Skip to main content
Log in

Merleau-Ponty on shared emotions and the joint ownership thesis

  • Published:
Continental Philosophy Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In “The Child’s Relations with Others,” Merleau-Ponty argues that certain early experiences are jointly owned in that they are numerically single experiences that are nevertheless given to more than one subject (e.g., the infant and caregiver). Call this the “joint ownership thesis” (JT). Drawing upon both Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenological analysis, as well as studies of exogenous attention and mutual affect regulation in developmental psychology, I motivate the plausibility of JT. I argue that the phenomenological structure of some early infant–caregiver dyadic exchanges is best described as involving joint subjects. From birth, some experiences are constitutively social in that certain phenomenal states, such as the positive emotions that arise within these early exchanges, are jointly owned. Along the way, I consider a possible objection. I conclude by considering the explanatory significance of adopting JT.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Merleau-Ponty (Merleau-Ponty 1964b, pp. 96–155).

  2. This second intention is a continuation of Merleau-Ponty’s own extensive dialogue with psychology—a dialogue also found in classical phenomenologists such as Husserl, Gurwitsch, and Sartre, among others. Of course, the phenomenological tradition harbors a number of rich and extremely varied treatments of intersubjectivity, many of which may be of similar use to cognitive science. In light of my focus on Merleau-Ponty’s joint ownership thesis, I won’t consider these alternative treatments here. For other examples of how phenomenological approaches to intersubjectivity can helpfully inform various discussions in cognitive science, see, for example, Fuchs (2010), Gallagher (2008, 2012), Gallagher and Zahavi (2008), Krueger (2008, 2012), Krueger and Overgaard (2012), Overgaard (2007), Ratcliffe (2008), Stawarska (2009), Thompson (2001), Zahavi (2011).

  3. Merleau-Ponty (1964b, p. 114).

  4. Merleau-Ponty (1964b, p. 114).

  5. Merleau-Ponty (1964b, p. 114).

  6. Merleau-Ponty (1964b, p. 115).

  7. Merleau-Ponty (1964b, p. 115).

  8. See, for example, Gallagher and Zahavi (2008, pp. 171–196), Gurwitsch (1979, pp. 9–33), Krueger and Overgaard (2012), Malcolm (1962), Ryle (1949), Sartre (1956, pp. 301–404), Scheler (1954, pp. 238–284).

  9. Merleau-Ponty (1964b, p. 115).

  10. Morton and Johnson (1991).

  11. Mondloch et al. (1999), Johnson et al. (1991).

  12. Slater and Quinn (2001).

  13. Meltzoff and Moore (1997), Legerstee (1991), Kugiumutzakis et al. (2005). But see Jones (2009) for a critical appraisal of this interpretation of neonate imitation.

  14. O’Neill (1986, p. 205).

  15. Merleau-Ponty (1964b, p. 117).

  16. Merleau-Ponty (2002, p. 410).

  17. Merleau-Ponty (1964b, p. 118).

  18. Merleau-Ponty (2002, p. 410).

  19. Merleau-Ponty (1964b, p. 119).

  20. See, for example, Carruthers (1989).

  21. Rochat (2009, p. 64); see also Legerstee (2005), Zelazo (1996).

  22. See, for example, Gopnik and Wellman (1992), Gallese (2001), Goldman (2006).

  23. Merleau-Ponty (2010, p. 147).

  24. Neisser (1995), Butterworth and Jarrett (1991).

  25. Eilan (2007) offers an alternative strategy for defending JT (or what she terms the “phenomenological thesis”). She suggests that adopting a relational view of experience (e.g., Campbell 2002), according to which the qualitative character of experience is constituted by the layout and characteristics of objects (their intrinsic properties, how they are arranged in relation to one another and to the subject, etc.) as well as their surrounding environment, offers resources for explicating the notion of a jointly owned mental state. According to the relational view of experience, perception is an irreducibly experiential relation with a physical object or some intrinsic aspect of it as a constituent of the experience. Accordingly, if young infants are capable of directly (noninferentially) perceiving an emotion in another’s facial expression, that emotion is a constituent of their experience and is thus jointly owned; it is a constituent of both the subject’s and the infant’s experience. This is an intriguing suggestion. However, it’s not clear why the same thing can’t be said of adult perceivers, too. This strategy thus appears insensitive to important ontogenetic and phenomenological differences between infant and adult perceivers. Rather than pursue this line of argument, I want to dig more deeply into the phenomenology of infant consciousness and offer reasons why, at this stage, consciousness is structurally poised to be shared in a way not the case for adult experience.

