Skip to main content
Log in

Mr. Magoo’s mistake

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Timothy Williamson has famously argued that the (KK) principle (roughly, that if one knows that p, then one knows that one knows that p) should be rejected. We analyze Williamson’s argument and show that its key premise is ambiguous, and that when it is properly stated this premise no longer supports the argument against (KK). After canvassing possible objections to our argument, we reflect upon some conclusions that suggest significant epistemological ramifications pertaining to the acquisition of knowledge from prior knowledge by deduction.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Williamson (2000). Unless noted otherwise, references are to this text and by name and page number only.

  2. We follow Williamson in calling (1 i ) a proposition rather a principle (e.g., “let q be the proposition that the tree is not i + 1 inches tall” p. 116). It would perhaps be better to call it a principle (one limited to Mr. Magoo’s situation) since the conditionals embedded in (1 i ) or (WP) are known for a uniform reason pertaining to Mr. Magoo’s perceptual and evaluative abilities. Williamson admits that a reliability condition on knowledge is implicit in the argument (p. 123). We thank Peter Pagin and Karl Karlander here.

  3. Strictly speaking, this is not a straightforward contraposition since the conditional is within the range of the knowledge operator. However, since, Mr. Magoo has deduced all that follows from his knowledge (Williamson, 116), and assuming closure and factivity (see (C) bellow), this change is legitimate. Apart from this the same justification supporting (1 i ) can be given as justification to (WP).

  4. For ease of exposition we present Williamson’s argument in a simplified form. Nothing of substance will turn on the differences between the original argument and the one we present here.

  5. This formulation of (KK) is meant to avoid the obvious counter-examples to the better known versions. Furthermore, it is clear that Williamson is out to refute the more plausible formulation of (KK), according to which, if one knows p, one is thereby in a position to know that one knows that p. The way he does this is by imagining that Mr. Magoo has made all the deductions: “If he is in a position to know that he knows p, he does know that he knows p” (Williamson, 115). He then goes on to present what he takes to be a counter instance assuming that Mr. Magoo knows all that is deducible from his position thereby (allegedly) refuting the weaker less demanding formulation. That this is the relevant formulation is evident form the way chapter (5) begins. For more detail, see (Williamson, 115).

  6. The case is so construed that Mr. Magoo has deduced all pertinent conclusions about the tree and its height: “Statement (C) is simply a description of Mr. Magoo’s state once he has attained reflective equilibrium over the propositions at issue, by completing his deductions.” (Williamson, 116) See also previous note.

  7. Williamson formalizes factivity as follows:∀ p□(Kpp) (Williamson, 271). For simplicity and clarity, we have omitted throughout this paper quantification and necessity operators which play no essential role in the arguments.

  8. He could reason that, although the tree is definitely taller than 3 inches and shorter than 6,000 inches, it cannot be of any height n, for any natural number n between 3 and 6,000. Absurdly, he could therefore deduce that the tree has no height whatsoever even though he can see that it does. In this case, even without factivity, the result would be absurd.

  9. “The crude point is that iterating knowledge is hard, and each iteration adds a layer of difficulty.” (Williamson, 122). “The iteration of knowledge operators leads sooner or later to falsity through a process of erosion resulting from the need for margins for error.” (Williamson, 140–1).

  10. The scope of the knowledge operator is explicitly presented by Williamson: “Mr. Magoo knows that (for all natural numbers m (if the tree is m + 1 inches tall then he does not know that it is not m inches tall) and (the tree is not 0 inches tall)).” (Williamson, 117–8; and in logical notation on page 139 and in Appendix 2 (305–6)).

  11. Assuming (C), it can be deduced from Mr. Magoo’s knowledge of the following truism about tree heights: \(t_i \supset \sim t_{i+1} \) . From this it follows that, if he knows the tree is i inches tall, he knows it is not i + 1 inches tall. Note that on the theoretical level it does not make any difference how wide the margin for error is.

  12. Notice that Williamson leaves out an important condition. As the Magee scenario shows, for the principle to be valid, Mr. Magoo must know what his source of knowledge is, and that it is exclusive.

  13. There is textual evidence suggesting that Williamson concedes a similar point, namely that the margin of error changes in accordance with what he calls “the basis of knowledge” (Williamson, 128, 132). When, for instance, one knows of an event by seeing it, the margin, according to Williamson may be different from what it would have been had one known it by hearing. He does not explain why the change in the “basis” of knowledge does not influence the margin of error in the Magoo case.

