Skip to main content
Log in

Species of Pluralism in Political Philosophy

  • Regular Paper
  • Published:
The Journal of Value Inquiry Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. Rawls 1993.

  2. Berlin (2002); Cohen (2008).

  3. For discussion of the distinction between value pluralism and reasonable pluralism, see Larmore (1996) chapter 7.

  4. In this paper, I use the term ‘justice’ the same way Rawls does: to refer to the output of practical reasoning about how we should design shared institutions. However, I think that there’s good reason to think of ‘justice’ as an input in practical reasoning: specifically, as a fundamental value that should be balanced against other fundamental values. The reason I adopt Rawls’s usage here is because his is currently common among political philosophers, and thus using the term differently would distract from my paper’s argument. For the arguments I give in support of the view that justice is one fundamental value among many, see Johannsen (2018) chapters 5 and 6. For a defense of my arguments, see Johannsen (2019) pp. 769–77.

  5. See Crowder (2002) pp. 158–84; and Galston (2002) pp. 46–7.

  6. For his earlier thoughts about the justificatory relationship between value pluralism and liberalism, see Crowder (1998).

  7. For worries about using value pluralism to justify political liberalism’s normative claims, see Larmore (1996) chapter 7. It is telling that Larmore tentatively concedes that value pluralism may play a role in explaining reasonable pluralism, even though he rejects the claim that it plays a justificatory role in political liberalism. For Larmore’s brief, unargued thoughts on value pluralism’s explanatory relationship with reasonable pluralism, see Larmore (2008) pp. 141–2; and Larmore (2015) pp. 71–2.

  8. See, for example, Waldron (1999).

  9. See, for example, Stocker (1990) and Stocker (1997), as well as Ross (1930).

  10. See endnote 2 in the present paper.

  11. For discussion of the phenomenon of rational moral regret see, for example, Williams (1973) and Stocker (1990). Value pluralists can explain rational moral regret more easily than monists can, but that hasn’t stopped monists from offering explanations of their own. See, for example, Hurka (1996).

  12. The criteria I’ve listed roughly match those endorsed by Rawls. See Rawls (1993) p. 54.

  13. Rawls (1993) pp. 140–54.

  14. See, for example, Waldron (1999).

  15. Though value pluralists have generally neglected the phenomenon of reasonable pluralism, two exceptions are George Crowder and William Galston. See endnote 5 in the present paper.

  16. See endnote 11 in the present paper.

  17. See Quong (2011) p. 142. For the quote, see Rawls (1993) p. 4.

  18. For examples of philosophers who have interpreted reasonable pluralism as a fact about existing liberal societies, see Raz (1990); Habermas (1995); and Klosko (1997).

  19. Rawls (1993) p. 35. Though Rawls stipulates that agreement about justice is one of the features of a well-ordered society, he sometimes acknowledges that reasonable disagreement about the correct political liberal conception of justice is both possible and likely. See endnote 29 in the present paper.

  20. See Rawls (1993).

  21. Rawls (1971) p. 3.

  22. Rawls (1971) pp. 158–61.

  23. Rawls (1971) pp. 34–9.

  24. See for, example, Stocker (1990) p. 72.

  25. Rawls (1971) pp. 40–4 and 302–3.

  26. Rawls (1971) pp. 302–3.

  27. Rawls (1971) p. 100–2.

  28. Rawls (1971) pp. 102–6.

  29. Rawls (1993) pp. 226–7. See also Rawls (1999) pp. 140–3.

  30. Rawls (1993) p. 6.

  31. Rawls (1993) p. 227.

  32. Rawls (1993) p. 54.

  33. Rawls (1993) p. 56.

  34. Rawls (1993) pp. 56–7. See also Crowder (2002) pp. 165–71; and Galston (2002) pp. 46–7.

  35. Rawls (1993) p. 57.

  36. For the quoted sentence, see Larmore (1996) p. 170. For additional discussion, see Larmore (2015) p. 72.

  37. For similar thoughts, see Galston (2002) pp. 46–7.

  38. See Rawls’s discussion of “the liberal principle of legitimacy” in Rawls (1993) pp. 136–7. See also Larmore’s discussion in Larmore (2015) pp. 74–80.

  39. Crowder (2002) pp. 158–84; Galston (2002) pp. 46–7.

  40. See, for example, Crowder (2002) p. 159, p. 165, and pp. 167–8; and Galston (2002) pp. 46–7.

  41. At one point, Crowder claims that value pluralism implies reasonable pluralism, i.e., that value pluralism is a sufficient condition for reasonable pluralism. See Crowder (2002) pp. 171–2.

  42. Waldron (1999).

  43. Cohen (2008) chapters 1 and 2.

  44. For seminal discussion of Cohen’s critique of incentives and the basic structure restriction see, for example, Williams (1998); and Murphy (1999). For more recent discussion see, for example, Shiffrin (2010); Macleod (2011); Schouten (2013); Johannsen (2013); Johannsen (2016); and Albertsen (2019).

  45. Whether the reason for redistribution is to secure equal resources, equal welfare, equal capabilities, equal access to advantage, etc., egalitarian theories converge on the conclusion that the radical inequalities of wealth and income existing in most contemporary societies are unjust. Nor must one be a so–called ‘distributive egalitarian’ to think so: ‘relational egalitarians’ concur. For a sampling of the different forms of egalitarianism on offer, see endnotes 46 and 47 in the present paper.

