Skip to main content
Log in

What Should I Believe About What Would Have Been the Case?

  • Published:
Journal of Philosophical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The question I am addressing in this paper is the following: how is it possible to empirically test, or confirm, counterfactuals? After motivating this question in Section 1, I will look at two approaches to counterfactuals, and at how counterfactuals can be empirically tested, or confirmed, if at all, on these accounts in Section 2. I will then digress into the philosophy of probability in Section 3. The reason for this digression is that I want to use the way observable absolute and relative frequencies, two empirical notions, are used to empirically test, or confirm, hypotheses about objective chances, a metaphysical notion, as a role-model. Specifically, I want to use this probabilistic account of the testing of chance hypotheses as a role-model for the account of the testing of counterfactuals, another metaphysical notion, that I will present in Sections 4 to 8. I will conclude by comparing my proposal to one non-probabilistic and one probabilistic alternative in Section 9.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. On the account of testing envisaged by [52] and sketched above one cannot distinguish between confirmation for a counterfactual of the form ‘if the value of F were set to f, then the value of G would change to g’ and confirmation for a counterfactual of the form ‘if the value of F were set to f, then the probability or chance that the value of G is g would change to 1’.

  2. Briggs [8], Galles & Pearl [15], Halpern [17], Zhang [53], and Zhang & Lam & De Clercq [54] give us a precise semantics for counterfactuals. However, they all seem to understand the variables in a singular sense. Therefore [52]’s account of testing is not available to them.

  3. The Straight Rule, and hence the Axiom of Converge or Reichenbach Axiom, does not enable us to learn hypotheses about objective chances. As is well known, though, it can be reformulated as a rule for inferring limiting relative frequencies. Then one can show that it eventually conjectures values that are arbitrarily close to the limiting relative frequencies in the actual world, provided the latter exist.

  4. I will mostly ignore contexts, as the context sensitivity of counterfactuals does not play a role for the purposes of this paper.

  5. Strictly speaking this notion of admissibility is relative to a context c, just as the notion of admissibility in the Principal Principle is relative to a point of time t. And strictly speaking one needs to assume that the presuppositions of a given context are admissible in this context, and that the world’s theory of deterministic alethic modality, or counterfactuality, is admissible in all contexts. However, the context sensitivity of counterfactuals does not play a role for present purposes, and so the presuppositions of all contexts can be assumed to be tautological. It is perhaps worth noting that history up to some time is a context. For details see ([26]: Section 4).

  6. Spohn ([47]: Chapter 12) proves many much more impressive results that are related to the Obvious Observation. However, the mathematics is not exactly the same, and the interpretation is entirely different. I presently cannot relate his results to mine in an illuminating way.

  7. For the relationship between rank-theoretic typicality or rank-theoretic normality, causation, and counterfactuals see [16, 18, 19, 25].

  8. In general the functions Y i need not have the same index set I as the first family (X i ) iI . Nor do they have to have a common range 𝓨 and associated algebra 𝓥. However, this is the special case we are interested in.

  9. Leitgeb’s [28, 29] probabilistic analysis of counterfactuals requires Pr(CA) = 1 for A ⎕→ C to be true, where Pr is a Popper-Rényi measure ([40, 42]) that is interpreted objectively as time-relative conditional single case chance. Independence in the sense of a Popper-Rényi measure Pr is a relation between three propositions: A is independent of B conditional on C just in case Pr(ABC) = Pr(AC)⋅ Pr(BC) ([43]: 103). Counterfactual independence is a relation between two propositions. Therefore the definition of independence in the sense of a Popper-Rényi measure has to be modified so that it becomes a relation between two propositions A and B. It is tempting to say that A is independent of B just in case A is independent of B conditional on the set of all possible worlds, the tautological proposition W. However, on Leitgeb’s logic of counterfactuals, just as on ours, ⊤ ⎕→ α is not logically equivalent to α. Therefore this temptation should be resisted. There are other options for modifying independence in the sense of a Popper-Rényi measure so that it becomes a relation between two propositions (see [14]). However, without stipulating which modification one chooses there are no formal relations between counterfactual independence, which relates two propositions, and independence in the sense of a Popper-Rényi measure Pr, which relates three propositions. Another complication may arise from a negative answer to the question whether the set of propositions for which time-relative conditional single case chances are defined is as rich as the set of propositions which can figure in the consequent of a counterfactual.

