Skip to main content
Log in

The Norton Dome and the Nineteenth Century Foundations of Determinism

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The recent discovery of an indeterministic system in classical mechanics, the Norton dome, has shown that answering the question whether classical mechanics is deterministic can be a complicated matter. In this paper I show that indeterministic systems similar to the Norton dome were already known in the nineteenth century: I discuss four nineteenth century authors who wrote about such systems, namely Poisson, Duhamel, Boussinesq and Bertrand. However, I argue that their discussion of such systems was very different from the contemporary discussion about the Norton dome, because physicists in the nineteenth century conceived of determinism in essentially different ways: whereas in the contemporary literature on determinism in classical physics, determinism is usually taken to be a property of the equations of physics, in the nineteenth century determinism was primarily taken to be a presupposition of theories in physics, and as such it was not necessarily affected by the possible existence of systems such as the Norton dome.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Boussinesq (1879a) also mentions Cournot as an author who discussed such indeterministic systems, referring to (Cournot 1841). But in fact, Cournot only discusses the problem of uniqueness of solutions to differential equations on a mathematical level, without relating it to problems in physics. Therefore his discussion does not tell us anything about his ideas on the issue of determinism in physics; for that reason I will not discuss it here.

  2. This term is introduced by Korolev (2007).

  3. The similarity between Poisson and Zinkernagel is also pointed out in Fletcher (2012).

  4. Duhamel (1797–1872) was at this time professor of mathematics at the École Polytechnique and member of the Académie des Sciences. See O’Connor and Robertson (2005a).

  5. Boussinesq (1842–1929) was at that time professor of mathematics at the Faculté des Sciences in Lille (Nye 1976). He is mainly known for his work in hydrodynamics, heat and light.

  6. About Boussinesq’s free will theory in its historical context, see Nye (1976), Hacking (1983) and Porter (1986). See also Israel (1992).

  7. Boussinesq emphasizes that singularies only arise for “les valeurs très-spéciales de A ou par suite de c 2”, where \(c=r^2\frac{d\theta}{d t}\) (Boussinesq 1879a, p. 104).

  8. Fletcher (2012) mentions that Boussinesq used systems similar to the Norton dome as a basis for a theory about free will, and adds in a footnote: “He did not, however, investigate how ubiquitous such systems might be”. However, Boussinesq put much effort in investigating exactly this issue, and had detailed ideas about the probability with which such systems can be expected to appear in reality.

  9. Bertrand (1822–1900) had been a pupil of Duhamel, and was at this time professor in mathematics at the Collège du France and the École Polytechnique, and secretary of the Académie des Sciences. See O’Connor and Robertson (2005b).

  10. That this can make indeterminism disappear is demonstrated in Zinkernagel (2010) who shows that the difference equation for the dome, contrary to the differential equation, does have a unique solution.

References

  • Arnold, V. I. (1989). Mathematical methods of classical mechanics (2nd ed.). New York: Springer. (Translation: K. Vogtmann & A. Weinstein).

  • Bertrand, J. L. F. (1878). Conciliation du véritable déterminisme mécanique avec l’existence de la vie et de la liberté morale, par J. Boussinesq. Journal des Savants, 1878, 517–523.

  • Boussinesq, J. (1879a). Conciliation du véritable déterminisme mécanique avec l’existence de la vie et de la liberté morale. Mémoires de la société des sciences, de l’agriculture et des arts de Lille, 6(4), 1–257.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boussinesq, J. (1879b). Le déterminisme et la liberté—Lettre au directeur du Journal des Savants. Revue Philosophique de la France et de l’Étranger, 7, 58–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brush, S.G. (1976). The kind of motion we call heat (Vols. 1 & 2). Amsterdam: North Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callender, C. (1995). The metaphysics of time reversal: Hutchison on classical mechanics. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 46(3), 331–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cournot, A. A. (1841). Traité élémentaire de la théorie des fonctions et du calcul infinitésimal (Vol. 2). Paris: L. Hachette.

  • Dahan Dalmedico, A. (1992). Le déterminisme de Pierre-Simon Laplace et le déterminisme aujourd’hui. In A. Dahan Dalmedico, J.-L. Chambert & K. Chemla (Eds.), Chaos et déterminisme. Paris: Éditions du Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deakin, M.A.B. (1988). Nineteenth century anticipations of modern theory of dynamical systems. Archive for History of the Exact Sciences, 39, 183–194.

