Skip to main content
Log in

Teaching Business Ethics Through Popular Feature Films: An Experiential Approach

  • Published:
Journal of Business Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Based on our experience in teaching ethics, we have developed, tested, and presented in this article a program of instruction that rests on four pillars: popular feature films, a six-stage ethical decision-making process, the principles necessary to address ethical situations, and the classroom instructor. Taken separately, there is nothing new or unique in these pillars. Taken together, however, and to our knowledge, these four pillars, including the requirement that each student is expected to prepare a written abstract of the film prior to the classroom discussion of that film in which the student is expected to demonstrate a practical application of ethical principles to actual and concrete moral situations, constitute a new, unique, and tested way to teach ethics to undergraduate students of management and economics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This question is at the heart of the current heated conflict in the United States regarding the Department of Health and Human Services mandate requiring private employer health insurance benefits plans to provide free preventive health services to women employees.

  2. Philosophy and Religion in Film: A List (no date) identifies “about 200 noteworthy films that deal with philosophical and religious themes,” including short lists of films under these headings: ethics, journalistic ethics, business ethics, and environmental ethics. None of the films enumerated below, which we employed successfully with our students, are to be found on that list.

References

  • Anderson, R., Johnson, D., Gotterbarn, D., & Perrolle, J. (1993). Using the ACM code of ethics in decision making. Communications of the ACM, 36(2), 98–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bayles, M. (1981). Professional ethics. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benestad, J. B. (2012). A catholic response to Henry George’s critique of Pope Leo XIII’s Rerum Novarum. American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 71(4), 913–937.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berger, J., & Pratt, C. (1998). Teaching business-communication ethics with controversial films. Journal of Business Ethics, 17(16), 1817–1823.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blair, R. J. R. (2007). The amygdala and ventromedial prefrontal cortex in morality and psychopathy. Trends in Cognitive Science, 11(9), 387–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blum, L. (1991). Moral perception and particularity. Ethics, 101(4), 701–725.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bosco, S., Melchar, D. E., Beauvais, L. L., & Desplaces, D. E. (2010). Teaching business ethics: The effectiveness of common pedagogical practices in developing students’ moral judgment competence. Ethics and Education, 5(3), 263–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, D. (2011). Proportionality in modern just war theory: A tort-based approach. Journal of Military Ethics, 10(3), 213–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruni, L. (2004). The ‘happiness transformation problem’ in the Cambridge tradition. European Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 11(3), 433–451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chappell, T. (2002). Two distinctions that do make a difference: The action/omission distinction and the principle of double effect. Philosophy, 77(300), 211–233.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dale, E. (1969). Audio-visual methods in teaching (3rd ed.). New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Danner, P. (2002). The economic person: Acting and analyzing. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeMartino, G. (2011). The economist’s oath: On the need for and the content of professional economic ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dinstein, Y. (2001). Just war or just peace? Humanitarian intervention and international law. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doris, J. M. (2002). Lack of character: Personality and moral behavior. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fadel, C., & C. Lemke. (2008). Multimodal learning through media: What the research says. Retrieved January 31, 2013, from http://www.cisco.com/web/strategy/docs/education/Multimodal-Learning-Through-Media.pdf.

  • Fisher, R., & Price, L. (1992). An investigation into the social context of early adoption behavior. Journal of Consumer Research, 19(12), 477–486.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fontrodona, J., & Argandoña, A. (2011). A panoramic view of business ethics. Universia Business Review, 30(1), 12–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, S. (2005). Moral contractarianism as a foundation for interpersonal morality. Contemporary debates. In J. Drier (Ed.), Moral theory (pp. 57–76). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. (2006). The happiness hypothesis. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J., & Graham, J. (2007). When morality opposes justice: Conservatives have moral intuitions that liberals may not recognize. Social Justice Research, 20(1), 98–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardy, S. A., & Carlo, G. (2011). Moral identity: What is it, how does it develop, and is it linked to moral action? Child Development, 5(3), 212–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartman, E. M. (2008). Reconciliation in business ethics: Some advice from Aristotle. Business Ethics Quarterly, 18(2), 253–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, T. [1651]. (2009). Leviathan or the matter, form and power of a common wealth ecclesiastical and civil. Reprint. Lawrence, KS: Digireads.com Publishing.

