Skip to main content
Log in

Tropes, Unmanifested Dispositions and Powerful Qualities

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to a well-known argument, originally due to David Armstrong, powers theory is objectionable, as it leads to a ‘Meinongian’ ontology on which some entities are real but do not actually exist. I argue here that the right conclusion to draw from this argument has thus far not been identified and that doing so has significant implications for powers theory. Specifically, I argue that the key consequence of the argument is that it provides substantial grounds for trope powers theorists, but not other powers theorists, to accept one version of the view that properties are powerful qualities. In particular, they have grounds to favour the view that powerful properties are properties with exclusively qualitative natures that ground modal facts.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Subsequent versions of this argument have been given by Handfield (2005), Bird (2007) and Tugby (2013), who each relate their argument to Armstrong’s argument in a different way. Handfield explicitly formulates his argument as an interpretation of Armstrong’s argument. Bird begins his presentation of his argument by invoking Armstrong’s argument but states that he does not intend to ascribe his argument to Armstrong. Tugby, in turn, merely notes in passing that Armstrong gives a similar argument. .

  2. Well-known versions of this sort of view include Harré and Madden (1975), Shoemaker (1980), Swoyer (1982), Ellis and Lierse (1994), Ellis (2001, 2002), Molnar (2003), Heil (2003), Mumford (2004), Bird (2007), Chakravartty (2007), Whittle (2008), Martin (2008), Mumford and Anjum (2011) and Jacobs (2011).

  3. This usage is in line with Armstrong’s (2002: 168–169) discussion of Ellis’s (2001) response to the argument from non-manifestation. There Armstrong (2002: 169) says: ‘There is one particular manifestation of the power that is actually manifested in a particular situation, but a huge number of manifestations of that power will be empirically possible yet never occur. The power in the particulars points to all of these.’ As Armstrong points out, this result seems to exacerbate the difficulties raised by the argument from non-manifestation, as it apparently has the implication that token powers are generally unmanifested many times over.

  4. See, for instance, Armstrong (1997: 79), Molnar (2003: 60–81), Heil (2003: 124), Mumford (2004: 194), Bird (2007: 126), Martin (2008) and Tugby (2013: 456) for this claim.

  5. See Armstrong (1997: 79) and Tugby (2013: 457) for this line of reasoning.

  6. See, for instance, Robinson (1982: 114–115), Armstrong (1997: 79), Molnar (2003: 60–61), Lowe (2006: 138), Bird (2007: 136–137) and Tugby (2013: 456–457).

  7. This argument is most clearly developed by Tugby (2013: 457), although Bird (2007: 100) also gives an argument along these lines.

  8. Tugby (2013: 460) raises this sort of objection to attempts to deny that directedness is a genuine relation.

  9. Mumford (2004: 194–195) seems to endorse the former view, while Tugby (2013) and Handfield (2008: 119) endorse the latter view.

  10. Bird (2007: 106–108) discusses but ultimately rejects the type level response. Tugby (2013), Handfield (2008: 119) and Mumford (2004: 194–195) all propose that a version of this response is at least partially successful as a response to versions of the argument from non-manifestation.

  11. This example is used in Linsky and Zalta (1994, 1996).

  12. See, for instance, Adams (1974), Plantinga (1974, 1976), Fine (1977).

  13. Strictly speaking, this result only follows if the token manifestation of an unmanifested power instance is possible, and it is not immediately obvious that no unmanifested power instances have impossible token manifestations. Jenkins and Nolan (2012), for instance, argue that some actual dispositions cannot, in fact, manifest. I ignore this complication here, because the sorts of unmanifested power tokens with which I am concerned, such as unmanifested instances of charge, generally have possible manifestations.

  14. Stalnaker (1968) and Lewis (1973) originally developed this account.

  15. I am grateful to a referee for Erkenntnis for pressing this point. Handfield (2005: 455–456), drawing on an argument by Smith and Stoljar (1998), also points out that conjoining dispositional essentialism with a possible worlds account of counterfactuals, in general, seems to require the ‘existence of an external similarity relation’ between worlds. If good sense could be made of such a relation, then the possible worlds account of counterfactuals could be conjoined with the counterfactual-grounding conception of powers by claiming that powers have qualitative natures that ground such relations. .

  16. I would like to thank a referee for Erkenntnis for raising this point. A similar point is also made by Jaag (2014: 18) in the course of discussing Tugby’s theory.

  17. See Tugby (2012: 726–727). Jaag (2014: 17–18) also interprets Tugby in this way.

  18. See Smith (2016) and Yates (2018) for this sort of conception of powerful qualities.

  19. Mumford and Anjum (2011) provide a well-known and detailed defence of a version of primitive dispositional modality. It is not clear, though, that their approach would be helpful in developing the position currently under consideration, as they often appear to conceive of dispositions as being constituted by a connection to their manifestations. The position under consideration, on the other hand, requires that dispositions are modal facts that may involve the possibilities of their manifestations but are not constituted by any connection to their manifestations.

