Skip to main content
Log in

Why We Cannot Learn from Minimal Models

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Philosophers of science have developed several accounts of how consideration of scientific models can prompt learning about real-world targets. In recent years, various authors advocated the thesis that consideration of so-called minimal models can prompt learning about such targets. In this paper, I draw on the philosophical literature on scientific modelling and on widely cited illustrations from economics and biology to argue that this thesis fails to withstand scrutiny. More specifically, I criticize leading proponents of such thesis for failing to explicate in virtue of what properties or features minimal models supposedly prompt learning and for substantially overstating the epistemic import of minimal models. I then examine and refute several arguments one may put forward to demonstrate that consideration of minimal models can prompt learning about real-world targets. In doing so, I illustrate the implications of my critique for the wider debate on the epistemology of scientific modelling.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I employ the expression ‘possible worlds’ broadly to indicate the hypothetical, imaginary, or counterfactual scenarios and states of affairs that are posited by specific models. My broad use of this expression covers what other authors (e.g. Morgan 2001; Sugden 2000) have called ‘model worlds’ and ‘worlds of the model’. Also, I speak of ‘properties’ and ‘features’—as opposed to ‘property’ and ‘feature’—to allow for the possibility that distinct properties and features enable learning in different modelling contexts. I shall comment on this context-dependency and its implications for the merits of LMM in Sect. 2.

  2. I shall occasionally state that minimal models ‘are assumed to lack any similarity, isomorphism, resemblance, etc. relation’ to real-world targets as an abbreviation for the characterization of ‘minimal models’ reported in the text. The proponents of LMM (e.g. Grüne-Yanoff 2009, 84) occasionally hint at a broader characterization of ‘minimal model’, according to which the set of minimal models includes both models that actually lack any similarity, isomorphism, resemblance, etc. relation to real-world targets and models for which no relation of similarity, isomorphism, resemblance, etc. to specific real-world targets has been determined by modellers. I shall expand in Sect. 2 on the differences between distinct characterizations of ‘minimal model’ and the implications of such differences for the merits of LMM. For now, I rely on the narrower characterization reported in the text both because the proponents of LMM repeatedly employ this characterization to single out minimal models (see e.g. Grüne-Yanoff 2009, 81–83) and because adopting the broader characterization would trivialize the issue whether we can learn from minimal models in the sense I explicate in Sect. 2.

  3. I am not concerned here with assessing the merits of this supposition. For present purposes, I note that not all scientific modellers speak of learning in the sense indicated by LMM. In particular, several authors (e.g. Morgan 1999) regard learning as more akin to acquiring novel information about one’s targets than to justifiably changing confidence in specific necessity or impossibility hypotheses about such targets. In what follows, I bracket these definitional concerns and examine what we can learn from minimal models in the sense indicated by LMM. I expand on different ways in which consideration of minimal models can allegedly prompt learning in Sect. 4.

  4. Some authors claim that learning from minimal models may go beyond undermining specific necessity or impossibility hypotheses (see e.g. Casini 2014, on the alleged provision of mechanistic insights about the examined targets). However, these authors typically adopt less restrictive characterizations of ‘minimal model’ than the characterization underlying LMM, since they allow that some world-linking relation may hold between what they call ‘minimal models’ and real-world targets (see e.g. Casini 2014, 660–662). For present purposes, I focus on the thesis that consideration of models that are minimal in the sense indicated by LMM can justifiably affect confidence in necessity or impossibility hypotheses.

  5. Indeed, one might question whether many scientific models qualify as minimal in the sense indicated by LMM. After all, the thought would be, given a model and a putative target, one can almost invariably find some sort of similarity, isomorphism, resemblance, etc. between such model and target. I am not concerned here with assessing the cogency of this supposition. For the purpose of my critique, it suffices to note that if no model qualified as minimal in the sense indicated by LMM, then LMM would reduce to the vacuous conditional statement that if there were minimal models, then we could learn from such models. In this respect, the challenge for the proponents of LMM is to provide a reformulation of LMM that is neither vacuous in this sense nor trivial in the sense specified in the text (see my remarks on LMM* and LMM** below).

