Skip to main content
Log in

In Defence of Activities

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, we examine what is to be said in defence of Machamer, Darden and Craver’s (MDC) controversial dualism about activities and entities (Machamer, Darden and Craver’s in Philos Sci 67:1–25, 2000). We explain why we believe the notion of an activity to be a novel, valuable one, and set about clearing away some initial objections that can lead to its being brushed aside unexamined. We argue that substantive debate about ontology can only be effective when desiderata for an ontology are explicitly articulated. We distinguish three such desiderata. The first is a more permissive descriptive ontology of science, the second a more reductive ontology prioritising understanding, and the third a more reductive ontology prioritising minimalism. We compare MDC’s entities-activities ontology to its closest rival, the entities-capacities ontology, and argue that the entities-activities ontology does better on all three desiderata.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We shall not discuss more distant rival ontologies in this paper—e.g., an ontology based on entities and laws.

  2. We reject MDC’s claim that activities are the producers of change for reasons we have discussed in more detail elsewhere. In a nutshell, the reason is that some activities may not produce change, but maintain stability. For example, the activity of the homeostatic mechanism that maintains body temperature is to maintain a steady 37 °C, in the face of environmental variation.

  3. Note: chemists use the word ‘mechanism’ to refer to activities or processes, and the word ‘activity’ itself to mean an effective concentration—the molar concentration of a substance adjusted for the presence of other substances in the solution that make it less able to react. See for example: ‘At very great dilution the hydrogen ion activity is equivalent to the hydrogen ion concentration [H+]’ (Dowes 1980, 39). However, the conceptual division of entity-like things from activity-like things is clear in chemistry despite the confusing difference in language.

  4. Psillos originally phrases this as a conceivability argument: ‘First, it’s conceivable that there are entities without activities’ (Psillos 2004, 312). We set this aside since conceivability is a notoriously unreliable guide to possibility.

  5. It might be argued that a perfect vacuum can engage in activities—e.g., sucking in matter. However, a perfect vacuum is arguably not entirely empty of entities, containing virtual particles (vacuum fluctuations) as well as dark energy.

  6. There are also process ontologists such as Whitehead (1929) and Rescher (1996) who claim that everything is a process. They are very much in the minority and we put them aside to address those MDC call ‘substantivalists’, such as Cartwright.

  7. In Illari and Williamson (2011) we argue that the fact that a mechanism is intended to offer a local explanation of its resulting phenomenon makes the objects-laws ontology, which renders mechanisms non-local, undesirable.

  8. Use of ‘capacity’ rather than ‘disposition’, ‘propensity’ or ‘power’ makes the point very clear, but this is not underhand. Any disposition or power is a disposition or power to do something in certain circumstances. The thing done is conceptually prior to the disposition or power to do that thing. Note that our argument here is not that activities are actual and capacities merely potential, so we should have activities not capacities. Capacities and activities both have modal implications. Activities must be modal because an adequate ontology needs ways of describing not just how things do act but how they will act or would have acted under different circumstances. Psillos (2004, 314) can be interpreted as making this point.

  9. As are dispositions and powers, of course.

  10. The powers literature now recognises this problem, along with the need for other cooperating entities, calling them ‘mutual manifestation partners’. See for example Mumford and Anjum (2011).

References

  • Adams, R. L. P., Knowler, J. T., & Leader, D. P. (1992). The biochemistry of the nucleic acids (11th ed.). London: Chapman and Hall.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1975). Causality and determination. In E. Sosa (Ed.), Causation and conditionals (pp. 63–81). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2005). Explanation: A mechanist alternative. In Studies in the history and philosophy of the biological and biomedical sciences, Vol. 36. pp. 421–441.