  26. Meltzoff and Moore (1997), Kugiumutzakis et al. (2005).

  27. Rochat and Hespos (1997), Marlier et al. (1998).

  28. Standley and Madsen (1990).

  29. Plantinga and Trainor (2009). Unlike the visual system, the auditory system is stimulated in utero (DeCasper et al. 1994).

  30. Gopnik (2009, pp. 106–123), Posner and Rothbart (1998).

  31. This developmental trajectory appears to be reflected at the neurochemical level. Cholinergic transmitters, which heighten attention, are abundant at birth; inhibitory transmitters, which suppress attention, develop later. Additionally, Luria’s (1973) distinction between an early developing, largely involuntary biological attention system and a later developing, largely voluntary and socially-mediated attention system has been supported by more recent work (Posner and Rothbart 1998). Parietal and sensory systems involved in exogenous attention are thus online early, developmentally speaking, while top-down frontal regions controlling endogenous attention only mature later (Gopnik 2008).

  32. Gopnik (2009, p. 123).

  33. Krueger (2013).

  34. Hopkins (1983, p. 131).

  35. Kaye (1982).

  36. Alberts et al. (1983).

  37. Murphy (1978), Bates et al. (1975).

  38. Butterworth and Jarrett (1991).

  39. Legerstee (2005, p. 16).

  40. Wexler (2008, p. 102).

  41. James (1950, v. 1, p. 142).

  42. An analogous experience in adult perceivers may be the radically self-effacing character of some advanced stages of meditation, particularly those that emphasize “open presence” in which the field of attention is dramatically broadened and the various contents of consciousness are simultaneously illuminated (Lutz et al. 2007).

  43. Neisser (1995, p. 23).

  44. Gopnik 2008. Additionally, the cross-modal character of early neonate experience (Meltzoff and Moore 1997; Meltzoff and Borton 1979; Kaye and Bower 1994; Rochat 1999) may contribute to the feeling of nonduality in that objects of experience (faces, sounds, touches, etc.) are simultaneously given with a richness and felt immediacy—an immersive or encompassing character, in other words—that reinforces the sense of being experientially united with the world. Similarly, cross-modal (synaesthetic) experiences in adults are often reported to be a feature of the nondual heights of advanced contemplative experiences, along with, suggestively, an attenuated sense of self-world differentiation (Walsh 2005).

  45. Merleau-Ponty (2010, p. 147). James terms this the “psychologist’s fallacy,” that is, “the confusion of [the psychologist’s] own standpoint with that of the mental fact about which he is making his report” (James 1950, v. 1, p. 196).

  46. Niedenthal (2007).

  47. Solomon (2004).

  48. Thompson (2007), pp. 360–381, Zeedyk (2006)

  49. Rothbart (1989).

  50. Hobson (2005), Tronick (2005).

  51. Beebe and Gerstman (1984).

  52. Trevarthen (1979).

  53. Rochat et al. (1999, p. 951).

  54. Hayes (1984).

  55. Field (1981).

  56. Feldman (2007, p. 609).

  57. Stern (2010, p. 108).

  58. This exchange is recorded in Stern (1995, pp. 421–422).

  59. See (Murray and Trevarthen 1985; Tronick et al. 1979).

  60. Stern (1985).

  61. Tronick et al. (1998).

  62. Merleau-Ponty (1964b, p. 140).

  63. See Welsh (2007).

  64. Gallagher (2005), Bermudez (1998).

  65. See Legerstee (2005, pp. 79–82).

  66. Merleau-Ponty accepted the dominant view of his day that the body-schema is acquired, and not innate (Gallagher 2005, pp. 66–69). Accordingly, he does appear to endorse the idea that the infant initially lacks any means for distinguishing her own experiences from her environment. However, given the wealth of developmental evidence now available suggesting that the body-schema is in place at birth, he might be willing to modify his view here.

