Skip to main content
Log in

Is Explanatoriness a Guide to Confirmation? A Reply to Climenhaga

  • Discussion
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We (2013, 2014) argued that explanatoriness is evidentially irrelevant in the following sense: Let H be a hypothesis, O an observation, and E the proposition that H would explain O if H and O were true. Then our claim is that Pr(H | O & E) = Pr(H | O). We defended this screening-off thesis (SOT) by discussing an example concerning smoking and cancer. Climenhaga (Philos Sci, forthcoming) argues that SOT is mistaken because it delivers the wrong verdict about a slightly different smoking-and-cancer case. He also considers a variant of SOT, called “SOT*”, and contends that it too gives the wrong result. We here reply to Climenhaga’s arguments and suggest that SOT provides a criticism of the widely held theory of inference called “inference to the best explanation”.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. McCain and Poston (2014) miss this point. They grant that SOT is true in certain cases, but contend that even in those cases explanatoriness is evidentially relevant because it affects what they term “weight of evidence”, which they say bears on a probability’s “resilience”.

  2. McCain and Poston miss this point; see Roche and Sober (2014, p. 197) for discussion. In Sect. 4, we consider a variant of E.

  3. We do not mean “realistic in all respects” since we assume that logical omniscience holds in the cases in question. However, this idealization is harmless, for if the assumption of logical omniscience were dropped, then a thesis similar to SOT would hold. See Roche and Sober (2014, p. 195) for discussion.

  4. We assume that explanatoriness can be informative to logically omniscient subjects. This should be uncontroversial. E is not a logical truth in the example about Joe. Note that in cases where E is a logical truth, SOT is trivially true.

  5. All references to Climenhaga are to Climenhaga (forthcoming).

  6. Climenhaga’s official formulation of SOT* (p. 5) involves the expression “for all K” where K is the background information. We take this to be a slip, for SOT* thus formulated is trivially false.

  7. The same is true of any alternative assumption on which Pr(~C 1 | Ca) equals 0 and Ca entails Sm.

  8. It is controversial how estimation problems should be solved. Broadly speaking, there are Bayesian and frequentist approaches. See Howson and Urbach (1993) for a Bayesian perspective and Romeijn (2016) for discussion of maximum likelihood estimation. For discussion of statistical decision theory, see Vassend, Sober, and Fitelson (2017).

  9. Climenhaga notes in effect (footnote 9) that it is not true in general that Pr(Sm | Ca) equals the sample frequency of people who smoke among people who get cancer. We are not claiming otherwise. Our claim, rather, is that Pr(Sm | Ca) equals your estimate of the population frequency of people who smoke among people who get cancer.

  10. Sober uses this example against Reichenbach’s principle of the common cause. For discussion and references, see, in addition to Sober (2001), Sober (2008, 2015).

  11. The assumption of monotonicity is inessential. See Sober (2001, Sec. 3). For a gaggle of real-world counterexamples to (**), see Vigen (2015).

  12. It might seem that Sober (2001, p. 343) believes otherwise. But there he has in mind cases where Pr(CC) ≥ Pr(SC).

  13. The same is true with respect to CSOT and a theory defended by Douven and Wenmackers (2015, p. 5) according to which, roughly, if you learn O, and also learn that H is the best explanation (in a partition of hypotheses) of O, then H gets a probabilistic bonus in that your new probability for H should exceed your old conditional probability for H given O.

  14. IBE-ists often hold that IBE is a successful theory of inference when the explanations in question are causal; see Lipton (2004) and Lycan (2002, p. 413).

References

  • Climenhaga, N. (forthcoming). How explanation guides confirmation. Philosophy of Science.

  • Douven, I., & Wenmackers, S. (2015). Inference to the best explanation versus Bayes’s rule in a social setting. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. doi:10.1093/bjps/axv025.

  • Howson, C., & Urbach, P. (1993). Scientific reasoning: The Bayesian approach (2nd ed.). Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the best explanation (2nd ed.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. (2002). Explanation and epistemology. In P. Moser (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of epistemology (pp. 408–433). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McCain, K., & Poston, T. (2014). Why explanatoriness is evidentially irrelevant. Thought, 3, 145–153.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2007). The fine structure of Inference to the Best Explanation. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 74, 441–448.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roche, W., & Sober, E. (2013). Explanatoriness is evidentially irrelevant, or inference to the best explanation meets Bayesian confirmation theory. Analysis, 73, 659–668.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roche, W., & Sober, E. (2014). Explanatoriness and evidence: A reply to McCain and Poston. Thought, 3, 193–199.

    Google Scholar 

  • Romeijn, J. (2016). Philosophy of statistics. In E. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2016 ed). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/statistics/.

  • Sober, E. (2001). Venetian sea levels, British bread prices, and the principle of the common cause. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 52, 331–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (2008). Evidence and evolution: The logic behind the science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (2015). Ockham’s razors: A user’s manual. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vassend, O., Sober, E., & Fitelson, B. (2017). The philosophical significance of Stein’s Paradox. European Journal for Philosophy of Science. doi:10.1007/s13194-016-0168-7.

  • Vigen, T. (2015). Spurious correlations. New York: Hachette Books.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to an anonymous referee for a helpful comment on a prior version of the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to William Roche.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Roche, W., Sober, E. Is Explanatoriness a Guide to Confirmation? A Reply to Climenhaga. J Gen Philos Sci 48, 581–590 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-016-9357-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-016-9357-5

Keywords

Navigation