  10. The comparison to [5] is complicated by the fact that the latter works with a multidimensional possible worlds semantics.

  11. Modal logicians might be interested in the fact that this provides an example of a sentence α such that: ⊩□α and ⊯ α.

References

  1. Adams, E.W. (1998). A Primer of Probability Logic. CLSI Publications: Stanford.

  2. Alchourrón, C.E, Gärdenfors, P., Makinson, D. (1985). On the logic of theory change: partial meet contraction and revision functions. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 50, 510–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Baumgartner, M., & Glynn, L. (2013). Introduction to special issue on ‘Actual Causation’. Erkenntnis, 78, 1–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Boutilier, C. (1996). Iterated revision and minimal change of belief. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 25, 263–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Bradley, R. (2012). Multidimensional possible-world semantics for conditionals. Philosophical Review, 121, 539–571.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Brössel, P., Eder, A.-M., Huber, F. (2013). Evidential support and instrumental rationality. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 87, 279–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Briggs, R. (2009). The big bad bug bites anti-realists about chance. Synthese, 167, 81–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Briggs, R. (2012). Interventionist counterfactuals. Synthese, 160, 139–166.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Carnap, R. (1980). A basic system of inductive logic, Part 2 In R. C. Jeffrey (Ed.) Studies in Inductive Logic and Probability (Vol. II, pp. 7–155). Berkeley: University of Berkeley Press.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Collins, J., Hall, N., Paul, L.A. (2004). Causation and Counterfactuals. Cambridge: MIT Press.

  11. Darwiche, A., & Pearl, J. (1997). On the logic of iterated belief revision. Artificial Intelligence, 89, 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Earman, J. (1992). Bayes or Bust? A Critical Examination of Bayesian Confirmation Theory. Cambridge: MIT Press.

  13. Edgington, D. (2008). Counterfactuals. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 108, 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Fitelson, B., & Hájek, A (ms). Declarations of Independence.

  15. Galles, D., & Pearl, J. (1998). An axiomatic characterization of causal counterfactuals. Foundations of Science, 1, 151–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Halpern, J.Y. (2008). Defaults and normality in causal structures. In Proceedings of the Eleventh International Conference on Principles of Knowledge Representation and Reasoning (KR 2008) (pp 198–208).

  17. Halpern, J.Y. (2013). From causal models to counterfactual structures. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 6, 305–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Halpern, J.Y., & Hitchcock, C.R. (2010). Actual Causation and the Art of Modelling In R. Dechter, H. Geffner, J. Halpern (Eds.), Heuristics, Probability, and Causality (pp. 383–406). London: College Publications.

  19. Halpern, J.Y., & Hitchcock, C.R. (2013). Compact representations of extended causal models. Cognitive Science, 37, 986–1010.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Hild, M., & Spohn, W. (2008). The measurement of ranks and the laws of iterated contraction. Artificial Intelligence, 172, 1195–1218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Hintikka, J. (1961). Knowledge and Belief. An Introduction to the Logic of the Two Notions. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

  22. Huber, F. (2007). The consistency argument for ranking functions. Studia Logica, 86, 299–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Huber, F. (2013a). Belief revision I: the AGM theory. Philosophy Compass, 8, 604–612.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Huber, F. (2013b). Belief revision II: ranking theory. Philosophy Compass, 8, 613–621.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Huber, F. (2013c). Structural equations and beyond. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 6, 709–732.

