Skip to main content
Log in

Is There a Future for AI Without Representation?

  • Published:
Minds and Machines Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper investigates the prospects of Rodney Brooks’ proposal for AI without representation. It turns out that the supposedly characteristic features of “new AI” (embodiment, situatedness, absence of reasoning, and absence of representation) are all present in conventional systems: “New AI” is just like old AI. Brooks proposal boils down to the architectural rejection of central control in intelligent agents—Which, however, turns out to be crucial. Some of more recent cognitive science suggests that we might do well to dispose of the image of intelligent agents as central representation processors. If this paradigm shift is achieved, Brooks’ proposal for cognition without representation appears promising for full-blown intelligent agents—Though not for conscious agents.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Bickhard, M. H. (1993). Representational content in humans and machines. Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence, 5, 285–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard, M. H. (2001). Why children don’t have to solve the frame problems: Cognitive representations are not encodings. Developmental Review, 21, 224–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard, M. H., & Terveen, L. (1996). Foundational issues in artificial intelligence and cognitive science. Amsterdam: Elsevier Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braitenberg, V. (1984). Vehicles: Experiments in synthetic psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, R. A. (1986). A robust layered control system for a mobile robot. IEEE Journal of Robotics and Automation, 2, 14–23.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, R. A. (1990). Elephants don’t play chess. Robotics and Autonomous Systems, 6, 3–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, R. A. (1991a). Intelligence without reason. In J. Myopoulos (Ed.), Proceedings of 12th international joint conference on artificial intelligence (IJCAI), computers and thought (pp. 569–595). Sidney: Morgan Kaufmann.

  • Brooks, R. A. (1991b). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47, 139–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2003). Natural born cyborgs: Minds, technologies, and the future of human intelligence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crabbe, F. L. (2006). Unifying undergraduate artificial intelligence robotics: Layers of abstraction over two channels. AI Magazine, 27, 23–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (2003). The mechanical mind: A philosophical introduction to minds, machines and mental representation (2nd ed.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, R., Shrobe, H., & Szolowits, P. (1993). What is a knowledge representation? AI Magazine, 14, 17–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2005). Sweet dreams: Philosophical obstacles to a science of consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Etzioni, O. (1993). Intelligence without robots: A reply to Brooks. AI Magazine, 14, 7–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harnad, S. (1990). The symbol grounding problem. Physica D, 42, 335–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirk, R. (2005). Zombies and consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (2005). Language: A biological model. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2005). Action in perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfeifer, R., Bongard, J. (2007). How the body shapes the way we think: A new view of intelligence. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Preston J., Bishop M. (Eds.). (2002). Views into the chinese room: New essays on searle and artificial intelligence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Prince, C. G. (2002). Review of Rodney A. Brooks Cambrian intelligence: The early history of the new AI. MIT Press 1999’. Minds and Machines, 12, 145–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, G. (2004). A place for consciousness: Probing the deep structure of the natural world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, S., & Norvig, P. (2003). Artificial intelligence: A modern approach (2nd ed.). Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1980). Minds, brains and programs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 417–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taddeo, M., & Floridi, L. (2005). Solving the symbol grounding problem: A critical review of fifteen years of research. Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence, 17, 419–445.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wallis, P. (2004). Intention without representation. Philosophical Psychology, 17, 209–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wallis P. (forthcoming). Symbol grounding for two year olds. In C. Schmidt (Ed.), I-C&P 2006: Computers and philosophy. Laval, Le Mans.

  • Wheeler, M. (2005). Reconstructing the cognitive world: The next step. Boston: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Vincent C. Müller.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Müller, V.C. Is There a Future for AI Without Representation?. Minds & Machines 17, 101–115 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-007-9067-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-007-9067-1

Keywords

Navigation