Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

A Historical Perspective on the Distinction Between Basic and Applied Science

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The traditional distinction between basic (“pure”) and applied science has been much criticized in recent decades. The criticism is based on a combination of historical and systematic epistemic argument. The present paper is mostly concerned with the historical aspect. I argue that the critics impose an understanding at odds with the way the distinction was understood by its supporters in debates on science education and science policy in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. And I show how a distinction that refers to difference on several epistemic and social dimensions makes good sense of representative historical cases. If this argument is tenable it suggests more continuity in the epistemology and politics of science than has been claimed by a new paradigm of science studies and politics during recent decades.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. His concept draws on Herbert Simon’s The Sciences of the Artificial (1969) and Georg Henrik von Wright’s concept of “technological norm” (von Wright 1963).

  2. “Focus: Applied Science.” Isis 103 (2012), pp. 515–563.

  3. Emphasis in original.

  4. The Organization for Economic Cooperation and Development (OECD) was founded in 1961 to promote international coordination of technological and economic development.

  5. Douglas (2009, 2014) and Kitcher (2001, 2004) do not discuss the OECD R&D classification. Other publications like Gibbons et al. (1994), Guston (2000), Nowotny et al. (2001), Nordmann et al. (2011) likewise gives little if any attention. Stokes (1997) and Niiniluoto (2013), however, explicitly discuss it.

  6. According to the 1981 edition of the Frascati Manual: “Experimental development is systematic work, drawing on existing knowledge gained from research and/or practical experience that is directed to producing new materials, products or devices, to installing new processes, systems and services, or to improving substantially those already produced or installed” (OECD 1981, p. 25).

  7. The classical locus for this distinction is philosopher Wilhelm Windelband’s inauguration speech as rector of the Kaiser-Wilhelm-Universität Strassburg, 1. May 1894.

References

  • Barker, G., & Kitcher, P. (2013). Philosophy of science. A new introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bentley, P. J., Gulbrandsen, M., & Kyvik, S. (2016). The relationship between basic and applied research in universities. Higher Education, 70, 689–709.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernal, J. D. (1939). The social function of science. NewYork: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biffen, R. H. (1917). Systematized plant breeding. In Seward 1917 (pp. 146–175).

  • Broberg, G., & Roll-Hansen, N. (1996). Eugenics and the welfare state. Sterilization policy in Denmark, Sweden, Norway, and Finland (2nd edition with a new preface 2005). East Lansing: Michigan State University Press.

  • Bucharin, N. I. (1931). Theory and practice from the standpoint of dialectical materialism. In N. I. Bucharin et al. (Eds.) Science at the cross roads. London: Frank Cass (Second edition 1971 with new foreword by Joseph Needham and new introduction by P.G. Werskey).

  • Bud, R. (2012). ‘Applied Science’. A phrase in search of meaning. Isis, 103, 537–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Calvert, J. (2004). The idea of ‘Basic Research’ in language and practice. Minerva, 42, 251–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, S. (2010). Pure science with a practical aim: The meanings of fundamental research in Britain, circa 1916–1950. Isis, 101, 285–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1927). The public and its problems. London: George Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2009). Science, policy, and the value-free ideal. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2014). Pure science and the problem of progress. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 46, 55–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edgerton, D. (2002). ‘The Linear Model’ did not exist. In K. Grandin, N. Wormbs, & S. Widmalm (Eds.), The science-industry nexus. History, policy, implications (pp. 31–57). New York: Science History Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forman, P. (2007). The primacy of science in modernity, of technology in postmodernity, and of ideology in the history of technology. History and Technology, 23, 1–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbons, M., Limoges, C., Nowotny, H., Schwartzman, S., Scott, P., & Trow, M. (1994). The new production of knowledge: The dynamics of science and research in contemporary societies. London: Sage Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbons, M., Limoges, C., & Scott, P. (2011). Revisiting Mode 2 at Noor’s slott. Prometheus, 29, 361–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godin, B. (2005). Measurement and statistics on science and technology. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godin, B. (2015). Innovation contested: The idea of innovation over the centuries. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gooday, G. (2012). ’Vague and Artificial’. The historically elusive distinction between pure and applied science. Isis, 103, 546–554.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gulbrandsen, M., & Kyvik, S. (2010). Are the concepts of basic research, applied research and experimental development still useful? An empirical investigation among Norwegian academics. Science and Public Policy, 37, 343–353.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gulbrandsen, M., & Langfeldt, L. (2004). In search of ‘Mode 2’: The nature of knowledge production in Norway. Minerva, 42, 237–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guston, D. (2000). Between science and politics. Assuring integrity and productivity of research. Cambrige: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hamlin, C. (2016). The pedagogical roots of the history of science: Revisiting the vision of James Bryant Conant. Isis, 107, 282–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harwood, J. (2015). Did Mendelism transform plant breeding? Genetic theory and breeding practice. In D. Philips & S. Kingsley (Eds.), New perspectives on the history of life sciences and agriculture (pp. 345–370). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965). Science and human values. In C. G. Hempel (Ed.), Aspects of explanation, and other essays in the philosophy of science (pp. 81–96). New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, F. G. (1917). Medicine and experimental science. In Seward 1917 (pp. 228–255).