  26. Huber, F. (2014). New foundations for counterfactuals. Synthese.

  27. Jeffrey, R.C. (1970). Dracula meets Wolfman: acceptance vs. partial belief In M. Swain (Ed.), Induction, Acceptance, and Rational Belief (pp. 157–185). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

  28. Leitgeb, H. (2012a). A probabilistic semantics for counterfactuals. Part A. Review of Symbolic Logic, 5, 26–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Leitgeb, H. (2012b). A probabilistic semantics for counterfactuals. Part B. Review of Symbolic Logic, 5, 85–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Leitgeb, H. (2013). Reducing belief simpliciter to degrees of belief. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 164, 1338–1389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Lewis, D.K. (1973). Counterfactuals. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  32. Lewis, D.K. (1979). Counterfactual dependence and time’s arrow. Noûs, 13, 455–476.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Lewis, D.K. (1980). A subjectivist’s guide to objective chance In R. C. Jeffrey (Ed.) Studies in Inductive Logic and Probability (Vol. II, pp. 263–293). Berkeley: University of Berkeley Press.

  34. Lin, H., & Kelly, K.T. (2012). Propositional reasoning that tracks probabilistic reasoning. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 41, 957–981.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Mumford, S. (1998). Dispositions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  36. Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical Explanations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  37. Paul, L.A. (2000). Aspect causation. Journal of Philosophy, XCVII, 235–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Pearl, J. (2009). Causality: Models, Reasoning, and Inference (2nd edn.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  39. Percival, P. (2002). Epistemic consequentialism. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary 76, 121–151.

  40. Popper, K.R. (1955). Two autonomous axiom systems for the calculus of probabilities. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 6, 51–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  41. Reichenbach, H. (1939). Experience and Prediction. An Analysis of the Foundations and the Structure of Knowledge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Rényi, A. (1955). On a new axiomatic system for probability. Acta Mathematica Academiae Scientiarum Hungaricae, 6, 285–335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  43. Rényi, A. (1970). Foundations of Probability. San Francisco: Holden-Day.

  44. Spirtes, P., Glymour, C., Scheines, R. (2000). Causation, Prediction, and Search(2nd edn.). Cambridge: MIT Press.

  45. Spohn, W. (1988). Ordinal conditional functions: a dynamic theory of epistemic states In W. L. Harper, & B. Skyrms (Eds.), Causation in Decision, Belief Change, and Statistics (Vol. II, pp. 105–134). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  46. Spohn, W. (2010). Chance and necessity: From humean supervenience to humean projection In E. Eells, & J. Fetzer (Eds.), The Place of Probability in Science. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science (Vol. 284, pp. 101–131). Dordrecht: Springer.

  47. Spohn, W. (2012). The Laws of Belief. Ranking Theory and its Philosophical Applications. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  48. Spohn, W. (2013). A ranking-theoretic approach to conditionals. Cognitive Science, 37, 1074–1106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  49. Stalnaker, R.C. (1968). A theory of conditionals In N. Rescher (Ed.), Studies in Logical Theory. American Philosophical Quarterly Monograph Series (Vol. 2, pp. 98–112). Oxford: Blackwell.

  50. Stalnaker, R.C. (2002). Epistemic consequentialism. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary 76, 153–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  51. Van Fraassen (1977). Relative frequencies. Synthese, 34, 133–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  52. Woodward, J.F. (2003). Making Things Happen. New York: Oxford University Press.

  53. Zhang, J. (2013). A lewisian logic of causal counterfactuals. Minds and Machines, 23, 77–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  54. Zhang, J., Lam, W.-Y., De Clercq, R. (2013). A peculiarity in pearl’s logic of interventionist counterfactuals. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 42, 783–794.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am very grateful to an anonymous referee, Alan Hájek, Christopher R. Hitchcock, Hannes Leitgeb, Timothy Williamson, and, especially, to Wolfgang Spohn for many most helpful comments and suggestions on several earlier versions of this paper

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Franz Huber.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Huber, F. What Should I Believe About What Would Have Been the Case?. J Philos Logic 44, 81–110 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-014-9314-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-014-9314-x

Keywords

Navigation