    Google Scholar 

  • Du Bois-Reymond, E. (1880). Die sieben Welträtsel. In E. Du Bois-Reymond (Eds.), Über die Grenzen des Naturerkennens—Die sieben Welträtsel. Leipzig: Verlag Von Veit & Comp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhamel, J.M.C. (1845). Cours de mécanique de l’école polytechnique (Vol. 1). Paris: Bachelier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J. (1986). A primer on determinism. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher, S. (2012). What counts as a Newtonian system? The view from Norton’s dome. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 2(3), 275–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1983). Nineteenth century cracks in the concept of determinism. Journal of the History of Ideas, 44(3), 455–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, R. (2005). Pierre Simon Laplace, 1749–1827: A determined scientist. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchison, K. (1993). Is classical mechanics really time-reversible and deterministic? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 44(2), 307–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Israel, G. (1992). L’histoire du principe du déterminisme et ses rencontres avec les mathématiques. In A. Dahan Dalmedico, J.-L. Chabert & K. Chemla (Eds.), Chaos et déterminisme. Paris: Éditions du Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kline, M. (1972). Mathematical thought from ancient to modern times. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korolev, A. (2007). Indeterminism, asymptotic reasoning, and time irreversibility in classical physics. Philosophy of science, 74, 943–956.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korolev, A. (unpublished). The Norton-type Lipschitz-indeterministic systems and elastic phenomena: Indeterminism as an artefact of infinite idealizations. In Philosophy of Science Association 21st Biennial Mtg (Pittsburgh, PA): PSA 2008 Contributed Papers. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/4314/.

  • Landau, L. D., & Lifshitz, E. M. (1976). Mechanics—course of theoretical physics (3rd edn., Vol. 1). Oxford: Pergamon. (Translation: J. B. Sykes & J. S. Bell).

  • Laplace, P.-S. (1772). Mémoire sur les solutions particulières des équations différentielles et sur les inégalités séculaires des planètes. Oeuvres complètes, 8, 325–366.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laplace, P.-S. (1814). Essai philosophique sur les probabilités. Courcier: Paris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipschitz, M.R. (1876). Sur la possibilité d’intégrer complétement un système donné d’équations différentielles. Bulletin des sciences mathématiques et astronomiques, 10(1), 149–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malament, D.B. (2008). Norton’s slippery slope. Philosophy of Science, 75, 799–816.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. (2003). Causation as Folk science. Philosopher’s Imprint, 3(4), 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. (2008). The dome: An unexpectedly simple failure of determinism. Philosophy of Science, 75, 786–798.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nye, M.J. (1976). The moral freedom of man and the determinism of nature: The Catholic synthesis of science and history in the “Revue des questions scientifiques”. British Journal for the History of Science, 9(3), 274–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, J. J., & Robertson, E. F. (2005a). Jean Marie Constant Duhamel. In MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive. http://www-history.mcs.st-andrews.ac.uk/Biographies/Duhamel.html.. Accessed 1 June 2012.

  • O’Connor, J. J., & Robertson, E. F. (2005b). Joseph Louis François Bertrand. In MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive, http://www-history.mcs.st-andrews.ac.uk/Biographies/Bertrand.html.. Accessed 1 June 2012.

  • Poisson, S.D. (1806). Mémoire sur les solutions particulières des équations différentielles et des équations aux différences. Journal de l’École Polytechnique, 6(13), 60–125.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poisson, S.D. (1833). Traité de mécanique (Vol. 1). Paris: Bachelier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Porter, T.M. (1986). The rise of statistical thinking, 1820–1900. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Strien, M. E. (2014). On the origins and foundations of Laplacian determinism. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 45(1), 24–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, M. (2009). Determinism and the mystery of the missing physics. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60, 173–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolfe, C.T. (2007). Determinism/Spinozism in the Radical Enlightenment: The cases of Anthony Collins and Denis Diderot. International Review of Eighteenth-Century Studies, 1(1), 37–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zinkernagel, H. (2010). Causal fundamentalism in physics. In M. Suárez, M. Dorato & M. Rédei (Eds.), EPSA philosophical issues in the sciences: Launch of the European philosophy of science association. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Jos Uffink, John Norton, Dennis Dieks, Samuel Fletcher, Eric Schliesser, Maarten Van Dyck, Bernhard Pos, Marcel Boumans, Thomas Müller (Lausanne University), Alexander Reutlinger and Sylvia Wenmackers for useful comments and discussion. I would also like to thank two anonymous referees for their helpful comments. This work was supported by the Research Foundation Flanders (FWO).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marij van Strien.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

van Strien, M. The Norton Dome and the Nineteenth Century Foundations of Determinism. J Gen Philos Sci 45, 167–185 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-014-9241-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-014-9241-0

Keywords

Navigation