  • Hosmer, L., & Steneck, N. (1989). Teaching business ethics: The use of films and videotapes. Journal of Business Ethics, 8(12), 929–936.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • IBSCDC. (no date). Movie-based case studies. Retrieved October 25, 2012, from www.ibscdc.org/movie-based-case-studies.asp.

  • Kant, I. [1785] (1969). Grundlegung zur metaphysik der sitten (Lewis W. Beck, Trans.). In R. P. Wolff (Ed.), Foundations of the metaphysics of morals, section 2. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill.

  • Kaptein, M. (2011). Understanding ethical behavior by unraveling ethical culture. Human Relations, 64(6), 843–869.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laditka, S. B., & Houck, M. (2006). Student-developed case studies: An experiential approach for teaching ethics in management. Journal of Business Ethics, 64(2), 157–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lauder, R. (2002). Business, cinema and sin. Teaching Business Ethics, 6(1), 63–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leffel, G. M. (2008). Who cares? Generativity and the moral emotions, part 2: A social intuitionist model of moral motivation. Journal of Psychology and Theology, 36(3), 182–201.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1981). After virtue: A study in moral theory. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maina, W. M. (2011). The common good and/or the human rights: Analysis of some papal social encyclicals and their contemporary relevance. Journal of the Study of Religions and Ideologies, 10(29), 3–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mattingly, C. (2012). Two virtue ethics and the anthropology of morality. Anthropological Theory, 12(2), 161–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCormick, M. (2005). Kant’s theory of mind in the critique of pure reason’s subjective deduction. Journal of Value Inquiry, 39(3), 353–381.

    Google Scholar 

  • McWilliams, V., & Nahavandi, A. (2006). Using live cases to teach ethics. Journal of Business Ethics, 67(4), 421–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Medema, S. G. (2007). Sidgwick’s utilitarian analysis of law: A bridge from Bentham to Becker? American Law and Economic Review, 9(1), 30–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Melé, D. (2009). Integrating personalism into virtue-based business ethics: The personalist and the common good principles. Journal of Business Ethics, 88(1), 227–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Melé, D. (2012). Management ethics: Placing ethics at the core of good management. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, W., & Delaney, H. D. (Eds.). (2005). Judeo-Christian perspectives on psychology: Human nature, motivation, and change. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Myyry, L. (2003). Components of morality. A professional ethics perspective on moral motivation, moral sensitivity, moral reasoning and related constructs among university students. Department of Social Psychology, University of Helsinki, Helsinki.

  • NLRA. (1935). National Labor Relations Act. Also known as Wagner Act. Retrieved December 2, 2012, from http://www.ourdocuments.gov/doc.php?flash-true&doc-67.

  • NSSE. (2012). National Survey of Student Engagement. Promoting student learning and institutional improvement: Lessons from NSSE at 13. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Center for Postsecondary Research.

  • Paterson, C. (2003). A life not worth living? Studies in Christian Ethics, 16(2), 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Philosophy and Religion in Film: A list (no date). Retrieved April 24, 2012, from http://www.philfilms.utm.edu/2/filmlist.htm.

  • Pilant, J. (2010). Using films to teach business ethics. Retrieved January 31, 2013, from http://southwerk.wordpress.com/2010/08/17/using-film-to-teach-business-ethics/.

