Skip to main content
Log in

Classicality First: Why Zurek’s Existential Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Implies Copenhagen

  • Published:
Foundations of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Most interpretations of Quantum Mechanics alternative to Copenhagen interpretation try to avoid the dualistic flavor of the latter. One of the basic goals of the former is to avoid the ad hoc introduction of observers and observations as an inevitable presupposition of physics. Non-Copenhagen interpretations usually trust in decoherence as a necessary mechanism to obtain a well-defined, observer-free transition from a unitary quantum description of the universe to classicality. Even though decoherence does not solve the problem of the definite outcomes, it helps to explain why we do not observe superpositions and, according to Zurek’s existential interpretation, why a specific preferred basis emerges through system–environment interactions. The aim of this paper is to show why such interpretation ends up begging the question and provides little progress in understanding the quantum-to-classical transition; the ultimate reason being that preferred bases always correlate to human observation. Benefitting from the technical discussion, some remarks will be offered in the last section regarding the role of classical observations as a necessary condition to make workable the formalism of Quantum Mechanics and scientific activity itself.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For an affordable description of the most important interpretations see, e.g., the different entries under the heading “Quantum Mechanics” in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

  2. When referring to Copenhagen interpretation I will mainly understand Bohr’s stance on Copenhagen interpretation regarding classicality, see, e.g. Faye (2014) and Bacciagaluppi (2016). This does not remove generality to the main thesis of this paper because, in this respect, Bohr and Heisenberg agree (Heisenberg 1958, Chapter 3).

  3. In that precise sense, my analysis may also help to enlarge the top-down view of the classical limit of QM presented in a recent book (Fortin and Lombardi 2017).

  4. There is no need for the “environment” to be in some sense external to the system. Overall, the macroscopic degrees of freedom of a system can be decohered by the residual degrees of freedom of that same system (Wallace 2008). But this makes the problem of the preferred basis even more pressing: the “residual” degrees of freedom have to be determined in each situation in a practical, non-fundamental, manner.

  5. For historical and contemporary discussion on Bohr’s understanding of the correspondence principle and its different interpretations, see Bokulich (2014).

  6. As far as I know, Dennett (1991) was the first to establish the functionalist link between “classically perceived reality” and predictability.

  7. Given an abstract Hilbert space and Hamiltonian, we could envisage a system-environment partition where the preferred basis is de-localized, i.e. formed by superpositions of localized vector states. In Schrödinger-cat terms, had we not observations, we would be a priori equally entitled to use as basis the superpositions of dead cat and live cat.

  8. [T]he Copenhagen development of quantum theory exemplifies a clear rejection of the [Appearance from Reality] Criterion. The famous Measurement Problem in the philosophy of quantum mechanics is not a problem from an empiricist point of view (…).The rejection may not be unique in the history of science, but is brought home to us inescapably by the advent of the new quantum theory. Even if that theory is superseded (or if fundamental physics develops in accordance with a new interpretation under which the Criterion can be satisfied) our view of science must be forever modified in the light of this historical episode. (van Fraassen 2008, p. 292).

References

  • Bacciagaluppi, G. (2016). The role of decoherence in quantum mechanics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2016/entries/qm-decoherence/. Accessed 5 Sept 2018.

  • Barnum, H., Knill, E., Ortiz, G., Somma, R., & Viola, L. (2004). A subsystem-independent generalization of entanglement. Physical Review Letters, 92, 107902.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barnum, H., Knill, E., Ortiz, G., & Viola, L. (2003). Generalizations of entanglement based on coherent states and convex sets. Physical Review A, 68, 032308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bokulich, A. (2014). Bohr’s correspondence principle. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/bohr-correspondence/. Accessed 5 Sept 2018.

  • Ceroni, M., & Prosperi, G. M. (2018). Free will, subjectivity and the physics of the nervous system. Open Journal of Philosophy, 8, 317–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (1995). Facing up to the problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2(3), 200–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1991). Real patterns. Journal of Philosophy, 87, 27–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewar, R. C., Lineweaver, C. H., Niven, R. K., & Regenauer-Lieb, K. (2014). Beyond the second law: An overview. In R. C. Dewar, C. H. Lineweaver, R. K. Niven, & K. Regenauer-Lieb (Eds.), Beyond the second law. Entropy production and non-equilibrium systems (pp. 15–27). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Durt, T. (2010). Anthropomorphic quantum Darwinism as an explanation for classicality. Foundations of Science, 15(2), 177–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J. (2015). Some puzzles and unresolved issues about quantum entanglement. Erkenntnis, 80, 303–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Faye, J. (2014). Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/qm-copenhagen/. Accessed 5 Sept 2018.

  • Fields, C. (2013). On the Ollivier–Poulin–Zurek Definition of objectivity. Axiomathes, 24, 137–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fortin, S., & Lombardi, O. (2017). A top-down view of the classical limit of quantum mechanics. In R. E. Kastner, J. Jeknić-Dugić, & G. Jaroszkiewicz (Eds.), Quantum structural studies (pp. 435–468). Europe: World Scientific.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hameroff, S., & Penrose, R. (2014). Consciousness in the universe: A review of the ‘Orch OR’ theory. Physics of Life Reviews, 11(1), 39–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harshman, N., & Ranade, K. (2011). Observables can be tailored to change the entanglement of any pure state. Physical Review A, 84, 012303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heisenberg, W. (1958). Physics and philosophy. The revolution in modern science. London: Unwin University Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landsman, N. P. (2007). Between classical and quantum. In J. Butterfield & J. Earman (Eds.), Handbook of the philosophy of science: Philosophy of physics (pp. 417–553). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lombardi, O., Fortín, S., & Castagnino, M. (2012). The problem of identifying the system and the environment in the phenomenon of decoherence. In H. W. de Regt, S. Hartmann, & S. Okasha (Eds.), The european philosophy of science association proceedings: Amsterdam 2009 (pp. 161–174). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Paty, M. (2000). The quantum and classical domains as provisional parallel coexistents. Synthese, 125, 179–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, R. (2004). The road to reality. A complete guide to the laws of the universe. London: Jonathan Cape.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riedel, C. J., Zurek, W. H., & Zwolak, M. (2012). The rise and fall of redundancy in decoherence and quantum Darwinism. New Journal of Physics, 14, 083010.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sánchez-Cañizares, J. (2014). The mind-brain problem and the measurement paradox of quantum mechanics: Should we disentangle them? NeuroQuantology, 12(1), 76–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlosshauer, M. (2007). Decoherence and the quantum-to-classical transition. Heidelberg: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tanona, S. (2004). Idealization and formalism in Bohr’s approach to quantum theory. Philosophy of Science, 71(December), 683–695.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tanona, S. (2013). Decoherence and the Copenhagen cut. Synthese, 190, 3625–3649.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tegmark, M. (2015). Consciousness as a state of matter. Chaos, Solitons & Fractals, 76, 238–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (2008). Scientific representation: Paradoxes of perspective. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Viola, L., & Barnum, H. (2010). Entanglement and subsystems, entanglement beyond subsystems, and all that. In A. Bokulich & G. Jaeger (Eds.), Philosophy of quantum information and entanglement (pp. 16–43). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, D. (2008). Philosophy of quantum mechanics. In D. Rickles (Ed.), The ashgate companion to the new philosophy of physics (pp. 16–98). Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, D. (2012). Decoherence and its role in the modern measurement problem. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London A, 370, 4576–4593.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zeh, H. D. (1970). On the interpretation of measurement in quantum theory. Foundations of Physics, 1, 69–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zurek, W. H. (1981). Pointer basis of quantum apparatus: Into what mixture does the wave packet collapse? Physical Review D, 24, 1516–1525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zurek, W. H. (1982). Environment-induced superselection rules. Physical Review D, 26, 1862–1880.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zurek, W. H. (1998). Decoherence, einselection, and the existential interpretation (the rough guide). Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London A, 356, 1793–1821.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zurek, W. H. (2002). Decoherence and the transition from quantum to classical—revisited. Los Alamos Science, 27, 86–109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zurek, W. H. (2009). Quantum Darwinism. Nature Physics, 5, 181–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zurek, W. H., Habib, S., & Paz, J. P. (1993). Coherent states via decoherence. Physical Review Letters, 70, 1187–1190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Javier Sánchez-Cañizares.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sánchez-Cañizares, J. Classicality First: Why Zurek’s Existential Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Implies Copenhagen. Found Sci 24, 275–285 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-018-9574-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-018-9574-y

Keywords

Navigation