  • Cartwright, N. (1989). Nature’s capacities and their measurement. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (2004). Causation: One word many things. Philosophy of Science, 71, 805–819.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L. (2006). Reasoning in biological discoveries. Cambridge: CUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L. (2008). Thinking again about biological mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 75(5), 958–969.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Regt, H. (2004). Making sense of understanding. Philosophy of Science, 71(1), 98–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Regt, H. (2009). The epistemic value of understanding. Philosophy of Science, 76(5), 585–597.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowe, P. (1995). Causality and conserved quantities: A reply to Salmon. Philosophy of Science, 62, 321–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowes, E. A. (1980). Quantitative problems in biochemistry. NY: Longman Group Limited.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (1993). The disorder of things: Metaphysical foundations of the disunity of science. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J., & O’Malley, M. (2012). Metagenomics and biological ontology reprinted in Dupré’: Processes of Life: Essays in the philosophy of biology (pp. 188–205), Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Gillett, C. (2007). The metaphysics of mechanisms and the challenge of the new reductionism. In M. Schouten & H. L. de Jong (Eds.), The matter of the mind. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, C. (2008). The hidden battles over emergence. In P. Clayton (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of religion and science (pp. 801–818). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Glennan, S. (2002). Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science, 69, S342–S353.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (2005). Modeling mechanisms. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biology and Biomedical Sciences, 36, 443–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Illari, P., & Williamson, J. (2010). Function and organization: Comparing the mechanisms of protein synthesis and natural selection. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 41, 279–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Illari, P. M., & Williamson, J. (2011). Mechanisms are real and local. In P. M. Illari, F. Russo, & J. Williamson (Eds.), Casuality in the sciences (pp. 818–844). Oxford: Oxford Uniuversity Press.

  • Illari, P., & Williamson, J. (2012). What is a mechanism? Thinking about mechanisms across the sciences. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 2, 119–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., & Ross, D. (2007). Every thing must go: Metaphysics naturalized. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P. (2004). Activities and causation: The metaphysics and epistemology of mechanisms. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 18(1), 27–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S. (2004). Laws in nature. Abingdon: Rutledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S., & Anjum, R. L. (2011). Getting causes from powers. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Persson, J. (2010). Activity-based accounts of mechanism and the threat of polygenic effects. Erkenntnis, 72(1), 135–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2004). A glimpse of the secret connexion: Harmonizing mechanisms with counterfactuals. Perspectives on Science College, 12(3), 288–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. Q. (1948). On what there is. In Review of metaphysics, Vol. 2, pp. 21–38, reprinted in Crane and Farkas (Eds.) Metaphysics, 2004, Oxford: OUP.

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1969). Existence and quantification. In Ontological relativity and other essays. New York: Columbia University Press.

  • Rescher, N. (1996). Process metaphysics: An introduction to process philosophy. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Santos-Lleo, M., Schartel, N., Tananbaum, H., Tucker, W., & Weisskopf, M. C. (2009). The first decade of science with Chandra and XMM-Newton. Nature, 462, 24–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (1980). Causality and properties. In V. Peter Inwagen (Ed.), Time and cause (pp. 109–135). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (1984). Identity, cause, and mind: Philosophical essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skipper, R., & Millstein, R. (2005). Thinking about evolutionary mechanisms: Natural selection. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 36, 327–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tabery, J. (2004). Synthesizing activities and interactions in the concept of a mechanism. Philosophy of Science, 71, 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Torres, P. J. (2009). A modified conception of mechanisms. Erkenntnis, 71(2), 233–251 (forthcoming).

  • Voet, D., & Voet, J. G. (2004). Biochemistry. NY: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead, A. N. (1929). Process and reality: An essay in cosmology. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitford, D. (2005). Proteins: Structure and function. Sussex: John Wiley and Sons Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (2007). The ontology of complex systems. In His re-engineering philosophy for limited beings. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Woodward, J. (2002). What is a mechanism? A counterfactual account. Philosophy of Science, 69(3), S366–S377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We are grateful to two anonymous referees for very helpful comments. This research was supported by The Leverhulme Trust and the UK Arts and Humanities Research Council.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Phyllis Illari.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Illari, P., Williamson, J. In Defence of Activities. J Gen Philos Sci 44, 69–83 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-013-9217-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-013-9217-5

Keywords

Navigation