  67. Stern (1995, p. 428).

  68. Stern (1995, p. 427).

  69. This characterization seems to exclude the possibility of infant-to-infant sharing since, as we’ve seen, infants (at least early on) lack the developmental resources needed to cultivate and regulate positive affect and therefore can’t provide one another with the necessary input needed to experience shared (positive) emotions. My thanks to a reviewer for raising this point.

  70. Greenwood (2013).

  71. See Hass (2008, pp. 102–112) and Overgaard (2013) for a discussion of Merleau-Ponty’s strategy for dissolving the epistemological problem of other minds.

  72. Premack and Woodruff (1978).

  73. See, for example, Gopnik and Wellman (1992).

  74. See, for example, Goldman (2006).

  75. Gallese (2001).

  76. Gallagher and Zahavi (2008), Krueger and Overgaard (2012).

  77. Trevarthen (1979), De Jaegher and Di Paolo (2007).

  78. Gopnik (1996), Goldman (2006).

  79. Merleau-Ponty (1968). As a reviewer notes, Merleau-Ponty’s later ontology of the flesh offers additional resources for conceptualizing this sort of elemental, embodied intersubjectivity. I am in full agreement. Adequately situating JT next to this subtle ontology, however, entails careful exegesis beyond the scope of this paper. Nevertheless, one way to understand Merleau-Ponty’s JT, I submit, is to see it as a microcosm of his later work. JT is Merleau-Ponty’s attempt to work out how individual experience can harbor alterity as a constitutive feature without falling back onto the subject-object dichotomy of Cartesian metaphysics. A similar motivation informs his later ontological concerns. With this later work—and by employing ontological concepts like écart, “reversibility,” “flesh,” chiasm, etc.—Merleau-Ponty moves beyond his earlier “philosophy of consciousness,” as he refers terms it (and which presumably includes JT) to develop a more general non-Cartesian approach to the problem of Being. For a lucid discussion, see Hass (2008, pp. 100–145).

  80. Merleau-Ponty (1964a, p. 167).

  81. Tronick et al. (1998, p. 296).

  82. Zeedyk (2006).

  83. Beebe and Lachmann (1998).

  84. Merleau-Ponty (2002, p. 413)

  85. See, for example, De Jaegher and Di Paolo (2007), Froese and Di Paolo (2010).

  86. See Legerstee (2005, pp. 158–182).

  87. See Slaby (2013) for further discussion.

References

  • Alberts, E., A.F. Kalverboer, and B. Hopkins. 1983. Mother-infant dialogue in the first days of life: An observational study during breast-feeding. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry and Allied Disciplines 24(1): 145–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bates, Elizabeth, Luigia Camaioni, and Virginia Volterra. 1975. The acquisition of performatives prior to speech. Merrill Palmer Quarterly 21: 205–226.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beebe, Beatrice, and Louis Gerstman. 1984. A method of defining ‘packages’ of maternal stimulation and their functional significance for the infant with mother and stranger. International Journal of Behavioral Development 7(4): 423–440.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beebe, Beatrice, and Frank M. Lachmann. 1998. Co-constructing inner and relational processes: Self-and mutual regulation in infant research and adult treatment. Psychoanalytic Psychology 15(4): 480–516.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bermudez, Jose Luis. 1998. The paradox of self-consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/Bradford Press.

  • Butterworth, George, and Nicholas Jarrett. 1991. What minds have in common is space: Spatial mechanisms serving joint visual attention in infancy. British Journal of Developmental Psychology 9(1): 55–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, John. 2002. Reference and consciousness. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, Peter. 1989. Brute experience. The Journal of Philosophy 86(5): 258–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeCasper, Anthony J., Jean-Pierre Lecanuet, Marie-Claire Busnel, Carolyn Granier-Deferre, and Roselyne Maugeais. 1994. Fetal reactions to recurrent maternal speech. Infant Behavior and Development 17(2): 159–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eilan, Naomi. 2007. Consciousness, self-consciousness, and communication. In Reading Merleau-Ponty on phenomenology of perception, ed. Thomas Baldwin, 118–138. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, Ruth. 2007. On the origins of background emotions: From affect synchrony to symbolic expression. Emotion 7(3): 601–611.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Field, Tiffany M. 1981. Infant arousal, attention, and affect during early interactions. In Advances in infancy research, ed. Lewis P. Lipsitt and Carolyn K. Rovee-Collier, 1:57–100. Norwood, NJ: Ablex.

