Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Domestic judicial defiance and the authority of international legal regimes

  • Published:
European Journal of Law and Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Tensions and occasional overt defiance of international courts suggest that compliance with international regimes is not a self-evident choice for domestic judges. I develop a formal theory of domestic judicial defiance in which domestic and supranational judges vie for jurisprudential authority in a non-hierarchical setting. The model emphasises the role of domestic non-compliance costs and power asymmetries in determining the conduct of domestic and international judges. I argue that the EU represents a special case of a particularly effective international regime. Weak domestic courts have little to gain from an escalated conflict with the European court of Justice. But even domestic judicial superpowers like the German Federal Constitutional Court have strong incentives to seek mutual accommodation with European judges. The analysis also yields new insights into concepts, such as “judicial dialogue” and “constitutional pluralism” that have featured prominently in the legal literature, and suggests new hypotheses for empirical research.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The US Supreme Court was explicitly granted the authority to reverse state court decisions by Section 25 of the 1789 Judiciary Act. A prerogative the Court first put to use against Virginian courts in Fairfax’s Devisee v. Hunter’s Lessee, 11 U.S. 603 (1813) (Story, J.).

  2. Tribunal Supremo de Justicia, Decision No. 1939 of 18 Dec. 2008, Gustavo Álvarez et al..

  3. Experiments show that play is more likely to converge towards strategic Nash-prescribed equilibrium when players have already taken the game several times (Nagel 1995).

  4. Since covert non-compliance is less costly for the international regime and, for the same reason, less likely to trigger court curbing at domestic level, we might speculate that it is more prevalent in advanced regimes. However, I leave it to future research to identify when domestic judges will opt for covert rather than overt defiance.

  5. As my analysis shall make clear, inter-court tensions do not always result in an actual case being adjudicated where jurisdictional boundaries are explicitly spelled out. This is why “jurisdiction” in our model cannot be defined in purely doctrinal terms as the sum of all formal authority-asserting statements.

  6. A more comprehensive model of national-international court interaction would also consider the conditions under which judges sharing the same agenda will want to cooperate. This question, however, lies outside the scope of the present paper, which focuses on judicial defiance—that is, on situations where domestic and international judges pursue antagonistic interests.

  7. Surely, some international legal regimes, such as the EU and the Andean Community, allow international judges to intervene directly in domestic disputes via interlocutory procedures. Yet such procedures, like the preliminary ruling mechanism in the EU, can only be activated at the behest of domestic judges.

  8. A large C value may also reflect a low degree of judicial independence. This captures the basic notion that courts lacking institutional autonomy have incentives to kowtow to the preferences of the other branches.

  9. Possible extensions to this basic model would consider the possibility for judicial agendas to converge (with the possibility that \(J<0\)) along with the possibility for legislators to punish the Domestic Court for upholding, rather than for flouting, international law. (In many countries, legislative opposition to international law rather than judicial resistance may be the principal obstacle to the domestic application of international legal rules.) Also, whereas I presume the legislative reaction to be exogenous to the courts’ behaviour, there may be scenarios where conceptualising legislative behaviour as endogenous to judicial decision making might make more sense. But I leave these extensions for future research.

  10. Because best response, unlike dominance, presupposes complete information as well as common knowledge of rationality, it is also behaviourally less robust (see Costa-Gomes et al. 2001). Empirically speaking, we are thus more likely to observe unilateral departures from the equilibrium outcome in the case of international judges. As the fate of the Southern African Development Community (SADC) Tribunal illustrates, though, a weak international court that misjudges the preferences of domestic courts does so at its own peril. In the first salient case it was given to review, the SADC Tribunal ruled that Zimbabwe’s farm eviction amendment amounted to de facto discrimination of white farmers. Yet not only did the High Court of Zimbabwe refuse to enforce the judgement but member state governments subsequently proceeded to disband the Tribunal.

  11. As long as \(3J>C>0\), the game is a Prisoner’s Dilemma.

  12. Defiance in one member state, though, may have a domino-effect in other member countries as each defection makes commitment to the regime less valuable until the tipping point where the regime begins to collapse. I leave it to future work to explore how interactions among courts in different member states may affect compliance dynamics.

  13. These doctrines illustrate the general assumption underlying the present analysis that legal reasoning rarely constitutes a real constraint on judicial decision making in cases pertaining to the relationship between international and domestic law.