  14. We call this proposition ‘(1 i -KK)’ since, as we intend to show, the advocates of (KK) can accept it.

  15. For our purposes this is similar enough to Williamson’s (C).

  16. If we are correct, a further assumption has been left tacit in Williamson’s argument, i.e., for the argument to work Mr. Magoo must not only know that he knows, but also how he knows. This is one more premise the (KK) advocate can deny (we thank Anders Nes for pointing this out). We will not follow this line of reasoning, however, since it seems that in special cases this problem can be overcome.

  17. This response was independently suggested by Hagit Benbaji and by Peter Pagin and Åsa Wikforss. We take this opportunity to thank Peter Pagin for correcting a mistake in a draft of this paper.

  18. This is mentioned in response to a possible claim according to which it is not (KK) that is the source of the contradiction but rather vagueness.

  19. Or if you want, it supports (WP-KK) as much as it supports (WP-dis).

  20. See, e.g., (Williamson, 135, 139).

  21. To the extent that they are independent of the Magoo argument, Williamson’s other considerations against luminosity are not debated here.

  22. We believe that the general lesson emerging from our criticism of Williamson’s argument, supports inquiring about the valid scope, or the constraints on the proper application, of the principle of epistemic closure. As discussing this principle clearly exceeds the scope of this paper, we pursue this project elsewhere (Sharon, A. & Spectre, L. Unpublished manuscript).

  23. Some subjects will get closer to the actual height of the tree by first judging in centimeters and then converting to inches. This is interesting since it seems that you get more knowledge from the same evidence (assuming that looking at the tree and thinking in centimeters is the same as looking at it and wondering how many inches it is in height). With a smaller tree, by looking, one can come much closer to its height than with a mammoth tree such as the one Williamson has chosen as his example. A reasonable evaluation of a tree that is 166 inches tall is that it is more than O inches and less than 332 inches.

  24. Note that it makes a big difference how tall the tree is. The smaller the tree, the smaller the interval it is reasonable to assume is indiscernible by a subject (by merely looking). (WP) will not apply to a “tree” 10 inches tall if the interval is 10 inches, but it will if the tree is 666 inches tall (as in the Magoo story).

  25. A Eucalyptus Regnans at Mt. Baw Baw, Victoria, Australian, is believed to have measured 143 m (470 ft.). The reports and measurements are from 1885. Another Australian eucalyptus, at Watts River, Victoria, had probably been over 150 m (492 ft.) tall. It is safe to assume that Mr. Magoo knows that in his area there are no 10,000 inches (833 ft.) trees.

  26. Given the reasoning above, it is quite straightforward to assume that Mr. Magoo should hold this belief. For the argument to work, however, this is not necessary, since, as we show later, it can be stated as an argument about what Mr. Magoo ought to believe.

  27. There is another formulation that perhaps comes closer than (WP-KK) to what was intended in formulating (WP), which also does not lead to contradiction. It turns on a distinction between reflective content and perceptual content. The general idea that this new proposition is justified by, is that the interval in the imbedded conditional (i.e., the interval in inches between what the subject knows the tree not to be and the height that it follows from this that the tree is not) decreases by an amount proportional to the increase in reflective content. This is one way to formalize this idea (when n is a positive natural number of reflections on what S knows by looking and m is a number such that 0 < m < 1):

    $$(\hbox{WP}-\hbox{int})\quad\quad K_S^{reflection} (K_S^{n} \sim t_i \supset \sim t_{i\pm m^{n}})$$

    This would hold generally and even with (KK) (given the correct value for m) no contradiction will result. What this demonstrates is that even if (WP-KK) is somehow shown to be too restrictive, there are yet other alternatives to (WP-dis) (at least one, namely, (WP-int)) which would also have to be dismissed for the Magoo argument to work. It is hard to see how (WP-dis) can be shown to be superior to (WP-int) since both can be applied indefinitely and both are disjunctive. Although (WP-int) is sensitive to the number of times it has been used it admits both reflective and perceptual content. It is therefore similar to (WP-dis) and should be expected to be more resilient in this context. In order for Williamson’s argument to work, then, it must be shown that the margin does not decrease and that Mr. Magoo can know that it does not decrease. That is a tall order indeed.

