on an earlier version of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to S. Matthew Liao.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Liao, S.M. A defense of intuitions. Philos Stud 140, 247–262 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-007-9140-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-007-9140-x

Keywords

Navigation