Skip to main content
Log in

Criteria of Theoreticity: Bridging Statement and Non-Statement View

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I reconstruct and compare criteria of theoreticity that have been developed by Carnap, Sneed and proponents of the Munich school of structuralist philosophy of science. For this purpose I develop a unified framework in which one can transform model-theoretic theory representations into linguistic ones, and vice versa. This bridges the gap between statement and non-statement view and allows a precise comparison of linguistic and model-theoretic criteria of theoreticity. In the final part I suggest a system of improved definitions of theoreticity and pre-theoreticity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. BR's for permanent dispositions entail the synthetical consequence ∃t(Txt∧Rxt) → ∀t(Txt → Rxt)); so they can be considered as "analytic" only relative to this assumption.

  2. Single quotation marks are used for stylistic and double ones for literal quotation.

  3. The implication R(T)→T is called the "Carnap-sentence" and expresses the analytic content of T in a global way, which is not "divisible" among the theory's axioms (s. Tuomela 1973, 59).

  4. Otherwise one incurs the so-called Newman problem according to which R(T) does not imply any restrictions on T's empirical submodels, except from possible cardinality restrictions on the domain, which means that the content of R(T) does not go "essentially" beyond T's empirical content (for further discussion see Ladyman and Ross 2007, 126f; Schurz 2014, chap. 5.8.2).

  5. More adequately one should also divide the domain(s) D into non-T-theoretical and T-theoretical individuals and restrict T's partial models to the subdomain Dn ⊆ D of non-T-theoretical individuals. This refinement is not made in structuralism. Balzer et al. (1987), 49, give an argument for why the notion of a particle is generally non-T-theoretical in classical particle mechanics. I don't think that their argument holds for microscopic entities—whether they behave particle-like or (e.g.) wave-like can only be determined using theories.

  6. The axiomatic changes are these: (EXT-in-ZFU): ∀x, y ∉ U(∀z(z ∈ x ↔ z ∈ y) → x = y). (FOUND-in-ZFU): ∀x ∉ U∪{Ø}∃y ∈ x(x ∩ y = Ø)). (UREL-1): ∀x ∈ U(∀y:y ∉ x). (UREL-2):∃B(BIJEC(ω, U)), where BIJEC(ω, U) is the formula asserting that B is a bijection from ω to U. Cf. Löwe (2006).

  7. Cf. van Dalen et al. (1978); Machover (1996). The formal translations can be lengthy. E.g., f:A→ B is translated as: ∀x∃y∃z(x ∈ f → x = (y, z)) ∧ ∀y∃x∃z(y ∈ A → x = (y, z)) ∧ ∀y∀z1, z2((y, z1) ∈ f ∧ (y, z2) ∈ f → z1 = z2), where subformulas of the form "x = (y, z)" have to be replaced by "∀u(u ∈ x ↔ u = y ∨ ∀w(w ∈ u ↔ w = y ∨ w = z))" (according to Kuratowski's definition of the pair (x, y) as {x, {x, y}}).

  8. To handle the problem of non-unique referents, Andreas (2010, def. 11) suggests partial truth values.

  9. The domain unification axiom should also hold for theory nets. Since the partial potential models of different theory lattices do not have all non-theoretical concepts in common, we must restrict this axiom here to those non-theoretical relations which are common to these models.

  10. I have put "essentially" in brackets, because if the additional axioms do not contain the concept rs essentially, this means by definition that there exist a formulation Ax++ of Ax+ which doesn't contain rs and is equivalent with Ax+ given the remainder axioms of T.

  11. A legitimate objection to def. 8 (suggested by a referee) could point out that the equivalent conditions (a) and (a*) are too strong, because several specializations of CPM are characterized by axioms which essentially involve the theoretical term whose values are to be determined. An example is the specialization of CPM by Hooke's law in regard to determinations of the force function. A similar problem is discussed in Balzer et al. (1987, 74f). It emerges from this discussion that if condition (a*) would be omitted, too many terms of a theory T would come out as T-theoretical; for example, the position function would come out as CPM-theoretical.

  12. This disadvantage applies also to the improved Sneed-criterion.

  13. Alternatively, one could allow that pre-theories contain new theoretical concepts and assume a well-founded ordering of "theoreticity-levels" of concepts. We cannot deal here with these complications. The idea of a pre-theory has been explicated in a slightly different way by Balzer and Mühlhölzer (1982). Similar ideas can also be found in Balzer et al. (1987), 58f, where "pre-theoreticity" is modeled by intertheoretical links.

References

  • Andreas, H. (2010). New account of empirical claims in structuralism. Synthese, 176, 311–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreas, H. (2013). Theoretical terms in science. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2013 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/theoretical-terms-science/.

  • Balzer, W. (1985a). On a new definition of theoreticity. Dialectica, 39, 127–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balzer, W. (1985b). Theorie und Messung. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Balzer, W. (1996). Theoretical terms: Recent developments. In W. Balzer, C. U. (Eds.) Structuralist theory of science (pp. 139–166). Berlin: W. de Gruyter.

  • Balzer, W., & Moulines, C. U. (1980). On theoreticity. Synthese, 44, 467–494.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balzer, W., Moulines, C. U., & Sneed, J. D. (1987). An architectonic for science. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Balzer, W., & Mühlhölzer, F. (1982). Klassische Stoßmechanik. Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie, 13, 22–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balzer, W., & Reiter, M. (1988). Completeness for systems including real numbers. Studia Logica, 48(1), 67–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1936/37). Testability and meaning. Philosophy of Science, 3, 419–471 und Vol. 4, 2–40.

  • Carnap, R. (1947). Meaning and necessity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1956). The methodological character of theoretical concepts. In H. Feigl & M. Scriven (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. I, pp. 38–76). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1958). Beobachtungssprache und theoretische Sprache. Dialectica, 12, 236–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1963). Carl G. Hempel on scientific theories. In P. A. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap (pp. 958–965) La Salle.

  • French, S. (2008). The structure of theories. In S. Psillos & M. Curd (Eds.), The Routledge companion to philosophy of science (pp. 269–280). London, New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gähde, U. (1983). T-theoretizität und Holismus. Frankfurt/M: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gähde, U. (1990). On innertheoretical conditions for theoretical terms. Er-kenntnis, 32, 215–233.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, N. R. (1958). Patterns of discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J. H. (1979). A semantical alternative to the Sneed-Stegmüller-Kuhn conception of scientific theories. In I. Niiniluoto, R. Tuomela (Eds.), Acta philosophica Fennica, Vol. 30, no. 2–4, pp. 184–204.

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions 1996 (3rd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., & Ross, D. (2007). Every thing must go. Metaphysics naturalized, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (With D. Spurrett and J. Collier).

  • Lewis, D. (1970). How to define theoretical terms. Journal of Philosophy, 67, 427–446.

    Google Scholar 

  • Löwe, B. (2006). Set theory with and without urelements and categories of interpretation. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 47(1), 83–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machover, M. (1996). Set theory, logic, and their limitations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maxwell, G. (1962). The ontological status of theoretical entities. In H. Feigl & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. III, pp. 3–27). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1962). What theories are not. In E. Nagel, P. Suppes, & A. Tarski (Eds.), Logic, methodology and philosophy of science (pp. 240–251). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheibe, E. (1982/2001). A comparison of two recent views on theories. Metamedicine 3, 193, 233–253; reprinted in Scheibe, E. (2001), Between rationalism and empiricism (ed. by B. Falkenburg), New York: Springer, pp. 175–194.

  • Schurz, G. (1990). Paradoxical consequences of Balzer’s and Gähde’s criteria of theoreticity. Erkenntnis, 32, 161–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2014). Philosophy of science: A unified approach. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sneed, J. D. (1971). The logical structure of mathematical physics. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stegmüller, W. (1976). The structure and dynamics of scientific theories. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stegmüller, W. (1986). Probleme und Resultate der Wissenschaftstheorie und Analytischen Philosophie. Band II.3: Die Entwicklung des neuen Strukturalismus seit 1973, Berlin: Springer.

  • Suppes, P. (1957). Introduction to logic. Princeton: D. Van Nostrand Comp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. (1973). Theoretical concepts. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Dalen, D., de Swart, H., & Doets, H. (1978). Sets. Naive, axiomatic and applied. Oxford: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image (new ed. 1990). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

For valuable comments I am indebted to Ulises Moulines, Holger Andreas, Hannes Leitgeb, Ulrich Gädhe, Wolfgang Balzer, and two anonymous referees.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gerhard Schurz.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Schurz, G. Criteria of Theoreticity: Bridging Statement and Non-Statement View. Erkenn 79 (Suppl 8), 1521–1545 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-013-9581-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-013-9581-x

Keywords

Navigation