  • Froese, Tom, and Ezequiel A. Di Paolo. 2010. Modelling social interaction as perceptual crossing: An investigation into the dynamics of the interaction process. Connection Science 22(1): 43–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, Thomas. 2010. Phenomenology and psychopathology. In Handbook of phenomenology and cognitive science, ed. Daniel Schmicking, and Shaun Gallagher, 546–573. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, Shaun. 2005. How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Gallagher, Shaun. 2008. Intersubjectivity in perception. Continental Philosophy Review 41(2): 163–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, Shaun, and Dan Zahavi. 2008. The phenomenological mind: An introduction to philosophy of mind and cognitive science. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, Vittorio. 2001. The ‘shared manifold’ hypothesis: From mirror neurons to empathy. Journal of Consciousness Studies 8(5–7): 33–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, Alvin. 2006. Simulating minds: The philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience of mindreading. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, Alison. 1996. Theories and modules: Creation myths, developmental realities, and neurath’s boat. In Theories of theories of mind, ed. Peter Carruthers, and Peter K. Smith, 169–183. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, Alison. 2008. Why babies are more conscious than we are. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30(5–6): 503–504.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, Alison. 2009. The philosophical baby: What children’s minds tell us about truth, love, and the meaning of life. New York: Farrar Straus and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, Alison, and Henry M. Wellman. 1992. Why the child’s theory of mind really is a theory. Mind & Language 7(1–2): 145–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenwood, Jennifer. 2013. Contingent transcranialism and deep functional cognitive integration: The case of human emotional ontogenesis. Philosophical Psychology 26(3): 420–436.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gurwitsch, Aron. 1979. Human encounters in the social world. Ed. Alexandre Metraux. Trans. Fred Kersten. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.

  • Hass, Lawrence. 2008. Merleau-Ponty’s philosophy. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayes, Alan. 1984. Interaction, engagement and the origins of communication: some constructive concerns. In The origins and growth of communications, eds. Lynne Feagans, Roberta Michnick Golinkoff, and Catherine Garvey, 136–161. Norwood, NJ: Ablex.

  • Hobson, Peter. 2005. What puts jointness into joint attention? In Joint attention: Communication and other minds, ed. Naomi Eilan, Christoph Hoerl, Teresa McCormack, and Johannes Roessler, 185–204. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, Brian. 1983. The development of early non-verbal communication: An evaluation of its meaning. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry and Allied Disciplines 24(1): 131–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher, Hanne, and Ezequiel Di Paolo. 2007. Participatory sense-making. Phenomenology and the cognitive sciences 6(4): 485–507. doi:10.1007/s11097-007-9076-9.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, William. 1950. The principles of psychology, Vols. 1 and 2. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, Mark H., Suzanne Dziurawiec, Hadyn Ellis, and John Morton. 1991. Newborns’ preferential tracking of face-like stimuli and its subsequent decline. Cognition 40(1–2): 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, Susan S. 2009. The development of imitation in infancy. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B Biological Sciences 364(1528): 2325–2335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaye, Kelley L., and T.G.R. Bower. 1994. Learning and intermodal transfer of information in newborns. Psychological Science 5(5): 286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaye, Kenneth. 1982. The mental and social life of babies: How parents create persons. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krueger, Joel. 2008. Levinasian reflections on somaticity and the ethical self. Inquiry an Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 51(6): 603–626.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krueger, Joel. 2012. Seeing mind in action. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 11(2): 149–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krueger, Joel. 2013. Ontogenesis of the socially extended mind. Cognitive Systems Research 25–26: 40–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krueger, Joel, and Søren Overgaard. 2012. Seeing subjectivity: Defending a perceptual account of other minds. In ProtoSociology: Consciousness and subjectivity, Ed. Sofia Miguens and Gerhard Preyer. 47: 239–262.

  • Kugiumutzakis, Giannis, Theano Kokkinaki, Maria Makrodimitraki, and Elena Vitalaki. 2005. Emotions in early mimesis. In Emotional development: Recent research advances, ed. Jacqueline Nadel, and Darwin Muir, 161–182. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Legerstee, Maria. 1991. The role of person and object in eliciting early imitation. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology 51(3): 423–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Legerstee, Maria. 2005. Infants’ sense of people: Precursors to a theory of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Luria, Alexander R. 1973. The working brain. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lutz, Antoine, John Dunne, J. Richard, and R.J. Davidson. 2007. Meditation and the neuroscience of consciousness: An introduction. In The Cambridge handbook of consciousness, ed. Morris Moscovitch, Evan Thompson, and Philip David Zelazo, 499–545. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Malcolm, Norman. 1962. Knowledge of other minds. In The philosophy of mind, ed. Vere Claiborne Chappell. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marlier, Luc, Benoist Schaal, and Robert Soussignan. 1998. Neonatal responsiveness to the odor of amniotic and lacteal fluids: A test of perinatal chemosensory continuity. Child Development 69(3): 611–623.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff, Andrew N., and Richard W. Borton. 1979. Intermodal matching by human neonates. Nature 282(5737): 403–404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff, Andrew N., and M. Keith Moore. 1997. Explaining facial imitation: A theoretical model. Early Development and Parenting 6: 179–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 1964a. Signs. Trans. Richard C. McCleary, 1st ed. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 1964b. The child’s relations with others. In The primacy of perception, ed. James Edie, trans. William Cobb, 96–155. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 1968. The visible and the invisible. Trans. Alphonso Lingis.. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 2002. Phenomenology of perception. Trans. Colin Smith. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 2010. Child psychology and pedagogy: The sorbonne lectures 1949–1952. Trans. Talia Welsh. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mondloch, Catherine J., Terri L. Lewis, D. Robert Budreau, Daphne Maurer, James L. Dannemiller, Benjamin R. Stephens, and Kathleen A. Kleiner-Gathercoal. 1999. Face perception during early infancy. Psychological Science 10(5): 419–422.