  46. For articulations of the harshness objections, see Anderson (1999) pp. 295–300; and Scheffler (2003) p. 33.

  47. For seminal examples of the luck egalitarian position, see Dworkin (2000); Arneson (1989); and Cohen (1989).

  48. In response to the harshness objection, some luck egalitarians have argued that luck egalitarianism is a conception of one value among many, and that the requirements of luck equality must be balanced against competing values. See, for example, Segall (2007); Cohen (2009) pp. 34–6; Casal (2007) pp. 321–3; and Johannsen (2018) pp. 34–5.

  49. See endnote 36 in the present paper.

References

  • Albertsen, Andreas. 2019. Markets, Distributive Justice and Community: The Egalitarian Ethos of G.A. Cohen. Political Research Quarterly 72: 376–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, Elizabeth. 1999. What is the Point of Equality? Ethics 109: 287–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arneson, Richard. 1989. Equality and Equal Opportunity for Welfare. Philosophical Studies 56: 77–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berlin, Isaiah. 2002. Two Concepts of Liberty. In Liberty: Incorporating Four Essays on Liberty, ed. Henry Hardy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Casal, Paula. 2007. Why Sufficiency Is Not Enough. Ethics 117: 296–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G.A. 1989. On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice. Ethics 99: 906–944.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G.A. 2008. Rescuing Justice and Equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Cohen, G.A. 2009. Why Not Socialism?. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crowder, George. 1998. John Gray’s Pluralist Critique of Liberalism. Journal of Applied Philosophy 15: 287–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crowder, George. 2002. Liberalism and Value Pluralism. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 2000. Equality of Resources. In Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality, ed. Ronald Dworkin, 65-119. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Galston, William A. 2002. Liberal Pluralism: The Implications of Value Pluralism for Political Theory and Practice. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jurgen. 1995. Reconciliation Through the Public Use of Reason: Remarks on John Rawls’s Political Liberalism. Journal of Philosophy 92: 109–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurka, Thomas. 1996. Monism, Pluralism, and Rational Regret. Ethics 106: 555–575.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johannsen, Kyle. 2013. Cohen on Rawls: Personal Choice and the Ideal of Justice. Social Philosophy Today 29: 135–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johannsen, Kyle. 2016. Cohen’s Equivocal Attack on Rawls’s Basic Structure Restriction. Ethical Perspectives 23: 499–525.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johannsen, Kyle. 2018. A Conceptual Investigation of Justice. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johannsen, Kyle. 2019. Defending A Conceptual Investigation of Justice. Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review 58: 763-78.

  • Klosko, George. 1997. Political Constructivism in Rawls’s Political Liberalism. American Political Science Review 91: 635–646.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Larmore, Charles. 1996. The Morals of Modernity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Larmore, Charles. 2008. The Autonomy of Morality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Larmore, Charles. 2015. Political Liberalism: Its Motivations and Goals. In Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy, ed. David Sobel, Peter Vallentyne, and Steven Wall, vol. 1, 63-88. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Macleod, Alistair M. 2011. G.A. Cohen on the Rawlsian Doctrine of the Basic Structure as Subject. Social Philosophy Today 26: 153–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, Liam B. 1999. Institutions and the Demands of Justice. Philosophy & Public Affairs 27: 251–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quong, Jonathan. 2011. Liberalism Without Perfection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press).

  • Rawls, John. 1993. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1999. The Law of Peoples. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph. 1990. Facing Diversity: The Case of Epistemic Abstinence. Philosophy & Public Affairs 19: 3–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, W.D. 1930. What Makes Right Acts Right? In The Right and the Good, ed. W.D. Ross. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Scheffler, Samuel. 2003. What is Egalitarianism? Philosophy & Public Affairs 31: 5–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schouten, Gina. 2013. Restricting Justice: Political Interventions in the Home and in the Market. Philosophy & Public Affairs 41: 357–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Segall, Shlomi. 2007. In Solidarity with the Imprudent: A Defense of Luck Egalitarianism. Social Theory and Practice 33: 177–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shiffrin, Seanna V. 2010. Incentives, Motives, and Talents. Philosophy & Public Affairs 38: 111–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stocker, Michael. 1990. Plural and Conflicting Values. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stocker, Michael. 1997. Abstract and Concrete Value: Plurality, Conflict, and Maximization. In Incomparability Incommensurability and Practical Reason, ed. Ruth Chang. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Waldron, Jeremy. 1999. Law and Disagreement. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Andrew. 1998. Incentives, Inequality, and Publicity. Philosophy & Public Affairs 27: 225–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Bernard. 1973. Ethical Consistency. In Problems of the Self, ed. Bernard Williams. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Download references

Acknowledgements

Earlier versions of this paper were presented at the American Philosophical Association’s Pacific Division, the Canadian Section of the International Association for Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy, and Queen’s University’s Political Philosophy Reading Group. I’m grateful to my audiences for their comments. For helpful written comments, I’m thankful to Lori Watson, Jared Houston, and an anonymous reviewer for the Journal of Value Inquiry.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kyle Johannsen.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Johannsen, K. Species of Pluralism in Political Philosophy. J Value Inquiry 55, 491–506 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-020-09750-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-020-09750-5

Navigation