  14. 22 December 1978, Ministre de l’intérieur v. Cohn-Bendit, Rec. 524.

  15. The Hawk–Dove Game is also known as the Game of Chicken, and less famously as the Snowdrift Game.

  16. The analysis here is predicated on the interpretation of mixed-strategy equilibria as equilibria in actions. An alternative, and arguably more realistic, interpretation is to see mixed-strategy equilibria as equilibria in beliefs (Aumann and Brandenburger 1995).

  17. This sequence is consonant with accounts of the decision making practices of activist international courts by legal scholars. Trevor Hartley, for example, observed that the ECJ frequently follows a test the waters tactic to develop its case law:

    A common tactic is to introduce a doctrine gradually: in the first case that comes before it, the Court will establish the doctrine as a general principle but suggest that it is subject to various qualifications; the Court may even find some reason why it should not be applied to the particular facts of the case. The principle, however, is now established. If there are not too many protests, it will be re-affirmed in later cases; the qualifications then can be whittled away and the full extent of the doctrine revealed (Hartley 1988, 78–79).

  18. Note, though, that the act disapplied does not have to be a judgement issued by the International Court but may be another rule emanating from the same international regime (e.g. a decision enacted by the European Central Bank or the Commission in the case of the EU).

  19. For illustrations of what these moves may concretely amount to I refer to the examples provided in the introduction and the discussion in Sect. 5.

  20. This, of course, is a simplification. After an interaction, real-world courts will usually learn something, but not everything about each others’ true preferences.

  21. As the real-world cost associated with writing obiter dicta is close to zero, it is more realistic to model it as cheap talk. In the international relations literature communication is usually treated as costly signal (Fearon 1994; Putnam 1988). However, it has been demonstrated that communication can be consequential, as part of a reputation-building strategy, even when modelled as cheap talk (Sartori 2002).

  22. It does so according to Bayes’ Rule.

  23. The equilibrium can also be shown to exist, albeit for a smaller range of parameter values, when allowing for forgiveness after a certain number of periods. The Grim Trigger variant I use here is for ease of exposition.

  24. This requires that \(-J^{l}>-J^{h}>\dfrac{J^{h}-C}{2}>\dfrac{J^{l}-C}{2}\) for the Domestic Court, and \(-\alpha _{l}>-\alpha _{h}>\dfrac{\alpha -\beta }{2}\) for the International Court.

  25. Provided other equilibrium conditions are met, when \(p=1\) and \(q=0\), the equilibrium breaks down as the Domestic Court becomes indifferent between cooperation and deviation. The opposite asymmetry, \(p=0\) and \(q=1\), results in what amounts to a Domestic Supremacy Equilibrium. (The Domestic Court can, under this hypothesis, effectively use its signal to impose permanent acquiescence on an International Court otherwise indifferent between cooperation and defection.) These scenarios seem empirically implausible, however. In practice, judicial preferences on the same court are likely to vary in intensity across policy areas.

  26. While parallels with Cold War relations have been made in scholarly writings (Weiler and Haltern 1996), a prominent GFCC judge, Udo di Fabio, has explicitly used the expression “pacific coexistence” (friedliche Koexistenz in German) to characterise the sort of relationship the German Court wants to establish with the European Court (see Fabio 2010).

  27. Another illustration of successful containment by domestic judges is offered by the UK Supreme Court in its dispute with the European Court of Human Rights over the status of hearsay evidence in criminal proceedings. In its first chamber judgement, Al-Khawaja and Tahery v United Kingdom, the Strasbourg Court held that criminal conviction could not be solely or decisively based on hearsay evidence. In R v Horncastle, however, the UK Supreme Court explicitly declined to follow this holding. The Grand Chamber of the European Court of Human Rights, though, averted further escalation by overruling the chamber decision, yielding in effect to the position of the British Court. (I am thankful to an anonymous reviewer for pointing me this example.)

  28. A weak domestic court, however, may use defiant language as a means to signal to a strong national court in the hope of encouraging to join the cause. Exploring the conditions under which this sort of horizontal dialogue can actually be consequential may be an interesting avenue for future research on inter-court dynamics in heterarchical systems.