  28. A third alternative is that both are unjustified norms. We claim, however, that no special problem results from adopting (BFN-KK).

  29. The arrow is not to be understood as an implication but rather as a conditional permission operating on beliefs. This applies to (BFN-KK) as well.

  30. We are indebted to Hagit Benbaji, Yitzhak Benbaji, David Enoch, Patrick Girard, Sandy Goldberg, Sören Häggqvist, John Hawthorne, Mikael Janvid, Karl Karlander, Igal Kvart, Avishai Margalit, Anders Nes, Peter Pagin, Itamar Pitowsky, James Simmons, Åsa Wikforss, Jonathan Yaari and Dror Yinon for many helpful comments. We have also benefited from the responses of participants in the Graduate Student Workshop at Stanford University, the Philosophy of Science Seminar at Stockholm University, and the Rutgers-Princeton Graduate Philosophy Conference (2007). In addition we would like to thank Timothy Williamson for helpful discussion. In private conversation Prof. Williamson and Josh Snyder independently mentioned that an argument along somewhat similar lines is being developed by Jérôme Dokic and Paul Egré. We cannot comment on similarities or differences. Let it be noted that this is not to imply that our argument is endorsed by Williamson.

Reference

  • Sharon, A. & Spectre, L. Towards a new principle of Epistemic Closure. Unpublished manuscript.

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Levi Spectre.

Appendix: what about (WP-dis)?

Appendix: what about (WP-dis)?

Is the disjunctively modified (WP) justifiable? Well, what was it that made (WP) appealing in the first place? Two features of Williamson’s presentation of the argument contribute to the intuitive plausibility of (WP) and obscure the matter at hand. One feature relates to the range for which the story is told and the other to the intervals of heights for which (WP) is stated. We take these points in turn.

First, Mr. Magoo’s story begins with his observation that the tree is not 0 inches tall. This makes the following steps intuitively compelling, since for normal trees it is reasonable that Mr. Magoo can correctly and directly judge that they are not 5, 6 or even 20 inches tall. But for this no proposition such as (WP-dis) is needed. It seems that we can easily go along with Williamson in the initial stages since we know that any reasonable evaluator of heights will not only know that the 666 inches tall tree, is not 0 inches tall, but will also know that the tree is not 20 inches tall. In normal conditions a person can know just by looking at a tree that it is not 20 inches tall, independent of his observations that it is not 3 or 4 inches tall. At these stages the appeal to (WP) is idle.

In fact, in stating the rationale for (WP) Williamson himself says that Mr. Magoo knows that the height of the tree is not 60 inches (p. 114). That is part of the reason why it seems evident that if Mr. Magoo knows that the tree is not 3 inches tall he can come to know that it is not 4 inches tall—he already knows it is taller than 4 inches. That much was already implicit in the setup. We easily play along with the first stages since we know already that Mr. Magoo knows that the tree is not 3, 4, or even 50 inches tall. But once we accept the first steps, the game seems to be over. We find no acceptable reason to stop the argument from proceeding past the limit that is directly discernable by a normal observer. To be more accurate, once the reader has accepted the first two steps, it is hard to see how a stopping rule can be devised. But what if we start the argument at a height that is at the limit of what Mr. Magoo can know by direct observation? For instance, let us say that 500 inches is the closest height to the actual height of the tree that Mr. Magoo can reliably judge that the tree is not.Footnote 23 Can Mr. Magoo proceed to infer that the tree is not 501 inches tall?

A negative answer to this question is in effect an unreasonable rejection of WP (and of (WP-KK) as well). It seems that if Mr. Magoo knows how poor his judgment of heights is, he may also legitimately infer from his knowing by looking at the tree that it is not 500 inches tall, that it is not 501 inches tall either. The point to think about, however, is the next step. Granted that Mr. Magoo knows that the tree is not 501 inches tall, can he then infer correctly from this knowledge and from his knowledge of his limited abilities to tell tree heights by looking, that the tree is not 502 inches tall? Here intuitions may diverge. It seems that when the case is laid open in this way, the intuition that he can so infer is no longer as compelling. To clothe this intuitive weakness in reasons, we suggest that this is so because the inference exceeds the evidence available to Mr. Magoo. No matter whether he knows that he knows the tree is not 501 inches tall or merely knows that it is not of that height, the evidence available to him does not support the claim that the tree is not 502 inches tall, at least not on the basis of this margin for error; and this brings us to the other point.

