Skip to main content
Log in

Cognitive science and epistemic openness

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recent findings in cognitive science suggest that the epistemic subject is more complex and epistemically porous than is generally pictured. Human knowers are open to the world via multiple channels, each operating for particular purposes and according to its own logic. These findings need to be understood and addressed by the philosophical community. The current essay argues that one consequence of the new findings is to invalidate certain arguments for epistemic anti-realism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Akins, K. 1996. Of sensory systems and the “`aboutness'” of mental states. Journal of Philosophy 93: 337–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alston, W. 1997. A Realist Conception of Truth. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alston, W. 2001. A Sensible Metaphysical Realism. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, M. L. 2003a. Embodied cognition: a field guide. Artificial Intelligence 149(1): 91–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, M. L. 2003b. Representations, symbols, and embodiment. Artificial Intelligence 149(1): 151–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, M. L. 2005. Representation, evolution and embodiment. In: D. Smith (ed), Evolutionary Biology and the Central Problems of Cognitive Science, special issue of Theoria et Historia Scientarum 9(1).

  • Anderson, M. L. forthcoming. How to study the mind: An introduction to embodied cognition. In: F. Santoianni and C. Sabatano, (eds.), Brain Development in Learning Environments: Embodied and Perceptual Advancements.

  • Anderson, M. L. and Oates, T. 2003. Prelinguistic agents will form only egocentric predicates. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26(3): 284–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, M. L. and Rosenberg, G. forthcoming. Content and action: the guidance theory of representation.

  • Bermúdez, J. L. 1995a. Ecological perception and the notion of a non-conceptual point of view. In: J. L. Bermúdez, A. Marcel and N. Eilan (eds), The Body and the Self pp. 153–174. MIT Press.

  • Bermúdez, J. L. 1995b. Non-conceptual content: From perceptual experience to subpersonal computational states. Mind and Language 10(4): 333–369.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bermúdez, J. L. 1998. The Paradox of Self-Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bosco, G. and Poppele, R. 2001. Proprioception from a spinocerebellar perspective. Physiological Reviews 81: 539–568.

    Google Scholar 

  • Botvinick, M. and Cohen, J. 1998. Rubber hands “feel” touch that eyes can see. Nature 391: 756.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. 2003. The Matrix as metaphysics. http://whatisthematrix.warnerbros.com/rl_cmp/new_phil_fr_chalmers.html.

  • Chrisley, R. 1995. Non-conceptual content and robotics: Taking embodiment seriously. In: K. Ford, C. Glymour, and P. Hayes (eds), Android Epistemology. pp. 141–166. Cambridge, MA: AAAI/MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. 1997. Being There: Putting Brain, Brain and World Together Again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. 2001. Visual experience and motor action: are the bonds too tight? Philosophical Review 110.

  • Craig, J. and Rollman, G. 1999. Somethesis. Annual Review of Psychology 50: 305–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. 1985. On the very idea of a conceptual scheme. In: Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. 1991. Realism and Truth 2nd ed. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dijkerman, H. C., Lê, S., Démonet, J. F. and Milner, A. D. 2004. Visuomotor performance in a patient with visual agnosia due to an early lesion. Cognitive Brain Research, in press.