  29. In other situations and inasmuch as there is no history of defection, signalling hawkishness does not change the behaviour of the International Court in the current period. Meanwhile, signalling becomes inconsequential after a court has been caught deviating.

References

  • Alter, K. J. (1998). Explaining national courts acceptance of European Court jurisprudence: A critical evaluation of theories of legal integration. In A.-M. Slaughter, A. Stone Sweet, & J. H. H. Weiler (Eds.), The European court and national courts—Doctrine and jurisprudence (Vol. 232). Oxford: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alter, K. J. (2001). Establishing the supremacy of European law: The making of an international rule of law in Europe. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alter, K. J. (2012). The global spread of European style international courts. West European Politics, 35(1), 135–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alter, K. J., & Helfer, L. R. (2010). Nature or nurture? Judicial lawmaking in the European court of Justice and the andean tribunal of justice. International Organization, 64(04), 563–592.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arnull, A. (2012). Judicial dialogue in the European Union. In J. Dickson & P. Eleftheriadis (Eds.), Philosophical foundations of European Union law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aumann, R., & Brandenburger, A. (1995). Epistemic conditions for nash equilibrium. Econometrica, 63(5), 1161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Axelrod, R. M. (1984). The evolution of cooperation. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bobek, M. (2014). Landtová, holubec, and the problem of an uncooperative court: Implications for the preliminary rulings procedure. European Constitutional Law Review (EuConst), 10(01), 54–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cameron, C., Segal, J., & Songer, D. (2000). Strategic auditing in a political hierarchy: An informational model of the supreme court’s certiorari decisions. American Political Science Review, 94, 101–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carrubba, C. J. (2005). Courts and compliance in international regulatory regimes. Journal of Politics, 67(3), 669–689.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carrubba, C. J., & Murrah, L. (2005). Legal integration and use of the preliminary ruling process in the European Union. International Organization, 59(02), 399–418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Costa-Gomes, M., Crawford, V. P., & Broseta, B. (2001). Cognition and behavior in normal-form games: An experimental study. Econometrica, 69(5), 1193–1235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dehousse, R. (1998). The European court of Justice: The politics of judicial integration. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Downs, G. W., Rocke, D. M., & Barsoom, P. N. (1996). Is the good news about compliance good news about cooperation? International Organization, 50(03), 379–406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dyevre, A. (2010). Unifying the field of comparative judicial politics: Towards a general theory of judicial behaviour. European Political Science Review, 2(02), 297–327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dyevre, A. (2013). European integration and national courts: Defending sovereignty under institutional constraints? European Constitutional Law Review (EuConst), 9(01), 139–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, L., Landes, W. M., & Posner, R. A. (2013). The behavior of federal judges: A theoretical and empirical study of rational choice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fabio, U. D. (2010). Gastbeitrag Friedliche Koexistenz. FAZ.NET .

  • Fearon, J. D. (1994). Domestic political audiences and the escalation of international disputes. The American Political Science Review, 88(3), 577.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fudenberg, D., & Tirole, J. (1991). Game theory. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garrett, G., Daniel Kelemen, R., & Schulz, H. (1998). The European court of Justice, national governments, and legal integration in the European Union. International Organization, 52(01), 149–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Golub, J. (1996). The politics of judicial discretion: Rethinking the interaction between national courts and the Eurpean court of Justice. West European Politics, 19(2), 360–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grimmett, J. J. (2011). World Trade Organization (WTO) decisions and their effect in US law. Congressional Research Service .

  • Hartley, T. C. (1988). The foundation of European community law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herzog, R. (2008) Stoppt den EuGh. Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitung .

  • Huneeus, A. (2011). Courts resisting courts: Lessons from the inter-American court’s struggle to enforce human rights. Cornell International Law Journal, 44, 493.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huneeus, A. (2013). Compliance with international court judgments decisions. In C. Romano, K. J. Alter, & Y. Shany (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of international adjudication (pp. 438–463). Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kastellec, J. P. (2007). Panel composition and judicial compliance on the US courts of appeals. JLEO, 23(2), 421–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keohane, R. O., Moravcsik, A., & Slaughter, A.-M. (2000). Legalized dispute resolution: Interstate and transnational. International Organization, 54(03), 457–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kumm, M. (2005). The jurisprudence of constitutional conflict: Constitutional supremacy in Europe before and after the constitutional treaty. European Law Journal, 11, 173–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kümmerli, R., Colliard, C., Fiechter, N., Petitpierre, B., Russier, F., & Keller, L. (2007). Human Cooperation in social dilemmas: Comparing the snowdrift game with the Prisoner’s Dilemma. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 274(1628), 2965–2970.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lax, J. (2003). Certiorari and compliance in the judicial hierarchy: Discretion, reputation and the rule of four. Journal of Theoretical Politics, 15(1), 61–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCormick, N. (1999). Questioning sovereignty: Law, state, and nation in the European Commonwealth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, R. (1995). Unraveling in guessing games: An experimental study. The American Economic Review, 85, 1313–1326.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nollkaemper, A. (2013). Conversations among courts: Domestic and international adjudicators. In C. P. R. Romano, K. J. Alter, & Y. Shany (Eds.), Handbook of international adjudication (pp. 524–549). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nollkaemper, A. (2014). The duality of direct effect of international law. European Journal of International Law, 25(1), 105–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poiares Maduro, M. (2003). Contrapunctual law: Europe’s constitutional pluralism in action. In N. Walker (Ed.), Sovereignty in transition (pp. 501–537). Oxford: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollack, M. A. (2013). Political science and international adjudication. In C. Romano, K. J. Alter, & Y. Shany (Eds.), The Oxford Handbook of International Adjudication (p. 357). Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, R. (1988). Diplomacy and domestic politics: The logic of two-level games. International Organization, 42(03), 427–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sadurski, W. (2008). ‘Solange, chapter 3’: Constitutional courts in central Europe—Democracy—European Union. European Law Journal, 14(1), 1–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartori, A. E. (2002). The might of the pen: A reputational theory of communication in international disputes. International Organization, 56(01), 121–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmid, C. U. (2001). All bark no bite: Notes on the federal constitutional court’s “Banana Decision”. European Law Journal, 7, 95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sharkey, C. M. (2009). Federal incursions and state defiance: Punitive damages in the wake of Philip Morris v Williams. Willamette Law Review, 46, 449.

    Google Scholar 

  • Staton, J. K., & Moore, W. H. (2011). Judicial power in domestic and international politics. International Organization, 65(03), 553–587.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stein, T. (2011). Always steering a straight course? The German federal constitutional court and European integration. ERA Forum, 12(1), 219–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stephenson, M. C. (2009). Legal realism for economists. The Journal of Economic Perspectives, 23(2), 191–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stone Sweet, A. (2004). The Judicial construction of Europe. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stone Sweet, A., & Brunell, T. (1998). Constructing a supranational constitution: Dispute resolution and Governance in the European Community. American Political Science Review, 92, 63–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szczerbiak, A., & Taggart, P. A. (Eds.). (2008). Opposing Europe? Volume 2: Comparative and theoretical perspectives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taggart, P., & Szczerbiak, A. (Eds.). (2008). Opposing Europe? The comparative party politics of Euroscepticism: Volume 1: Case studies and country surveys. Oxford: OUP.

  • Weiler, J. H. H. (2009). The “Lisbon Urteil” and the fast food culture. European Journal of International Law, 20(3), 505–509.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weiler, J. H. H., & Haltern, U. R. (1996). The autonomy of the community legal order—Through the looking glass. Harvard International Law Journal, 37, 411.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westerland, C., Segal, J. A., Epstein, L., Cameron, C. M., & Comparato, S. (2010). Strategic defiance and compliance in the U.S. courts of appeals. American Journal of Political Science, 54(4), 891–905.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Arthur Dyevre.

Appendices

Appendix 1: Proof of coexistence equilibrium

Proof is based on the one-stage deviation principle for infinite-horizon games (Fudenberg and Tirole 1991, 110). It demonstrates that no player can gain by unilaterally deviating from the actions prescribed by the coexistence equilibrium in any single period t, for all relevant histories h.