Both (WP) and (WP-dis), gain intuitive appeal from the density of the intervals chosen. The interval of 1 inch is very modest relative to the evaluative abilities of normal subjects. But, once again, this is not material to (WP). Clearly, the small interval of 1 inch, although it may very well be the source of our tendency to accept (WP) in the initial stages, is not essential to the proposition. (WP) should be true for any interval of which Mr. Magoo knows that he cannot discriminate just by looking. If (WP) is correct for intervals of 1 inch, it should be good for 5, or 10 inches as well (provided that Mr. Magoo cannot discriminate between heights differing by 10 inches). It seems, however, that when the interval is sufficiently large, only one or two applications of the principle are intuitively convincing.Footnote 24

Combining these two observations regarding the source of (WP)’s intuitive appeal, defeats repeated applications of the principle and therefore undermines the validity of the multiple-application-enabling (WP-dis). If we start the Magoo argument at the closest height that Mr. Magoo can know that the tree is not in inches and we take the interval to be the largest that Mr. Magoo can know that he cannot discern by mere looking, then, it seems to us, allowing for more than one application of (WP) is rather unintuitive. In any case, the intuitive appeal of (WP-dis), at least of its recurring application, is not maintained once the contingent features of the story are changed.

But, regardless of intuitive force, is there an argument to show that (WP-dis) is not acceptable?

There are two strategies to argue against the acceptability of (WP-dis). The first is a direct rebuttal, viz. showing that it leads to unwelcome consequences, or is in conflict with some other, well-based, principle. The second strategy, and the one we pursue here, is an indirect argument. Our rejection of (WP-dis) is motivated by an analysis of the faults of propositions similar in both form and function. The general strategy is to show that the unacceptable conclusion reached by Mr. Magoo’s argument can be reached without the (KK) principle. We introduce two propositions similar to (WP-dis), and articulate two Magoo-type arguments. We show how these new disjunctive propositions lead to the same contradiction as does (WP-dis) without assuming (KK). This shows that the appeal to knowledge (or to its known limits) is not essential to the argument. In other words, it seems that just as in these cases the contradiction is reached through the introduction of the disjunctive propositions and independently of (KK), in the Magoo argument too the disjunctive (WP-dis) is responsible for the mess and not necessarily (KK). So, if the argument is sound, there’s reason to suspect that disjunctive propositions like (WP-dis) should be rejected.

Assume that for a normal tree Mr. Magoo can tell that if he recognizes it from a distance of 100 yards, it must be taller than one foot. Sitting at one end of a football field, Mr. Magoo sees a tree at the other end of the field. He therefore knows that the tree at the far end of the field is not 12 inches tall. He also knows that it is not taller than 10,000 inches, since presumably, no tree is.Footnote 25

$$ K_M t_{12-10,000}\quad\quad(\hbox{Mr. Magoo knows that the tree's height in inches is between 12 and 10,000}) $$
(A)

Since knowledge entails belief (as will be assumed throughout) we may also suppose that:

$$ B_M t_{12-10,000}\quad\quad(\hbox{Mr. Magoo believes that the tree's height in inches is between 12 and 10,000}). $$
(B)

Footnote 26Now think of a principle quite similar to (WP-dis):

$$ K_M (B_M ^{looking\vee reflection}\sim t_i \supset \sim t_{i+1}) $$
(1)

The idea behind this principle is that, knowing the limitations of his own visual ability Mr. Magoo knows that if, upon looking and reflecting on his abilities alone, he has formed a belief that the tree is not of a certain height, then the tree must not be 1 inch taller than that. Now contrast (1) with:

$$ K_M (B_M^{looking} \sim t_i \supset \sim t_{i+1}) $$
(1’)

We will demonstrate that while the non-disjunctive (1’) does not lead to a contradiction, its disjunctive analogue, (1), does, and this without recourse to (KK).

