Skip to main content
Log in

Personal Uniqueness and Events

  • Theoretical / Philosophical Paper
  • Published:
Human Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In contrast to Anglophone debates on personal identity initially formed by John Locke’s investigation of personal identity in the sense of personal continuity or persistence through time, the Continental tradition focuses on what constitutes ipseity (ipséité, Selbstsein, selfhood) in the sense of individuality or uniqueness of the human being “constituted” by its continuous transformation through changing experience. In this study, I claim that contemporary phenomenological research in France—especially the “phenomenology of the event” as represented by Henri Maldiney and Claude Romano—contributes to this Continental discussion in a significant way: it formulates the conditions of personal uniqueness or distinctiveness with regard to other persons, conditions not to be found in Heidegger’s existential conception of selfhood in Being and Time. More precisely, Maldiney and Romano allow us to answer the principal questions of this study: In what does the personal uniqueness consist? What exactly individualizes the first-person selfhood disclosed in Dasein’s relation to death? In my three-stage analysis, I first deal with Heidegger’s conception of selfhood in Being and Time and its limits with respect to the question of personal uniqueness. Next, I analyse Maldiney’s conception of “eventful selfhood” in which he “completes” Heidegger’s conception of selfhood by describing Dasein’s openness to ontical, and yet fully authentic events. Finally, I develop the argumentation by presenting Romano’s even more radical conception of the “happening subjectivity” (advenant), which allows us to return to the second major feature of personal identity: personal persistence. Nonetheless, I conclude that the connection between personal uniqueness and persistence is not sufficiently examined in the phenomenology of the event, which opens the path towards another related inquiry into the following problem: What is the proper subjective dimension or the “underlying thing” (ὑποκείμενον) in the background of personal persistence which somehow resists events?

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Ricœur’s definition of individual character: “By ‘character’ I understand the set of distinctive marks which permit the reidentification of a human individual as being the same” (Ricœur 1992: 119).

  2. Note that Latin ipse is employed to emphasize that it is precisely the person in question, the person herself. Romano (2016a: 45) clearly defines Latin ipse in this manner: “ipse Caesar: Caesar himself […] ipse is only employed as an expression of emphasis by which one indicates that it is the person herself, or the very person who is in question”. See with Ricœur’s definition (1992: 3) of “oneself”: “‘Oneself’ (soi-même) is only an emphatic form of ‘self’, the expression même serving to indicate that it is precisely a matter of the being or the thing in question”.

  3. As J.-L. Chrétien remarks, before becoming a widely known philosopher, Maldiney had long been respected in artistic and psychiatric circles (Chrétien 2012: 7–29). His conception of human existence draws upon his encounters with friends and acquaintances from both disciplines: for example, with artists such as Tal Coat, J. Bazaine, F. Ponge or A. du Bouchet, and with psychiatrists such as J. Schotte, L. Binswanger, L. Szondi or R. Kuhn.

  4. Maldiney describes such a transcendence that is irreducible to the transcendence of Dasein’s projection. That is why he groups together (under the name of event) what Levinas strictly distinguishes: the metaphysical transcendence of the Other and the transcendence of impersonal element from which subjectivity lives (vivre de…). Moreover, Levinas does not employ the term “event” for an individualizing event but for “an event of being, as the openness of a dimension indispensable, in the economy of being, for the production of infinity” (1979: 240).

  5. “L’émotion ressentie excède l’attente et le sens de la quête. Elle est bouleversante à la mesure du monde bouleversé. L’apparition du chamois ne s’inscrit pas dans une configuration préalable qu’au contraire elle annule” (Maldiney 1991: 406). I use and slightly modify S. Thoma’s translation of this passage (Thoma 2014).

  6. “L’identité n’est pas l’ipséité. L’ipséité, c’est le soi-même qui est toujours en jeu. L’identité, c’est déjà quelque chose d’établi, à quoi on ramène le reste […] C’est l’ipséité qui compte: l’identité, c’est tout ramener au même” (Maldiney 1997: 113; see Maldiney 1991: 351).

  7. “Résoudre la crise c’est intégrer l’événement en se transformant” (Maldiney 1991: 320).

  8. Even though they both define event as an existential transformation, it seems that they do not agree on what leads to this reversal. While Maldiney considers every single small sensation as an event, Romano focuses on rare intense transformations through events like the above-mentioned death of a close friend. Thus, Romano’s books on events lack reflections on what is crucial for Maldiney: on sensation (sentir). (see Dika et al. 2012: 201).

  9. Inspired by Heidegger, Romano (2009a: 32–39) distinguishes events in their evential (événemential) and evental (événementiel) sense: while the latter is the usual French adjective referring to events as they occur in everyday interpretation as innerworldly facts, the former is a neologism referring to their existential definition.

  10. I have to remark here that Romano’s position is still evolving and it is not absolutely clear what the relation is between his early theory of selfhood, laid out in his books on the event, and the theory he holds today. With regard to his habilitation work (Romano 2015), one may say that while “evential selfhood” is still relevant for Romano’s current theory, he takes into account two other important aspects of human existence neglected in his books on event, namely “natural” capabilities (corporeality) and culture. However, although he recently published a book on “being-oneself” (Romano 2019), he shed no light on the relation between what he designates as three different capabilities (capacités) of the existent, that is, “‘natural’ capabilities that we share with other living beings, capabilities that depend on a specifically human culture, [and] capabilities-of-being in the Heideggerian sense” (see Romano 2015: 400).

  11. I deal with these questions in a related study on the subjective continuity of happening existence according to M. Richir (Prášek 2021).

References

  • Abettan, C. (2015). L’événement et l’historicité de l’existant chez Heidegger et Maldiney. Alter, 23, 275–290.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1998). The human condition. The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barbaras, R. (2019). L’appartenance. Vers une cosmologie phénoménologique. Peeters.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Canullo, C. (2013). Claude Romano au carrefour de la phénoménologie française. Journal of French and Francophone Philosophy – Revue de la philosophie française et de langue française, 21(2), 87–104.

  • Čapek, J., & Loidolt, S. (2021). Phenomenological approaches to personal identity. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 20, 217–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chrétien, J.-L. (2012). Introduction aux "Œuvres philosophiques”. In H. Maldiney, Regard parole espace, Paris: Cerf, 7–29.

  • Crowell, S. (2021). On what matters. personal identity as a phenomenological problem. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 20, 261–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dastur, F. (2016). Phénoménologie de la surprise : Horizon, projection et événement. Alter, 24, 31–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dika, T.R., Hackett W., & Romano C. (2012). Les concepts fondamentaux de la phénoménologie, entretien avec Claude Romano. Journal of French and Francophone Philosophy – Revue de la philosophie française et de langue française, 20(2), 173–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drummond, J. (2021). Self-identity and personal identity. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 20, 235–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Escoubas, E. (2006). Henri Maldiney. In P. Cabestan (Ed.), Introduction à la phénoménologie contemporaine (pp. 69–82). Ellipses.

    Google Scholar 

  • Escudero, J. A. (2014). Heidegger on selfhood. American International Journal of Contemporary Research, 4(2), 6–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gondek, H., & Tengelyi, L. (2011). Neue Phänomenologie in Frankreich. Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guignon, Ch. (2015). Authenticity and the question of being. In D. McManus (Ed.), Heidegger, authenticity and the self (pp. 8–20). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1966). Discourse on thinking. Harper and Row Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1996). Being and time. State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (2001). Zollikon seminars. Protocols – conversations – letters. Edited by M. Boss. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Housset E. (2002). Henri Maldiney: Le moi inimaginable. In S. Meitinger (Ed.), Henri Maldiney, une phénoménologie à l’impossible. Paris: Cercle Herméneutique.

  • Housset, E. (2007). La dramatique de la personne ou l’ipséité comme paradoxe. Les Études Philosophiques, 81(2), 215–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1960). Cartesian meditations. Martinus Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1973). Experience and judgment. Investigations in a genealogy of logic. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1991). On the phenomenology of the consciousness of internal time. Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, H. (2010). Towards a phenomenological account of personal identity. In C. Iena, H. Jacobs, & F. Mattens (Eds.), Philosophy, phenomenology, sciences: Essays in commemoration of Edmund Husserl (pp. 333–361). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jacquet, F. (2017). La transpassibilité et l’événement. Essai sur la philosophie de Maldiney. Éditions Classiques Garnier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kouba, P. (2015). The phenomenon of mental disorder. Perspectives of Heidegger’s thought in psychopathology. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, E. (1979). Totality and infinity. Martinus Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (2008). An essay concerning human understanding. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loidolt, S. (2020). “Who one is“ – A political issue? Hannah Arendt on personhood, maximal self, and bare life. In T. Bedorf, S. Herrmann (Eds.), Political phenomenogy. Experience, ontology, episteme. London: Routledge.

  • Luft, S. (2005). Husserl’s concept of the “transcendental person”: Another look at the Husserl-Heidegger relationship. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 13(2), 1–39, available at https://www.researchgate.net/publication/39712561_Husserl%27s_Concept_of_the_%27Transcendental_Person%27_Another_Look_at_the_Husserl-Heidegger_Relationship

  • MacKinlay, S. (2005). Phenomenality in the middle, Marion, Romano, and the hermeneutics of the event. In I. G. Leask & E. G. Cassidy (Eds.), Givenness and God: Questions of Jean-Luc Marion (pp. 167–181). Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maldiney, H. (1973). Regard parole espace. Lausanne: L’Age d’Homme.

  • Maldiney, H. (1991). Penser l’homme et la folie. Grenoble: Millon.

  • Maldiney, H. (1997). Avenèment de l’œuvre. Saint Maximin: Théétète.

  • Maldiney, H. (2001). Existence: Crise et création. Fougères: Les Belles Lettres.

  • Maldiney, H. (2010). Ouvrir le rien, l’art nu. Les Belles Lettres.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maldiney, H. (2012). L’art, l’éclair de l’être. Les Éditions du Cerf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marion, J.-L. (2002). Un moment français de la phénoménologie. Rue Descartes, 35(1), 9–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marion, J.-L. (2013). Étant donné. Presses Universitaires de France.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Marion, J.-L. (2016). Reprise du donné. Presses Universitaires de France.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McManus, D. (2015). Anxiety, choice and responsibility in Heidegger’s account of authenticity. In D. McManus (Ed.), Heidegger, authenticity and the self (pp. 163–185). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • McNeill, W. (2020). The fate of phenomenology. Heidegger’s legacy. Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prášek, P. (2021). Is the “Happening subjectivity” still a subject? Marc Richir’s conception of subjective identity. META: Research in Hermeneutics, Phenomenology, and Practical Philosophy, 13(1), 58–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raffoul, F. (2020). Thinking the event. Indiana University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ricœur, P. (1992). Oneself as another. The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Romano, C. (2009a). Event and world. Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Romano, C. (2009b). Mémoire de synthèse présenté en vue d’habilitation à diriger des recherches. Available at: http://paris-sorbonne.academia.edu/ClaudeRomano

  • Romano, C. (2010). L’aventure temporelle. Presses Universitaires de France.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Romano, C. (2014). Event and time. Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Romano, C. (2015). At the heart of reason. Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Romano, C. (2016a). Identity and selfhood: Paul Ricoeur’s contribution and its continuations. In S. Davidson, M.-A. Vallée (Eds.), Hermeneutics and phenomenology in Paul Ricoeur. Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Romano, C. (2016b). There is, the event and the finitude of appearing. Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Romano, C. (2019). Être soi-même. Une autre histoire de la philosophie. Gallimard.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sommer, Ch. (2014). Nouvelles phénoménologies en France. Hermann.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tengelyi, L. (2010). La formation de sens comme événement. Eikasia. Revista De Filosofia, 34, 149–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tengelyi, L. (2012). New phenomenology in France. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 50(2), 295–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thoma, S. (2014). A psychopathology à l’impossible – On Henri Maldiney’s inclusive anthropology of Schizophrenia. Available at: http://www.henri-maldiney.org/sites/default/files/imce/hommage_to_henri_maldiney_by_samuel_thoma-1.pdf

  • Virri, F. (2017). Essai d’une cartographie de la notion d’ “événement” dans la phénoménologie française contemporaine. Methodos, 17, 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wrathall, M. (2015). Autonomy, authenticity, and the self. In D. McManus (Ed.), Heidegger, authenticity and the self (pp. 193–214). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author would like to thank Jakub Čapek, Sophie Loidolt and the anonymous reviewers for their valuable comments and efforts towards improving the manuscript.

Funding

The author gratefully acknowledges that this work was supported by the Czech Science Foundation, financing the project “Personal Identity at the Crossroads: Phenomenological, Genealogical, and Hegelian Perspectives” (GAČR 18-16622S).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Petr Prášek.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Prášek, P. Personal Uniqueness and Events. Hum Stud 44, 721–740 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-021-09597-0

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-021-09597-0

Keywords

Navigation