1. Beginning with the Domestic Court at the last node of the stage game after the International Court played M, it is easy to see that, to the extent that no court has been caught deviating (denote this history as \(h_{1}\)), the Domestic Court does not gain by playing D rather than \(\sim D\). As long as no history of deviation exists (history \(=h_{1}\)), playing D does not only precipitate a constitutional crisis but because it itself constitutes deviation from the equilibrium path it triggers punishment from the International Court in subsequent periods. For the Domestic Court, the present value of compliance in this situation is at a minimum:

$$\begin{aligned} PV_{domestic}(compliance|h_{1})&= -J^{h}+\dfrac{\delta }{1-\delta }\left( \dfrac{1}{2}qpJ^{h}-\dfrac{1}{2}qpJ^{h}+q(1-p)J^{h}\right. \\&\left. -(1-q)pJ^l+\dfrac{1}{2}(1-q)(1-p)J^l-\dfrac{1}{2}(1-q)(1-p)J^l\right) \end{aligned}$$
(1)

This simplifies to:

$$\begin{aligned} PV_{domestic}(compliance|h_{1})=-J^{h}+\dfrac{\delta }{1-\delta }\left( q(1-p)J^{h}-(1-q)pJ^{l}\right) \end{aligned}$$
(2)

For the same history, the present value of defection is at most:

$$\begin{aligned} PV_{domestic}(defection|h_{1})=\dfrac{J^h-C}{2}+\dfrac{\delta }{1-\delta }\left( -qJ^{h}-(1-q)J^{l}\right) \end{aligned}$$
(3)

Therefore, as long as \(PV_{domestic}(compliance|h_{1})>PV_{domestic}(defection|h_{1})\) the Domestic Court is better off playing \(\sim D\). On the other hand, if the International Court has been caught deviating either in the current period (by playing M out of turn) or at the end of any previous period (denote this history as \(h_{2}\)), the Domestic Court must punish the International Court as is prescribed by the Coexistence Equilibrium. In that case, the present value of compliance for the Domestic Court is at a minimum:

$$\begin{aligned} PV_{domestic}(compliance|h_{2})=\dfrac{J^{l}-C}{2}+\dfrac{\delta }{1-\delta }\left( qJ^{h}+(1-q)J^{l}\right) \end{aligned}$$
(4)

whereas the Domestic Court’s unwillingness to punish entails that the present value of defection is at best:

$$\begin{aligned} PV_{domestic}(defection|h_{2})=-J^{l}+\dfrac{\delta }{1-\delta }\left( -qJ^{h}-(1-q)J^{l}\right) \end{aligned}$$
(5)

(unwillingness to punish means playing M is always safe for the International Court). The incentive compatibility constraint, therefore, is:

$$\begin{aligned} \dfrac{J^{l}-C}{2}+\dfrac{\delta }{1-\delta }\left( qJ^{h}+(1-q)J^{l}\right) >-J^{l}+\dfrac{\delta }{1-\delta }\left( -qJ^{h}-(1-q)J^{l}\right) \end{aligned}$$
(6)

2. We now consider the International Court at the penultimate node of the stage game. It is easy to see that, given history \(=h_{1}\), the International Court has no incentive to defect when it is of type = hawk and the Domestic Court signals \(\sim T\); the same applies when the Domestic Court was caught deviating in a previous period; ditto, for \(h_{1}\), when the International Court is of type = dove, but the last time the courts were of type = dove the Domestic Court had its way. Now, if there was no deviation in previous period but the last time the two courts were of type = hawk the Domestic Court yielded (denote this history as \(h_{1a}\)), and the Domestic Court signalled T in the current period, the present value of compliance (which involves playing \(\sim M\) in the current period) for the hawkish International Court is captured by:

$$\begin{aligned} PV_{international}(compliance|h_{1a},T)=-\alpha ^{h}+\dfrac{\delta }{1-\delta }\left( p(1-q)\alpha ^{h}-(1-p)q\alpha ^{l}\right) \end{aligned}$$
(7)

Because it involves making an immediate concession on an issue relatively dearer to its judges, Eq. (7) is when the present value of compliance is smallest for the International Court. By playing M out of turn, though, the International Court immediately reveals deviation, which triggers undelayed punishment by the Domestic Court:

$$\begin{aligned} PV_{international}(defection|h_{1a},T)=\dfrac{\alpha ^{h}-\beta }{2}+\dfrac{\delta }{1-\delta }\left( -p\alpha ^{h}-(1-p)\alpha ^{l}\right) \end{aligned}$$
(8)