  6. I am not aware of authors who explicitly relinquish LMM to advocate LMM*. Grüne-Yanoff might be taken to speak in favour of LMM* when he observes (2009, 98) that minimal models do not support hypotheses about particular real-world situations without empirical information about the world (see also Grüne-Yanoff 2013a).

  7. I focus on these two models because the proponents of LMM have debated over the epistemic import of those models in great detail and have claimed such models to constitute “a good example” of how minimal models can prompt learning about real-world targets (see e.g. Grüne-Yanoff 2009, 96, on Schelling’s model). My considerations hold mutatis mutandis for other instances of putative learning from minimal models (see e.g. Batterman and Rice 2014, on Fisher’s model of the 1:1 sex ratio, and Knuuttila 2009, on Tobin’s ultra-Keynesian model).

  8. In his works, Schelling presents several versions of the checkerboard model, which differ in various details (see e.g. Sugden 2011). I shall expand on these differences whenever they are material to my critique of LMM.

  9. Maynard Smith and Price (1973) explore more complicated versions of the Hawk–Dove model, where individual contestants can adopt several different strategies and can modify their own behaviour in response to their opponent’s behaviour. I focus on the basic Hawk–Dove model because it constitutes a more plausible candidate minimal model than the more complicated versions explored by Maynard Smith and Price (1973).

  10. The expression ‘how-possibly explanations’ was originally used by Dray (1957, 1968) to indicate explanations that purport to account for how events whose occurrence was previously regarded as impossible could have occurred. Here I employ such expression to designate explanations that aim to identify possible causes of the examined phenomena, irrespective of whether the occurrence of these phenomena was previously regarded as impossible (for another characterization of how-possibly explanations that drops the presumption of impossibility, see e.g. Resnik 1991; for a recent discussion of how-possibly explanations, see e.g. Bokulich 2014; Forber 2012; Reydon 2012).

  11. Rohwer and Rice (2013, 341 and 349) put forward similar remarks concerning Maynard Smith and Parker’s (1976) Hawk–Dove model of animal conflict. However, Rohwer and Rice adopt a less restrictive characterization of ‘minimal model’ than the characterization underlying LMM, since they allow that some world-linking relation may hold between what they call ‘minimal models’ and real-world targets (see e.g. Rohwer and Rice 2013, 347). Hence, their calls for the possibility of learning from minimal models do not directly support LMM, and my critique of LMM does not directly apply to such calls (see footnote no. 13 for a similar point about Batterman and Rice 2014).

  12. The expression that models ‘come into clusters’ has been employed in different senses by scientific modellers. Below I use this expression to indicate situations where modellers’ predictive and explanatory goals are best achieved by using a combination of structurally dissimilar models.

  13. Batterman and Rice emphasize a similar point when they claim that minimal models can be used to explain why classes of heterogeneous target systems display the same large-scale behavior “by demonstrating that the details that distinguish the model system and [the target] systems are irrelevant” (2014, 350). However, Batterman and Rice adopt a less restrictive characterization of ‘minimal model’ than the characterization underlying LMM, since they allow that some world-linking relation may hold between what they call ‘minimal models’ and real-world targets (see e.g. Batterman and Rice 2014, 355). Hence, their calls for the possibility of learning from minimal models do not directly support LMM, and my critique of LMM does not directly apply to such calls (see footnote no. 11 for a similar point about Rohwer and Rice 2013).

  14. As Grüne-Yanoff puts it: “if model use merely contributes to the formulation of [a] hypothesis, then no learning takes place. Learning requires that the model effects justified changes of our confidence in the hypothesis, or if the model itself gave rise to its formulation that it forces us to form a belief about this newly-formulated hypothesis based on consideration of the model itself” (2009, 85).

References

  • Alfi, V., Cristelli, M., Pietronero, L., & Zaccaria, A. (2009). Minimal agent based model for financial markets I. European Physical Journal B: Condensed Matter and Complex Systems, 67, 385–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arthur, W. B., LeBaron, B., Palmer, B., & Taylor, R. (1997). Asset pricing under endogenous expectations in an artificial stock market. In W. B. Arthur, et al. (Eds.), Economy as an evolving complex system II (Vol. XXVII, pp. 15–44). Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aydinonat, N. E. (2007). Models, conjectures and exploration: An analysis of Schelling’s checkerboard model of residential segregation. Journal of Economic Methodology, 14, 429–454.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R. (2002). Asymptotics and the role of minimal models. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 53, 21–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R., & Rice, C. (2014). Minimal model explanations. Philosophy of Science, 81, 349–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bokulich, A. (2014). How the tiger bush got its stripes: ‘How possibly’ vs. ‘how actually’ model explanations. The Monist, 97, 321–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1999). Capacities. In J. B. Davis, D. W. Hands, & U. Mäki (Eds.), The handbook of economic methodology (pp. 45–48). Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (2009). If no capacities then no credible worlds. But can models reveal capacities? Erkenntnis, 70, 45–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casini, L. (2014). Not-so-minimal models. Between isolation and imagination. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 44, 646–672.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Donato Rodriguez, X., & Zamora Bonilla, J. (2009). Credibility, idealisation, and model building: An inferential approach. Erkenntnis, 70, 101–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dray, W. (1957). Laws and explanations in history. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dray, W. (1968). On explaining how-possibly. The Monist, 52, 390–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, R. A. (1930). The genetical theory of natural selection. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Forber, P. (2010). Confirmation and explaining how possible. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 41, 32–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forber, P. (2012). Conjecture and explanation: A reply to Reydon. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 43, 298–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fossett, M., & Dietrich, D. (2009). Effects of city size, shape, and form, and neighborhood size and shape in agent-based models of residential segregation: Are Schelling-style preference effects robust? Environment and Planning B: Planning and Design, 36(1), 149–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, S. (2003). A model-theoretic account of representation (or, I don’t know much about art…but I know it involves isomorphism). Philosophy of Science, 70, 1472–1483.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fumagalli, R. (2015). No learning from minimal models. Philosophy of Science, 82.

  • Giere, R. N. (2004). How models are used to represent reality. Philosophy of Science, 71, 742–752.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2006). The strategy of model-based science. Biology and Philosophy, 21, 725–740.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldenfeld, N. (1992). Lectures on phase transitions and the renormalization group. Frontiers in physics (Vol. 85). Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2009). Learning from minimal economic models. Erkenntnis, 70, 81–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2013a). Appraising models nonrepresentationally. Philosophy of Science, 80, 850–861.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2013b). Genuineness resolved: A reply to Reiss’ purported paradox. Journal of Economic Methodology, 20, 255–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman, D. M. (1992). The inexact and separate science of economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1962). Explanation in science and history. In R. Colodny (Ed.), Frontiers of science and philosophy (pp. 9–19). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila, T. (2009). Isolating representations vs. credible constructions? Economic modelling in theory and practice. Erkenntnis, 70, 59–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuorikoski, J., & Lehtinen, A. (2009). Incredible worlds, credible results. Erkenntnis, 70, 119–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuorikoski, J., Lehtinen, A., & Marchionni, C. (2010). Economic modelling as robustness analysis. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 61, 541–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuorikoski, J., Lehtinen, A., & Marchionni, C. (2012). Robustness analysis disclaimer: Please read the manual before use! Biology and Philosophy, 27, 891–902.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • LeBaron, B. (2006). Agent-based computational finance. In L. Tesfatsion & K. L. Judd (Eds.), Handbook of computational economics. Agent-based computational economics (Vol. 2, pp. 1187–1233). Amsterdam: Elsevier North Holland

  • Levins, R. (1966). The strategy of model building in population biology. American Scientist, 54, 421–431.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lux, T., & Marchesi, M. (1999). Scaling and criticality in a stochastic multi-agent model of a financial market. Nature, 397, 498–500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mäki, U. (1992). On the method of isolation in economics. Poznań Studies in the Philosophy of Science and the Humanities, 26, 316–351.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäki, U. (2005). Models are experiments, experiments are models. Journal of Economic Methodology, 12, 303–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mäki, U. (2009). MISSing the world. Models as isolations and credible surrogate systems. Erkenntnis, 70, 29–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith, J., & Parker, G. A. (1976). The logic of asymmetric contests. Animal Behavior, 24, 159–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith, J., & Price, G. R. (1973). The logic of animal conflict. Nature, 246, 15–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, M. S. (1999). Learning from Models. In X. Morgan & Z. Morrison (Eds.), Models as mediators: Perspectives on natural and social science (pp. 347–388). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, M. S. (2001). Models, stories and the economic world. Journal of Economic Methodology, 8, 361–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muldoon, R., Smith, T., & Weisberg, M. (2012). Segregation that no one seeks. Philosophy of Science, 79, 38–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pancs, R., & Vriend, N. J. (2007). Schelling’s spatial proximity model of segregation revisited. Journal of Public Economics, 91, 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pincock, C. (2012). Mathematical models of biological patterns: Lessons from Hamilton’s selfish herd. Biology and Philosophy, 27, 481–496.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reiner, R. (1993). Necessary conditions and explaining how-possibly. Philosophical Quarterly, 44, 58–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Resnik, D. B. (1991). How-possibly explanations in biology. Acta Biotheoretica, 39, 141–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reydon, T. (2012). How-possibly explanations as genuine explanations and helpful heuristics: A comment on Forber. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 43, 302–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rohwer, Y., & Rice, C. (2013). Hypothetical pattern idealization and explanatory models. Philosophy of Science, 80, 334–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. C. (1969). Models of segregation. American Economic Review, 59, 488–493.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. C. (1971). Dynamic models of segregation. Journal of Mathematical Sociology, 1, 143–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. C. (1972). The process of residential segregation: Neighbourhood tipping. In A. Pascal (Ed.), Racial discrimination in economic life (pp. 157–185). Lexington: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. C. (1978). Micromotives and macrobehavior. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. C. (2006). Strategies of commitment and other essays. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlimm, D. (2009). Learning from the existence of models: On psychic machines, tortoises, and computer simulations. Synthese, 169, 521–538.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schulz, A. W. (2012). Beyond the hype: The value of evolutionary theorizing in economics. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 20, 1–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2004). An inferential conception of scientific representation. Philosophy of Science, 71, 767–779.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2000). Credible worlds: The status of theoretical models in economics. Journal of Economic Methodology, 7, 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2009). Credible worlds. Capacities and Mechanisms, Erkenntnis, 70, 3–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2011). Explanations in search of observations. Biology and Philosophy, 26, 717–736.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2013). How fictional accounts can explain. Journal of Economic Methodology, 20, 237–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swoyer, C. (1991). Structural representation and surrogative reasoning. Synthese, 87, 449–508.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Teller, P. (2001). Twilight of the perfect model model. Erkenntnis, 55, 393–415.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2006). Robustness analysis. Philosophy of Science, 73, 730–742.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2007a). Three kinds of idealization. The Journal of Philosophy, 104, 639–659.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2007b). Who is a modeler? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 58, 207–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2012). Getting serious about similarity. Philosophy of Science, 79, 785–794.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2006). Some varieties of robustness. Journal of Economic Methodology, 13, 219–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wynne-Edwards, V. C. (1963). Intergroup selection in the evolution of social systems. Nature, 200, 623–626.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ylikoski, P., & Aydinonat, N. E. (2014). Understanding with theoretical models. Journal of Economic Methodology, 21, 19–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, J. (2004). Residential segregation in an all-integrationist world. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 54, 533–550.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank J. McKenzie Alexander, Jesus Zamora Bonilla, Lorenzo Casini, Till Grüne-Yanoff, Olivier Roy, Paul Teller, and Michael Weisberg for their comments on earlier versions of this paper. I also benefited from the observations of audiences at the Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy, the 6th Models and Simulations Conference at the University of Notre Dame, and the 24th Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association in Chicago. An earlier version of part of the paper appeared in the Proceedings of the 24th Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Roberto Fumagalli.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Fumagalli, R. Why We Cannot Learn from Minimal Models. Erkenn 81, 433–455 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-015-9749-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-015-9749-7

Keywords

Navigation