Skip to main content
Log in

Why a convincing argument for causalism cannot entirely eschew population-level properties: discussion of Otsuka

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Causalism is the thesis that natural selection can cause evolution. A standard argument for causalism involves showing that a hypothetical intervention on some population-level property that is identified with natural selection (e.g., variation in fitness) will result in evolution. In a pair of articles, one of which recently appeared in the pages of this journal, Jun Otsuka has put forward a quite different argument for causalism. Otsuka attempts to show that natural selection can cause evolution by considering a hypothetical intervention on an individual-level property. Specifically, Otsuka identifies natural selection with the causal relationship between a trait and fitness, claims an intervention on the strength of this relationship can cause evolution, then concludes that natural selection can cause evolution. Below I describe why Otsuka’s argument for causalism is unconvincing. Central to my criticism is that Otsuka’s argument works only if one adopts an indefensible account of natural selection, according to which natural selection can occur in the absence of trait or fitness variation. I go on to explain why any attempt to demonstrate the truth of causalism via a hypothetical intervention on an individual-level property would appear to require one to adopt an account of natural selection that is inadequate for the same reason. This in turn means the plausibility of causalism does indeed depend on the plausibility of the claim that population-level properties, which supervene on the properties of the individuals in the population, can be causally efficacious.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. One could attach subscripts to β to indicate that it represents the causal influence of Z on W. Since I do not use β for any other purpose in this paper, I will leave these subscripts out.

  2. Since I, along with the majority of other participants in the debate over causalism and statisticalism, endorse roughly this account of causation, I will not provide a more in depth description or defense of it. The unfamiliar reader should consult Woodward (2003) and Pearl (2009) for particularly illuminating exegeses.

  3. Otsuka’s description of natural selection may remind some readers of descriptions of “selection for.” But the similarities only go so far; “selection for” is typically understood to occur only when there is trait and fitness variation (Sober 1984a). See also Lewens (2010) for discussion of these issues.

  4. One potential objection to Otsuka’s discussion of an intervention on β is that interventions are typically understood to be carried out on variables, not parameters. I will not consider that objection here.

  5. See McLoone (2015) for a discussion of how this issue relates to the definition of "group selection" articulated by some proponents of the "contextual approach" to multilevel selection.

  6. See Sober (1984b) for a related discussion, though his is focused on the difference between type- and token-level causal claims.

  7. Matthen and Ariew write that they “assume Sober’s fairly orthodox treatment” of natural selection, namely, “natural selection is evolution due to heritable variation in fitness” (Matthen and Ariew 2009, p. 204). In fact, this is not Sober’s account of natural selection. The part of Sober’s book that Matthen and Ariew explicitly reference says this: “If the organisms in a population differ in their ability to survive and reproduce, and if the characteristics that affect these abilities are transmitted from parents to offspring, then the population will evolve” (1984a, b pp. 21–22). This is different than saying, “natural selection is evolution due to heritable variation in fitness,” which is the interpretation Matthen and Ariew ascribe to the passage. Later in that same chapter, Sober also provides a case that he explicitly and plausibly describes as one in which there is selection but not evolution (Ibid., pp. 40–41). Sober writes later in that book, “selection doesn’t imply evolution…Selection implies evolution only when no other evolutionary force counteracts it and the trait being selected is heritable” (Ibid., p. 151, emphasis in original).

References

  • Brandon RN (1990) Adaptation and environment. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin C (1859) The origin of species. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, p 1964

    Google Scholar 

  • Endler JA (1986) Natural selection in the wild. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher RA (1930) The genetical theory of natural selection. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Forber P, Reisman K (2007) Can there be stochastic evolutionary causes? Philos Sci 74:616–627

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gayon J (1998) Darwinism’s struggle for survival: heredity and the hypothesis of natural selection. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Glymour B (2006) Wayward modeling: population genetics and natural selection. Philos Sci 73:369–389

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2007) Conditions for evolution by natural selection. J Philos 104:489–516

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2009) Darwinian populations and natural selection. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lennox JG, Wilson BE (1994) Natural selection and the struggle for existence. Stud Hist Philos Sci 25:65–80

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewens T (2010) The natures of selection. Br J Philos Sci 61:313–333

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC (1970) The units of selection. Annu Rev Ecol Syst 1:1–18

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen M, Ariew A (2002) Two ways of thinking about fitness and natural selection. J Philos 99:55–83

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen M, Ariew A (2009) Selection and causation. Philos Sci 76:201–224

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLoone B (2015) Some criticism of the contextual approach, and a few proposals. Biol Theory 10(2):116–124

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mills SK, Beatty JH (1979) The propensity interpretation of fitness. Philos Sci 46:263–286

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millstein RL (2006) Natural selection as a population-level causal process. Br J Philos Sci 4(1):627–653

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Otsuka J (2016a) Causal foundations of evolutionary genetics. Br J Philos Sci 67:247–269

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Otsuka J (2016b) A critical review of the statisticalist debate. Biol Philos 31:459–482

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearl J (2009) Causality: models, reasoning, and inference. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reisman K, Forber P (2005) Manipulation and the causes of evolution. Philos Sci 72:1113–1123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro L, Sober E (2007) Epiphenomenalism: the do’s and don’ts. In: Wolters G, Machamer P (eds) Thinking about causes: from Greek philosophy to modern physics. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1984a) The nature of selection: evolutionary theory in philosophical focus. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1984b) Two concepts of cause. Philos Sci 2:405–424

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (2011) A priori causal models of natural selection. Australas J Philos 89:571–589

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (2013) Trait fitness is not a propensity, but fitness variation is. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 44:336–341

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spirtes P, Glymour C, Scheines R (2000) Causation, prediction, and search. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh DM (2000) Chasing shadows: natural selection and adaptation. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 31:135–153

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh DM (2007) The pomp of superfluous causes: the interpretation of evolutionary theory. Philos Sci 74:281–303

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh DM, Lewens T, Ariew A (2002) The trials of life: natural selection and random drift. Philos Sci 69:452–473

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh DM, Ariew A, Matthen M (2017) Four pillars of statisticalism. Philos Theory Pract Biol 9:1–18

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (2003) Making things happen: a theory of causal explanation. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Robert Brandon, Bruce Glymour, Jun Otsuka, Elliott Sober, and two anonymous referees for providing helpful comments on earlier versions of this manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Brian McLoone.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

McLoone, B. Why a convincing argument for causalism cannot entirely eschew population-level properties: discussion of Otsuka. Biol Philos 33, 11 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-018-9620-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-018-9620-8

Keywords

Navigation