  • Proctor, R., & Adler, R. (1991). Teaching interpersonal communication with feature films. Communication and Education, 40(4), 393–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reynolds, S. J., & Ceranic, T. L. (2007). The effects of moral judgment and moral identity on moral behavior: An empirical examination of the moral individual. Journal of Applied Psychology, 92(6), 1610–1624.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, R. (2012). Narrative ethics. Philosophy Compass, 7(3), 174–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roca, E. (2008). Introducing practical wisdom in business school. Journal of Business Ethics, 82(3), 607–620.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rossouw, G. J. (2002). Three approaches to teaching business ethics. Teaching Business Ethics, 6, 411–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rossouw, G. J. (2003). Business is not just war. Transferring the principle of double effect from war to business. South African Journal of Philosophy, 22(3), 236–246.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shaun, N. (2004). Sentimental rules: On the natural foundations of moral judgment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spieker, M. (2005). The universal destination of goods. The ethics of property in the theory of Christian society. Journal of Markets and Morality, 8(2), 333–354.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vaccaro, A., Veloso, F., & Brusoni, S. (2009). The impact of virtual technologies on knowledge-based processes: An empirical study. Research Policy, 8(38), 1278–1287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Velasquez, M. (2011). Business ethics: Concepts and cases (7th ed.). London: Pearson.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We are most grateful to two anonymous reviewers for their very helpful suggestions. Nevertheless, we alone are responsible for any errors.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Edward J. O’Boyle.

Appendix

Appendix

Sample abstract of the feature film MISTER ROBERTS.

The critical ethical issue raised in this film may be stated as follows. For the first-line supervisor, which duty is the more important: duty to one’s self, duty to one’s subordinates, or duty to one’s superiors (including, here, one’s country)? A more instructive statement of the issue might be How is the first-line supervisor to balance the rightful demands of his subordinates and his superiors with his own personal needs?

The proper ethical balancing of the three duties of the first-line supervisor is a matter of prudential judgment. Even so, we are able draw some relevant conclusions which move us in the direction of a clearer understanding of the responsibilities of the first-line supervisor.

First, Mr. Roberts does not have an obligation in justice to seek a transfer to a combat ship and thereby expose himself to a greater risk of losing his own life. He can fulfill his duty to his country by remaining in his role as cargo officer. In other words, he is not required to completely subordinate himself to his country’s demands. Even so, he may freely choose to seek combat duty and even risk his life in that role. Here, however, it is not justice that operates so much as love (of country, of shipmates).

Second, it follows that he does not have to completely subordinate himself to his superiors or to his subordinates. His own needs, in other words, do not have to be set aside completely to accommodate his superiors or his subordinates. Thus, it is not the demands of justice that prompt him to trade his own prospects for a transfer for his subordinates’ liberty. Rather it is an authentic love for his men, freely given and freely expressed. Given the command structure of the military and the fact that the balancing of duties is being done in wartime, Mr. Roberts is not free to leave and seek relief from the demands of an overbearing, ambitious, and manipulative superior by simply resigning. Furthermore, he is not free to initiate a slowdown to protest the captain’s orders since down the line someone’s life may depend on the supplies that his ship provides.

Third, Mr. Roberts might have met his duty to his subordinates and to himself much more effectively by preparing Ensign Pulver as his replacement. Then he could have argued to the captain that he was no longer indispensable as cargo officer and that his request for transfer legitimately could not be held up. All of this could have been accomplished without Mr. Roberts failing in his duty to his superiors. To be precise, Mr. Roberts has not met his obligation in contributive justice to his subordinates to provide for their leadership after his departure. This duty should have been more apparent to him given the great respect and affection he receives from his subordinates.

LESSON: perhaps the most demanding task of the first-line supervisor is the balancing of competing demands from above, from below, and from self, especially when a clear central value (such as the value of human life) is not at risk. This is what we mean by “prudential judgment.” When this balancing of duties bears overly much on the first-line supervisor, escape through resignation is an appropriate and ethical decision.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

O’Boyle, E.J., Sandonà, L. Teaching Business Ethics Through Popular Feature Films: An Experiential Approach. J Bus Ethics 121, 329–340 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-013-1724-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-013-1724-0

Keywords

Navigation