(Immediate punishment means the International Court incurs the cost associated with a constitutional crisis in the present period while facing the prospect of perpetual punishment in subsequent periods.) Therefore, the International Court is most tempted to deviate from the equilibrium path when it is type \(=dove\), given one of the two following situations: the Domestic Court played T in the current period (thus signalling hawkishness) and the last time the two courts were of type \(=hawk\) the International Court yielded (denote this history as \(h_{1b}\)); the Domestic Court played \(\sim T\) in the current period and the previous time both courts were of type \(=dove\) the International Court had its way (denote this history as \(h_{1c}\)). The present value of compliance for the International Court in both scenarios is thus captured by:

$$\begin{aligned} PV_{international}(compliance|h_{1b},T)&= PV_{ecj}(compliance|h_{1c},\sim T)=-\alpha ^l+ \\&\dfrac{\delta }{1-\delta }\left( p(1-q)\alpha ^{h}-(1-p)q\alpha ^{l}\right) \end{aligned}$$
(9)

whereas the present value of defection is:

$$\begin{aligned} PV_{international}(defection|h_{1b},T)& = PV_{ecj}(defection|h_{1c},\sim T)=\alpha ^l+ \\&\dfrac{\delta }{1-\delta }\left( p(1-q)\alpha ^{h}-(1-p)q\alpha ^{l}\right) \end{aligned}$$
(10)

Therefore, the International Court is better off complying insofar as:

$$\begin{aligned} -\alpha ^l+\dfrac{\delta }{1-\delta }\left( p(1-q)\alpha ^{h}-(1-p)q\alpha ^{l}\right) >\alpha ^{l}+\dfrac{\delta }{1-\delta }\left( -p\alpha ^{h}-(1-p)\alpha ^l\right) \end{aligned}$$
(11)

3. Finally, we consider the Domestic Court at the communication stage. The only situation in which defection can make the Domestic Court better off is when it is type \(=dove\) and the previous time both courts were type \(=hawk\) it yielded while the last time the courts were both type \(=dove\) the International Court yielded (denote this history as \(h_{1d}\)).Footnote 29 In that case, the present value of compliance for the Domestic Court is captured by:

$$\begin{aligned} PV_{domestic}(compliance|h_{1d})=-J^l+\dfrac{\delta }{1-\delta }\left( q(1-p)J^{h}-(1-q)pJ^{l}\right) \end{aligned}$$
(12)

The present value of defection for the same circumstances is:

$$\begin{aligned} PV_{domestic}(defection|h_{1d})=J^{l}+\dfrac{\delta }{1-\delta }\left( -qJ^{h}-(1-q)J^l\right) \end{aligned}$$
(13)

This reflects the situation where the doveish Domestic Court plays T in the current period, which in turn induces the International Court to infer that its true type \(=hawk\). As a result, the International Court plays \(\sim M\) and the Domestic accrues payoff \(J^{l}\). However, at the end of the period, the International Court observes the Domestic Court’s true type and punishment ensues. So the Domestic Court is better of telling the truth as long as:

$$\begin{aligned} -J^l+\dfrac{\delta }{1-\delta }\left( q(1-p)J^{h}-(1-q)pJ^{l}\right) >J^{l}+\dfrac{\delta }{1-\delta }\left( -qJ^{h}-(1-q)J^l\right) \end{aligned}$$
(14)

Appendix 2: Proof of international law expansion equilibrium

Proof of the International Law Expansion Equilibrium is straightforward. At the last node of the stage game, the Domestic Court cannot improve its lot by revolting against the International Court, as this brings about a constitutional crisis in the current period without stopping the court of Justice’s activism in subsequent periods. Regardless of history, the present value of compliance for the Domestic Court is at a minimum:

$$\begin{aligned} PV_{domestic}(compliance)=-J^{h}+\dfrac{\delta }{1-\delta }\left( -qJ^{h}-(1-q)J^l\right) \end{aligned}$$
(15)

Positing that the Domestic Court prefers a jurisdictional loss over a constitutional crisis, this implicates that it is strictly better off complying. Knowing this, the International Court has no reason to deviate from M at the preceding node. The lack of credible domestic deterrence entails, in turn, that the Domestic Court’s signal has no effect.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dyevre, A. Domestic judicial defiance and the authority of international legal regimes. Eur J Law Econ 44, 453–481 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10657-016-9551-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10657-016-9551-2

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation