Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Habermas and Gauchet on religion in postsecular society. A critical assessment

  • Published:
Continental Philosophy Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article seeks to demonstrate that in his recent reading of the role of religion in the postsecular public realm, Habermas overlooks a most fundamental dimension of religion: its power to symbolically institute communities. For his part, Gauchet starts from a vision of religion in which this fundamental dimension is central. In his evaluation of the role of religion in postsecular society, he therefore arrives at results which are very different from those of Habermas. However, I believe that Gauchet too underestimates the extent to which religion’s power of symbolic community institution has remained intact within modern, postsecular society. In support of this position, I show how relatively heterogeneous phenomena within Western societies, such as the renewed importance of religion in the public realm, the revival of certain forms of nationalism and the associated demand for recognition of group rights and hence for forms of legal pluralism, may prefigure a new transformation of the public realm.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Cooke (2006, p. 189, 2007), Lafont (2007).

  2. Habermas (2005, p. 116).

  3. Habermas (1996, p. 5).

  4. Habermas (1996, p. 103, 1998, p. 37).

  5. Habermas (1998, pp. 43–44).

  6. Habermas (1998, p. 38), Cooke (2000, p. 953).

  7. Habermas (1998, p. 42). For the epistemic content of legal norms as the outcome of public deliberative processes, see Habermas (1996, pp. 121, 147, 151, 2005, p. 126), Cooke (2000, p. 952, 2007, p. 224), Geenens (2007, pp. 363, 365), Lafont (2007, p. 253).

  8. Habermas (2005, p. 115).

  9. Habermas (2005, pp. 116, 137).

  10. Habermas (2005, pp. 132–133).

  11. Habermas (2005, p. 133).

  12. Habermas (2005, pp. 133–134).

  13. Habermas (2005, p. 140).

  14. Habermas (2001, p. 14).

  15. Habermas (2005, p. 269).

  16. Habermas (2005, pp. 117–118, 145).

  17. Habermas (2005, pp. 137, 145).

  18. Rawls (1993, pp. 58–66).

  19. See inter al. Rawls (1993, pp. 217–218, 226).

  20. Habermas (2005, p. 133).

  21. Lafont (2007, p. 245).

  22. Habermas (2005, p. 117).

  23. See in this respect inter al. Habermas (1996, pp. 16, 18–19).

  24. Habermas (2005, p. 267).

  25. Gauchet (1997). For analyses of Gauchet’s position in contemporary French political thought, see Doyle (2003, 2006), Moyn (2004, 2005), Behrent (2004), Weymans (2005). An account of his own intellectual biography is presented in Gauchet (2003).

  26. A survey of Gauchet’s intellectual development regarding the interrelatedness of religion and politics is offered in Gauchet (2005); see also Kalyvas (1999).

  27. Gauchet (2005, pp. 12, 70). In this respect, Gauchet relies on Clastres (1974); see Gauchet (2005, pp. 91–180). For a critical assessment of Gauchet’s indebtedness to Clastres, see Moyn (2005).

  28. Gauchet (2005, pp. 64, 66).

  29. Gauchet (2005, p. 74). This idea in Gauchet resumes Lefort’s concept of ‘the political’: the underlying societal structure that institutes a particular distribution of knowledge, law and power, and which is disclosed most clearly by unravelling the symbolic structure of power (Lefort 1986, pp. 17–30, 251–300). For a discussion of the political in Lefort, see Flynn (2005, pp. 115, 121–122) and Doyle (2003, pp. 77–78).

  30. Gauchet (2005, p. 13).

  31. Gauchet (1985).

  32. Gauchet (2005, p. 18).

  33. Gauchet (2005, pp. 46, 48).

  34. Gauchet (2005, p. 64).

  35. Gauchet (2003, p. 330).

  36. Moyn (2005, p. 181).

  37. Gauchet (2005, p. 453).

  38. Gauchet (2003, p. 329).

  39. The structure of representation thus converges with the structure of the ‘original supplement’ in Derrida: the derivative (here: the state as representation of society) is the condition of possibility, and therefore the origin (!) of the original (here: society). Only through this representation does society as society come into being. In his reading of the American Declaration of Independence, Derrida has masterfully expounded this logic of representation (Derrida 1984). See Lindahl (2006, pp. 893ff.) for a similar elaboration of this logic of representation.

  40. Gauchet (2005, p. 145).

  41. Gauchet (2005, p. 74).

  42. Gauchet (1997).

  43. Gauchet (2002, pp. 335–339).

  44. Gauchet (2002, pp. 339–340).

  45. Gauchet (1998, pp. 59–60).

  46. Gauchet (1998, pp. 61–62).

  47. For a probing analysis of the nation state exhorting self-sacrificing citizens, see Anderson (1991, pp. 143–144).

  48. Gauchet (1997, p. 186).

  49. Gauchet (2002, p. 340).

  50. Gauchet (2002, pp. 344–345).

  51. Gauchet (1998, pp. 62–63).

  52. Gauchet (1998, p. 108).

  53. Gauchet (1998, p. 111).

  54. Gauchet (1998, p. 115).

  55. Gauchet (1998, p. 117).

  56. Gauchet (1998, p. 121).

  57. Gauchet (1998, p. 124).

  58. Gauchet (1998, pp. 155–156).

  59. Gauchet (1998, pp. 121–124).

  60. Gauchet (1998, pp. 129–133).

  61. Gauchet (1998, pp. 143–151).

  62. Gauchet (2002, p. ix).

  63. Habermas (2005, pp. 119–154), Gauchet (1998).

  64. Gauchet (1997, pp. 200–207), Ferry and Gauchet (2004).

  65. In this respect Gauchet (1998, p. 11) states clearly: “In one word, we have metaphysically become democrat.”

  66. Anderson (1991, pp. 5, 10–12).

  67. Anderson (1991, pp. 143–144).

  68. The classical (religious) example of such a ‘community of destiny’ is of course the Jewish people, but one could easily understand Serbian, Russian or even American nationalism along the same lines.

  69. Young (1997, p. 402).

  70. Habermas (1998, pp. 205–210, 2005, pp. 277, 305).

  71. Taylor (1995, pp. 255–256).

  72. Taylor (1995, p. 248).

References

  • Anderson, Benedict. 1991. Imagined communities. Reflections on the origin and spread of nationalism. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Behrent, Michael. 2004. Religion, republicanism, and depoliticization. Two intellectual itineraries—Régis Debray and Marcel Gauchet. In After the Deluge. New perspectives on the Intellectual and Cultural History of Postwar France, ed. Julian Bourg, 325–349. Lanham, Maryland: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clastres, Pierre. 1974. La société contre l’État. Paris: Minuit.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooke, Maeve. 2000. Five arguments for deliberative democracy. Political Studies 48: 947–969.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooke, Maeve. 2006. Salvaging and secularizing the semantic contents of religion. The limitiations of Habermas’s postmetaphysical proposal. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 60: 187–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooke, Maeve. 2007. A secular state for a postsecular society? Postmetaphysical political theory and the place of religion. Constellations 14: 224–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, Jacques. 1984. Otobiographies. L’enseignement de Nietzsche et la politique du nom propre. Paris: Galilée.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doyle, Nathalie. 2003. Democracy as socio-cultural project of individual and collective sovereignty. Claude Lefort, Marcel Gauchet and the French debate on modern autonomy. Thesis Eleven 75: 69–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doyle, Nathalie. 2006. The sacred, social creativity and the state. Critical Horizons 7: 207–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Flynn, Bernard. 2005. The philosophy of Claude Lefort. Interpreting the political. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferry, Luc, and Marcel Gauchet. 2004. Le Religieux après la religion. Paris: Grasset et Fasquelle.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauchet, Marcel. 1985. Le désenchantement du monde. Une histoire politique de la religion. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauchet, Marcel. 1997. The disenchantment of the world. A political history of religion. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauchet, Marcel. 1998. La religion dans la démocratie. Parcours de la laïcité. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauchet, Marcel. 2002. La démocratie contre elle-même. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauchet, Marcel. 2003. La condition historique. Entretiens avec François Azouvi et Sylvain Piron. Paris: Stock.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauchet, Marcel. 2005. La condition politique. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geenens, Raf. 2007. The deliberative model of democracy. Two critical remarks. Ratio Juris 20: 355–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1996. Between facts and norms. Contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1998. The inclusion of the other. Studies in political theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 2001. Glauben und Wissen. Friedenspreis des Deutschen Buchhandels 2001. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 2005. Zwischen Naturalismus und Religion. Philosophische Aufsätze. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kalyvas, Andreas. 1999. Democracy’s lifecycle? Marcel Gauchet on religion and politics. European Journal of Social Theory 2: 485–496.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lafont, Christina. 2007. Religion in the public sphere. Remarks on Habermas’s conception of public deliberation in postsecular societies. Constellations 14: 239–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lefort, Claude. 1986. Essais sur le politique. XIXe-XXe siècles. Paris: Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindahl, Hans. 2006. Give and take: Arendt and the Nomos of political community. Philosophy and Social Criticism 32: 881–901.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moyn, Samuel. 2004. Of savagery and civil society. Pierre Clastres and the transformation of French political thought. Modern Intellectual History 1: 55–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moyn, Samuel. 2005. Savage and modern liberty. Marcel Gauchet and the origins of new French thought. European Journal of Political Theory 4: 164–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1993. Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 1995. Philosophical arguments. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, Iris Marion. 1997. Difference as a resource for democratic communication. In Deliberative democracy. Essays on reason and politics, ed. James Bohman and William Rehg, 388–406. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weymans, Wim. 2005. Freedom through political representation. Lefort, Gauchet and Rosanvallon on the relationship between state and society. European Journal of Political Theory 4: 263–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Antoon Braeckman.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Braeckman, A. Habermas and Gauchet on religion in postsecular society. A critical assessment. Cont Philos Rev 42, 279–296 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-009-9108-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-009-9108-y

Keywords

Navigation