  • Ellis, R. R. and Lederman, S. J. 1998. The golf-ball illusion: evidence for top-down processing in weight perception. Perception 27(2): 193–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. 1982. The Varieties of Reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. 1985. Molyneux's question. In: G. Evans (ed), The Collected Papers of Gareth Evans. London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, J. R. and Beltzner, M. A. 2000. Independence of perceptual and sensorimotor predictions in the size-weight illusion. Nature Neuroscience 3(7): 737–741.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. and Pylyshyn, Z. 2002. How direct is visual perception?: Some reflections on Gibson's “`Ecological Approach'”. In A. Nöe and E. Thompson (eds), Vision and Mind: Selected Writings in the Philosophy of Perception, pp. 167–228. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. 2003. Bodily self-awareness and object perception. Theoria et Historia Scientarum: International Journal for Interdisciplinary Studies 7(1): 53–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. 1986. Body image and body schema: a conceptual clarification. Journal of Mind and Behavior 7: 541–554.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, I., James, T. W., Curby, K. and Tarr, M. J. 2003. The influence of conceptual knowledge on visual discrimination. Cognitive Neuropsychology 20(3–6): 507–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghez, C., Gordon, J. and Ghilardi, M. F. 1995. Impairments of reaching movements in patients without proprioception. II. Effects of visual information on accuracy. Journal of Neurophysiology 73: 361–372.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. 1966. The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. 1977. On the analysis of change in the optic array in cotemporary research in visual space and motion perception. Scandinavian Journal of Psychology 18: 161–163.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glenberg, A. and Kaschak, M. (2002). Grounding language in action. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review 9: 558-565.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldschalk, M., Lemon, R. N., Kuypers, H. G. J. M. and Ronday, H. K. 1984. Cortical afferents and efferents of monkey postarcuate area: an anatomical and electrophysiological study. Experimental Brain Research 56: 410–424.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodale, M. A., Milner, A. D., Jakobson, L. S. and Carey, D. P. 1991. A neurological dissociation between perceiving objects and grasping them. Nature 349: 154–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodale, M. A., Murphy, K. J., Meenan, J.-P., Racicot, C. I. and Nicolle, D. A. 1993. Spared object perception but poor object-calibrated grasping in a patient with optic ataxia. Society for Neuroscience Abstracts 19: 775.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodale, M. A., Meenan, J.-P., Bülthoff, H. H., Nicolle, D. A., Murphy, K. J. and Racicot, C. I. 1994. Separate neural pathways for the visual analysis of object shape in perception and prehension. Current Biology 4: 604–610.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. 1978. Ways of Worldmaking. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gregory, R. 1998. Brainy mind. British Medical Journal 317: 1693–1695.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gregory, R. 2002. Perceptions as hypotheses. In: A. Nöe, and E. Thompson, (eds), Vision and Mind: Selected Writings in the Philosophy of Perception, pp. 111–134. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gunther, Y. (ed), 2003. Essays on Nonconceptual Content. Cambridge MA: Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. 1983. Representing and Intervening. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Humphrey, G. K., Goodale, M. A., Jakobson, L. S. and Servos, P. 1994. The role of surface information in object recognition: studies of a visual form agnosic and normal subjects. Perception 23: 1457–1481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurford, J. 2003. The neural basis of predicate-argument structure. Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

  • James, T. W., Culham, J., Humphrey, G. K., Milner, A. D. and Goodale, M. A. 2003. Ventral occipital lesions impair object recognition but not object-directed grasping: an fMRI study. Brain 126: 2463–2475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. 1912. Essays in Radical Empiricism. New York: Longmans, Green.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. 1981. Pragmatism. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M. 1997. The Cognitive Neuroscience of Action. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kawai, S. 2002. Constant involvement of haptically perceived size in weight discrimination. Experimental Brain Research 147(1): 16–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. 1994. Mind and World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marr, D. 2002. Selections from Vision. In: A. Nöe and E. Thompson (eds), Vision and Mind: Selected Writings in the Philosophy of Perception, pp. 229–266. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matelli, M., Camarda, R., Glickstein M. and Rizzolatti, G. 1986. Afferent and efferent projections of the inferior area 6 in the macaque monkey. Journal of Comparative Neurology 251: 281–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. 1962. The Phenomenology of Perception. C. Smith (tr) London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milner, A. D., Perrett, D. I., Johnston, R. S., Benson, P. J., Jordan, T. R. and Heeley, D. W. et al. 1991. Perception and action in “`visual form agnosia'”. Brain 114: 405–428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milner, A. D. and Goodale, M. 1995. The Visual Brain in Action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nicolelis, M., Ghazanfar, A., Stambaugh, C., Olivera, L., Laubach, M., Chapin, J., Nelson, R. and Kass, J. 1998. Simultaneous encoding of tactile information by three primate cortical areas. Nature Neuroscience 1: 621–631.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nöe, A. (ed), 2002a. Is the Visual World a Grand Illusion? Special issue of the Journal of Consciousness Studies 9.

  • Nöe, A. 2002b. Is the visual world a grand illusion? In: A. Nöe (ed), Is the Visual World a Grand Illusion? Special issue of the Journal of Consciousness Studies 9.

  • Nöe, A. and Thompson, E. (eds), 2002a. Vision and Mind: Selected Writings in the Philosophy of Perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nöe, A. and Thompson, E. 2002b. Introduction. In: A. Noe and E. Thompson (eds), Vision and Mind: Selected Writings in the Philosophy of Perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O'Donovan-Anderson, M. 1996. Science & things: Scientific method as embodied access to the world. In: M. O'Donovan-Anderson (ed), The Incorporates Self: Interdisciplinary Perspectives on Embodiment. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • O'Donovan-Anderson, M. 1997. Content and Comportment: On Embodiment and the Epistemic Availability of the World. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • O'Donovan-Anderson, M. 2002. Understanding bodily awareness. Proceedings of Tucson 2002:Towards a Science of Consciousness. Tucson, AZ.

  • O'Regan, J. K. and Nöe, A. 2001. A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24.

  • O'Shaughnessy, B. 1995. Proprioception and the body image. In: J. L. Bermúdez, A. Marcel and N. Elian (eds), The Body and the Self, pp. 175–203. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O'Shaughnessy, B. 1980. The Will: A Dual Aspect Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. 1998. Nonconceptual content defined. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58(2): 381–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. 1955. The Philosophical Writings of Peirce. In: J. Buchler (ed), New York: Dover.

  • Peirce, C. S. 1958. The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perenin, M. T. and Vighetto, A. 1983. Optic ataxia: A specific disorder in visuomotor coordination. In: A. Hein and M. Jeannerod (eds), Spatially oriented behavior. New York: Springer-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perenin, M. T. and Vighetto, A. 1988. Optic ataxia: a specific disruption in visuomotor mechanisms. I. Different aspects of the deficit in reaching for objects. Brain 111: 643–674.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. 1997. How the Mind Works. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Power, S. 2003. The AIDS rebel. The New Yorker May 19: 54–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. 1981. Reason, Truth and History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. 1969. Ontological Relativity New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. 1985. Two dogmas of empiricism. In: A. Martinich (ed), The Philosophy of Language, pp. 26–39. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., Camarda, R., Fogassi, L., Gentilucci, M., Luppino, G. and Matelli, M. 1988. Functional organization of inferior area 6 in the macaque monkey. II. Area F5 and the control of distal movements. Experimental Brain Research 71: 491–507.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. 1979. The world well lost. In: The Consequences of Pragmatism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. 1991. Objectivity, Relativism and Truth. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, G. and Anderson, M. L. 2004. A brief introduction to the guidance theory of representation. Proceedings of the 26th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society.

  • Sakata, H., Taira, M., Mine, S. and Murata A. 1992. Hand-movement related neurons of the posterior parietal cortex of the monkey: their role in visual guidance of hand movements. In: R. Caminiti, P. B. Johnson and Y. Burnod (eds), Control of Arm Movement in Space. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sanders, M. D., Warrington, E. K., Marshall, J. and Weiskrantz, L. 1974. “`Blindsight'”: vision in a field defect. Lancet 20: 707–708.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schneider, G. E. 1969. Two visual systems: Brain mechanisms for localization and discrimination are dissociated by tectal and cortical lesions. Science 163: 895–902.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sommer, M. and Wurtz, R. 2002. A pathway in primate brain for internal monitoring of movements. Science 296: 1480–1482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stroud, B. 1984. The Significance of Philosophical Skepticism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stroud, B. 2000. Understanding Human Knowledge: Philosophical Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, R. and Barto, A. 1998. Reinforcement Learning: An Introduction. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taira, M., Mine, S., Georgopoulos, A. P., Mutara, A. and Sakata, H. 1990. Parietal cortex neurons of the monkey related to the visual guidance of hand movements. Experimental Brain Research 83: 29–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. 1995. Colour Vision. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ungerleider, L. G. and Mishkin, M. 1982. Two cortical visual systems. In: D. J. Ingle, M. A. Goodale and R. J. W. Mansfield (eds), Analysis of Visual Behavior. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J., Thompson, E. and Rosch E. 1991. The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiskrantz, L., Warrington, E. K., Sanders, M. D. and Marshall, J. 1974. Visual capacity in the hemianopic field following a restricted occipital ablation. Brain 97: 709–728.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, M. 1996. Unnatural Doubts. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. 1988. Realism, antirealism, irrealism, quasirealism. In: P. French, T. Uehling, and H. Wettstein (eds), Midwest Studies in Philosophy XII: Realism and Antirealism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. 1994. Truth and Objectivity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael L. Anderson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Anderson, M.L. Cognitive science and epistemic openness. Phenom Cogn Sci 5, 125–154 (2006). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-005-9008-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-005-9008-5

Keywords

Navigation