References

  • Adams, R. (1974). Theories of actuality. Noûs, 8, 211–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1997). A world of states of affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1999). The causal theory of properties: Properties according to Shoemaker, Ellis, and others. Philosophical Topics, 26, 25–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. M. (2002). Two problems for essentialism. In B. Ellis (Ed.), The philosophy of nature: A guide to the new essentialism (pp. 167–171). Chesham: Acumen.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Barker, S. (2013). The Emperor’s new metaphysics of powers. Mind, 122(487), 605–653.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s metaphysics: Laws and properties. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Borghini, A., & Williams, N. E. (2008). A dispositional theory of possibility. Dialectica, 62, 21–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2007). A Metaphysics for scientific realism: Knowing the unobservable. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Coates, A. (2020). Making sense of powerful qualities. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02576-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2001). Scientific essentialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2002). The philosophy of nature: A guide to the new essentialism. Chesham: Acumen.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B., & Lierse, C. (1994). Dispositional essentialism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 72, 27–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1977). Postscript. In A. N. Prior & K. Fine (Eds.), Worlds, times, and selves (pp. 116–161). Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Handfield, T. (2005). Armstrong and the modal inversion of dispositions. Philosophical Quarterly, 55, 452–461.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Handfield, T. (2008). Humean dispositionalism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 86, 113–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R., & Madden, E. H. (1975). Causal powers: A theory of natural necessity. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heil, J. (2003). From an ontological point of view. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jaag, S. (2014). Dispositional essentialism and the grounding of natural modality. Philosopher’s Imprint, 14, 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, J. D. (2010). A powers theory of modality: Or, how I learned to stop worrying and reject possible worlds. Philosophical Studies, 151, 227–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, J. D. (2011). Powerful qualities, not pure powers. The Monist, 94, 81–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jenkins, C. S., & Nolan, D. (2012). Disposition impossible. Noûs, 46, 732–753.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linsky, B., & Zalta, E. (1994). In defense of the simplest quantified modal logic. In J. Tomberlin (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives 8: Logic and language (pp. 431–458). Atascadero: Ridgeview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linsky, B., & Zalta, E. (1996). In defense of the contingently concrete. Philosophical Studies, 84, 283–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2006). The four-category ontology: A metaphysical foundation for natural science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C. B. (2008). The mind in nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menzel, C. (2015). Actualism. In E.N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2015 Edition) http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/actualism/

  • Molnar, G. (2003). Powers: A study in metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S. (2004). Laws in nature. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S., & Anjum, R. L. (2011). Getting causes from powers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1974). The nature of necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1976). Actualism and possible worlds. Theoria, 42, 139–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, H. (1982). Matter and sense. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (1980). Causality and properties. In P. van Inwagen (Ed.), Time and cause: Essays presented to Richard Taylor (pp. 109–135). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, D. C. (2016). Quid Quidditism Est? Erkenntnis, 81, 237–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M., & Stoljar, D. (1998). Global response-dependence and noumenal realism. The Monist, 81, 85–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1968). A theory of conditionals. In N. Rescher (Ed.) Studies in logical theory. American Philosophical Quarterly Monograph Series (Vol. 2, pp. 98–112). Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Swoyer, C. (1982). The nature of natural laws. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 60, 203–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tugby, M. (2012). Rescuing dispositionalism from the ultimate problem: Reply to Barker and Smart. Analysis, 72, 723–731.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tugby, M. (2013). Platonic dispositionalism. Mind, 122, 451–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vetter, B. (2015). Potentiality: From dispositions to modality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Whittle, A. (2008). A functionalist theory of properties. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 77, 59–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (1998). Bare possibilia. Erkenntnis, 48, 257–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (1999). Existence and contingency. The Aristotelian Society: Supplementary Volume, 73, 181–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2013). Modal logic as metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Yates, D. (2018). Inverse functionalism and the individuation of powers. Synthese, 195, 4525–4550.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zalta, E. N. (1983). Abstract objects: An introduction to axiomatic metaphysics. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This article is partly based on work that I did for my PhD thesis at the University of the Witwatersrand. I would like to thank the philosophy department and my supervisor, David Martens, for their assistance and support while writing the thesis. I would also like to thank referees for Erkenntnis for unusually extensive and helpful comments that substantially improved the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ashley Coates.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Coates, A. Tropes, Unmanifested Dispositions and Powerful Qualities. Erkenn 87, 2143–2160 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-020-00295-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-020-00295-4

Navigation