  • Morton, John, and Mark H. Johnson. 1991. CONSPEC and CONLERN: a two-process theory of infant face recognition. Psychological Review 98(2): 164–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, Catherine M. 1978. Pointing in the context of a shared activity. Child Development 49(2): 371–380.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murray, Lynn, and Colwyn Trevarthen. 1985. Emotional regulation of interactions between two month-olds and their mothers. In Social perception in infants, ed. Tiffany M. Field, and Nathan Fox. Norwood, NJ: Ablex.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niedenthal, Paula M. 2007. Embodying emotion. Science 316(5827): 1002–1005.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neisser, Ulric. 1995. Criteria for an ecological self. In The self in infancy, ed. Philippe Rochat, 17–53. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, John. 1986. The specular body: Merleau-Ponty and Lacan on infant self and other. Synthese 66(2): 201–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Overgaard, Søren. 2007. Wittgenstein and other minds: Rethinking subjectivity and intersubjectivity with Wittgenstein, Levinas, and Husserl. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Overgaard, Søren. 2013. Other people. In The oxford handbook of contemporary phenomenology, ed. Dan Zahavi. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, Judy, and Laurel J. Trainor. 2009. Melody recognition by two-month-old infants. The Journal of the Acoustical Society of America 125(2): EL58–EL62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Posner, Michael, and Marky K. Rothbart. 1998. Attention, self-regulation, and consciousness. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B Biological Sciences 353: 1915–1927.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Premack, David, and Guy Woodruff. 1978. Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1: 515–526.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliffe, Matthew. 2008. Feelings of being: Phenomenology, psychiatry and the sense of reality, 1st ed. New York, USA: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rochat, Philippe. 2009. Others in mind: Social origins of self-consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rochat, Philippe, and Susan J. Hespos. 1997. Differential rooting response by neonates: Evidence for an early sense of self. Early Development and Parenting 6(34): 105–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rochat, Philippe (ed.). 1999. Early social cognition. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rothbart, M.K. 1989. Temperament and development. In Temperament in childhood, ed. John E. Bates, Mary Klevjord Rothbart, and Geldolph A. Kohnstamm. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, Gilbert. 1949. The concept of mind. London: Hutchins’ University Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1956. Being and nothingness. Tran. Hazel E. Barnes. New York: Washington Square Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheler, Max. 1954. The nature of sympathy. Trans. Peter Heath. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slaby, J. 2013. Emotions and the extended mind. In Collective emotions, ed. Mikko Salmela, and Christian Von Scheve. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slater, Alan, and Paul C. Quinn. 2001. Face recognition in the newborn infant. Infant and Child Development 10(1–2): 21–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, Robert. 2004. Emotions, thoughts, and feelings: Emotions and engagements with the world. In Thinking about feeling: Contemporary philosophers on emotions, ed. Robert Solomon, 76–88. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Standley, Jayne M., and Clifford K. Madsen. 1990. Comparison of infant preferences and responses to auditory stimuli: Music, mother, and other female voice. Journal of Music Therapy 27: 54–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stawarska, Beata. 2009. Between you and I: Dialogical phenomenology, 1st ed. Athens, Ohio: Ohio University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern, Daniel. 1985. The interpersonal world of the infant: A view from psychoanalysis and developmental psychology. New York: Basic books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern, Daniel. 1995. Self/other differentiation in the domain of intimate socio-affective interaction: Some considerations. In The self in infancy: Theory and research, ed. Philippe Rochat, 419–429. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stern, Daniel. 2010. Forms of vitality: Exploring dynamic experience in psychology, the arts, psychotherapy, and development. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, Evan. 2001. Empathy and consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 8(5–7): 1–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, Evan. 2007. Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Cambridge: Belknapp Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, Colwyn. 1979. Communication and cooperation in early infancy: A description of primary intersubjectivity. In Before speech: The beginning of interpersonal communication, ed. Margaret Bullowa, 321–347. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tronick, Edward. 2005. Why is connection with others so critical? The formation of dyadic states of consciousness and the expansion of individuals’ states of consciousness: Coherence governed selection and the co-creation of meaning out of messy meaning making. In Emotional development: Recent research advances, ed. Jacqueline Nadel, and Darwin Muir, 293–316. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tronick, Edward Z., Heidelise Als, and Lauren Adamson. 1979. Structure of early face-to-face communicative interactions. In Before speech: The beginning of interpersonal communication, ed. Margaret Bullowa, 349–370. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tronick, Edward Z., Nadia Bruschweiler-Stern, Alexandra M. Harrison, Karlen Lyons-Ruth, Alexander C. Morgan, Jeremy P. Nahum, Louis Sander, and Daniel N. Stern. 1998. Dyadically expanded states of consciousness and the process of therapeutic change. Infant Mental Health Journal 19(3): 290–299. doi:10.1002/(SICI)1097-0355(199823)19:3<290:AID-IMHJ4>3.0.CO;2-Q.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, Roger. 2005. Can synaesthesia be cultivated? Implications from surveys of meditators. Journal of Consciousness Studies 12(4–5): 5–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Welsh, Talia. 2007. Primal experience in Merleau-Ponty’s philosophy and psychology. Radical Psychology A Journal of Psychology Politics & Radicalism 6(1): 1–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wexler, Bruce. 2008. Brain and culture: Neurobiology, ideology, and social change. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, Dan. 2011. Empathy and direct social perception: A phenomenological proposal. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 2(3): 541–558.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zeedyk, M. Suzanne. 2006. From intersubjectivity to subjectivity: The transformative roles of emotional intimacy and imitation. Infant and Child Development 15(3): 321–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zelazo, Philip David. 1996. Towards a characterization of minimal consciousness. New Ideas in Psychology 14(1): 63–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgment

I am grateful for helpful input from an anonymous reviewer, as well as extremely helpful comments on an earlier draft of this essay from Julian Kiverstein, Giovanna Colombetti, and John Michael.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joel Krueger.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Krueger, J. Merleau-Ponty on shared emotions and the joint ownership thesis. Cont Philos Rev 46, 509–531 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-013-9278-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-013-9278-5

Keywords

Navigation