Assume that after looking at the tree Mr. Magoo believes it is not 12 inches tall:

$$ B_M^{looking} \sim t_{12} $$
(2)

Now assume that Mr. Magoo performs a series of deductions, similar to those Williamson has him perform. To avoid possible failure of transparency of beliefs, assume that he is writing the steps of the deduction on paper, so that in this case:

$$ B_M p\supset K_M B_M p $$
(3)

From (2) and (3) it follows that Mr. Magoo knows that he believes the tree is not 12 inches tall:

$$ K_M B_M \sim t_{12} $$
(4)

Positing (2) as the antecedent in (1) we get:

$$ K_M (B_M \sim t_{12} \supset \sim t_{13}) $$
(5)

From (4) and (5) it follows by closure that Mr. Magoo knows that the tree is not 13 inches tall:

$$ K_M \sim t_{13} $$
(6)

Since knowledge entails belief, from (6) it follows that:

$$ B_M \sim t_{13} $$
(7)

At this point Mr. Magoo can posit (7) in (1) and get:

$$ K_M (B_M \sim t_{13} \supset \sim t_{14}) $$
(8)

Once again, since he is fully conscious and writing the steps of his deduction as he is going through them, Mr. Magoo knows that he believes that the tree is not 13 inches tall:

$$ K_M B_M \sim t_{13} $$
(9)

and therefore, again by closure we get:

$$ K_M \sim t_{14} $$
(10)

These iterations can be continued for the full expanse between 12 and 10,000 inches. Looking at his notes, Mr. Magoo concludes, and therefore knows, that the tree is not any height within this interval (or at least knows that he believes this):

$$ K_M \sim t_{12\hbox{--}10,000} $$
(11)

(11) clearly contradicts (A) thus ascribing to Mr. Magoo knowledge of contradictory propositions. Note that this conclusion amounts to possible inconsistency within Magoo’s cognitive system, regardless of the tree’s actual height (so no appeal to factivity is required). But more importantly, this time the blame cannot be laid on (KK), since the troubling result is reached without recourse to this principle. In the present argument, (KK) has been replaced with (3), which is, under the circumstances of the case, very plausible.

Now, the point to notice is that the knowledge in (6) is knowledge by direct perception and inference by reflection on Mr. Magoo’s visual abilities. The belief in (7) therefore, must also be modified as belief by looking and reflection. (7) is then plugged into (2) which—modified to accommodate belief by looking or reflection—allows the argument to proceed. So the full formulization of (7) should be:

$$ B_M^{looking\,\&\,reflection} \sim t_{13} $$
(7*)

Let us remind ourselves that our inquiry into this case has emerged from the question of the adequacy of the disjunctively modified (WP-dis). Our question was whether this disjunctive modification, allowing for knowledge gained by both mere looking and inference from reflective truths to appear as the antecedent in the conditional, is acceptable. Proposition (1) of the present argument has been modified in exactly the same way as (WP-dis). We now want to suggest that it is this liberal formulation which is the source of trouble. Think of the less permissive (1′) (structurally analogous to (WP-KK)):

$$ K_M (B_M^{looking} \sim t_i \supset \sim t_{i+1}) $$
(1′)

It is easy to see that (7*) cannot be posited in (1′). To put it explicitly, had the belief operator in (1) been modified to accommodate only belief by mere looking, it would have been wrong to posit (7) in (1) and the move to (8) and (11) would have been blocked. It seems then, that the inappropriate modification of the belief operator in (1) is to blame for the unwanted results. Since this argument and proposition (1) on which it turns were designed to mirror Mr. Magoo’s argument in its (WP-dis) formulation, the failure of the former argument can be instructive regarding the latter. Although this is not a direct argument against the coherence of (WP-dis), the present argument does suffice to cast doubt on the plausibility of disjunctive conditionals like (WP-dis). The argument shows that a disjunctive proposition similar to (WP-dis) in both form and intent leads to a contradiction independent of (KK). It is therefore reasonable to suspect that it is also the disjunctive modification in (WP-dis) that leads into trouble and not (KK).Footnote 27

Let us take another disjunctive principle of the (WP-dis)-type, this time, one pertaining not to knowledge but rather to the norms of belief-formation. Once again, we show, the disjunctive character of the principles leads to inconsistency regardless of (KK) or any analogous principle.

Say Mr. Magoo is deliberating about his own perceptual beliefs. Which of the following belief forming norms, structurally analogous to (WP-KK) and (WP-dis), should Mr. Magoo adopt?

(BFN-dis) If Mr. Magoo believes by looking or reflecting (on what he believes by looking) that a tree is not i inches tall, then he may also form a belief that a tree is not i+1 inches tall.

Or, alternatively, is he justified in adopting: Footnote 28

(BFN-KK) If Mr. Magoo believes by looking alone that a tree is not i inches tall, then he may also form the belief that it is not i + 1?

Notice that (BFN-dis) is more permissive than (BFN-KK). Like (WP-dis), it applies to other sources of belief, besides the purely visual. As we will now demonstrate, this permissiveness makes (BFN-dis) unacceptable since it can lead one to an incoherent belief system. In other words, the permissiveness of this norm leads to incoherence just as its analogue, (WP-dis), leads to a contradiction.

Imagine that, looking at a tree, Mr. Magoo forms the true belief that it’s between 5 and 10,000 inches tall. We therefore have the following:

$$\begin{eqalign} B_M^{looking} t_{5-10,000}\quad\quad(\hbox{Mr. Magoo believes by looking that the tree is between 5 and 10,000\,inches tall}). \end{eqalign}$$
(12)

From (12) we can infer:

$$ B_M^{looking\,\&\,reflecting} \sim t_4\quad\quad(\hbox{Mr. Magoo believes by reflecting and looking that the tree is not 4\,inches tall}). $$
(13)

Now recall our candidate for belief-forming norm:

(BFN-dis)Footnote 29

$$ B_M^{looking\vee reflecting} \sim t_i \rightarrow B\sim t_{i+1} $$

Following the direction of (BFN-dis), Mr. Magoo forms on the basis of (13) the belief:

$$ B_M^{looking\,\&\,reflecting} \sim t_5\quad\quad(\hbox{Mr. Magoo believes by reflecting and looking that the tree is not 5\,inches tall}). $$
(14)

He then iterates this move, advancing 1 inch at a time. Imagine that he is recording these steps by writing them in succession on paper. Therefore, at least in this case, if he has a belief (Bp) he also knows that he has it (KBp). He repeats these steps again and again, forming his beliefs according to the direction of his accepted norm (BFN-dis). Finally, after surveying his records, he concludes that:

$$ B_M^{looking\,\&\,reflecting} \sim t_{5--10,000}\quad\quad(\hbox{Mr. Magoo believes by reflecting on what he believes by looking and reflecting that the tree is not of any height between 5 and 10,000}) $$
(15)

But (15) is in direct conflict with (12). Although a person may (arguably) hold incompatible beliefs, the fact that (BFN-dis) inevitably leads to contradiction is good reason not to adopt it as a norm of belief-formation. This conclusion is strengthened by the fact that there is another candidate available that has the virtues of (BFN-dis) (it is justified by the same considerations) without its vices, namely (BFN-KK):

$$ (\hbox{BFN}\hbox{-KK})\;B_M^{looking} \sim t_i \rightarrow B_M^{looking\,\&\,reflecting} \sim t_{i+1} $$

To see the advantage of this norm, imagine that we start with the visually formed belief:

$$ B_M^{looking} \sim t_4\quad\quad(\hbox{Mr. Magoo believes by looking that the tree is not 4\,inches tall.}) $$
(13′)

Under the guidance of (BFN-KK) he can form the belief that the tree is not 5 inches tall.

$$ B_M^{looking\,\&\,reflecting} \sim t_5\quad\quad(\hbox{Mr. Magoo believes by looking and reflecting}, \hbox{that the tree is not 5\,inches tall}). $$
(14′)

But this belief-forming norm can carry Mr. Magoo no further than this, since (14′) cannot be posited as the antecedent in (BFN-KK). The more moderate character of (BFN-KK) prevents one from getting into contradictions, by adopting it. Unlike its more radical disjunctive counterpart: (BFN-dis).

Notice that the problematic result of (BFN-dis) does not involve (KK). It seems then that it is just the disjunctive nature of (BFN-dis) that is to blame for the inconsistency. And so, by analogy it is plausible to claim that the disjunctive nature of (WP-dis), rather than (KK), should be identified as responsible for Magoo’s contradiction. It is this principle’s insensitivity to the source of knowledge it operates on (which, ironically, was the reason for accepting this principle in the first place) that entitles us to reject it. Footnote 30

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Sharon, A., Spectre, L. Mr. Magoo’s mistake. Philos Stud 139, 289–306 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-007-9119-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-007-9119-7

Keywords

Navigation