  • Huxley, T. H. (1881). Science and culture. In T. H. Huxley (Ed.), Science and culture, and other essays (pp. 1–23). London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huxley, J. S. (1934). Scientific research and social needs. London: Watts & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1997). An argument about free inquiry. Noûs, 31(1997), 279–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2001). Science, truth, and democracy. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2004). On the autonomy of the sciences. Philosophy Today, Supplement 2004 (New directions in the philosophy of science): 51–57.

  • Kitcher, P. (2011a). Science in a democratic society. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2011b). Second thoughts. In W. J. Gozalez (Ed.), Scientific realism and democratic society: The philosophy of Philip Kitcher (pp. 353–389). Amsterdam: Rodipi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lucier, P. (2012). The origins of pure and applied science in gilded age America. Isis, 103, 527–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meinel, C. (1985). Reine und angewandte Chemie. Die Entstehung einer neuen Wissenschaftskonzeption in der Chemie der Aufklärung. Berichte zur Wissenschaftsgeschichte, 8, 25–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merton, R. (1938). Science and the social order. Philosophy of Science 5: 321–37. Reprinted in Merton (1968) The sociology of science (pp. 254–264). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Moulton, J. F. (1917). Introduction. In Seward 1917 (pp. iix–xx).

  • Niiniluoto, I. (1993). The aim and structure of applied research. Erkenntnis, 38, 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (2013). On the philosophy of applied social sciences. In H. Andersen et al. (Eds.), New challenges to philosophy of science. The philosophy of science in a European perspective 4 (pp. 265–274). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (2014). Values in design sciences. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 46, 11–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nordmann, A. (2011). The age of technoscience. In Normann et al (pp. 18–30).

  • Nordmann, A., Radder, H., & Schiemann, G. (Eds.). (2011). Science transformed? Debating claims of an epochal break. Pittsburgh PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nowotny, H., Scott, P., & Gibbons, M. (2001). Re-thinking science. Knowledge and the public in an age of uncertainty. Oxford: Polity Press/Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • OECD. (1981). The measurement of scientific and technical activities. Paris 1981. Fourth edition of the “Frascati Manual.”

  • OECD. (2015). The measurement of scientific, technological and innovation activities: Frascati manual 2015: Guidelines for collecting and reporting data on research and experimental development. Paris: OECD.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rip, A. (2011). The future of research universities. Prometheus, 29, 443–453.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roll-Hansen, N. (2005). The Lysenko effect: Undermining the autonomy of science. Endeavour, 29(December 2005), 143–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roll-Hansen, N. (2009). Eugenics and the science of genetics. In A. Bashford & P. Levine (Eds.), Handbook of the history of eugenics (pp. 80–97). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roll-Hansen, N. (2015). On the philosophical roots of today’s science policy: Any lessons from the ‘Lysenko affair’? Studies in East European Thought, 67, 91–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowland, H. (1883). A plea for pure science. Science, 2, 242–250.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rudner, R. (1953). The scientist Qua scientist makes value judgements. Philosophy of Science, 20, 1–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schiemann, G. (2011). We are not witnesses to a new scientific revolution. In Nordmann et al. 2011 (pp. 31–42).

  • Seward, A. C. (Ed.). (1917). Science and the nation. Essays by Cambridge graduates with an introduction by the Right Hon. Lord Moulton, K.C.B., F.R.S. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. (1969). The sciences of the artificial (2nd ed.). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stokes, D. E. (1997). Pasteur’s quadrant. Basic science and technological innovation. Washington, D.C.: Brookings Institution Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Wright, G. H. (1963). Norm and action. London: Routledge and Keagan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nils Roll-Hansen.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Roll-Hansen, N. A Historical Perspective on the Distinction Between Basic and Applied Science. J Gen Philos Sci 48, 535–551 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-017-9362-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-017-9362-3

Keywords

Navigation