Skip to main content
Log in

Dehorning the Darwinian dilemma for normative realism

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Normative realists tend to consider evolutionary debunking arguments as posing epistemological challenges to their view. By understanding Sharon Street’s ‘Darwinian dilemma’ argument in this way, they have overlooked and left unanswered her unique scientific challenge to normative realism. This paper counters Street’s scientific challenge and shows that normative realism is compatible with an evolutionary view of human evaluative judgment. After presenting several problems that her adaptive link account of evaluative judgments faces, I outline and defend an evolutionary byproduct perspective on evaluative judgment. I then argue that a consideration of levels of analysis in biological–behavioral explanation suggests that the realist who adopts the byproduct perspective I outline is not at a prima facie disadvantage to the normative anti-realist on grounds of parsimony. This perspective, I suggest, can enable normative realists to answer evolutionary challenges to their view.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. By stance-independent I mean independent of any hypothetical or actual psychological attitude. I adopt Street’s use of the term, which follows Shafer-Landau (2003).

  2. Joyce argues that moral judgments express both a belief about a normative standard and a conative acceptance of that standard, the latter of which “denotes a motivation-implicating state” (2006, 109). Why is a mental state with propositional content needed in addition to a strong conative state to generate the requisite motivation for the adaptive behavior? Joyce suggests that Robin Dunbar’s grooming and gossip hypothesis provides a clue: language evolved to facilitate social cohesion within increasingly large groups through the exchange of information about individual reputations. Joyce suggests that language would have been utilized not only to describe, say, failures of individuals to reciprocate helpful action, but to criticize those individuals. So language may have evolved to evaluate and keep score of others’ actions within large groups engaging in complex forms of exchange, much the same way as grooming facilitates social cohesion within small groups of nonhuman primates. While it is not possible to provide an assessment of Joyce’s account here, it is worth noting that Dunbar’s hypothesis has been challenged on both theoretical and empirical grounds. For example, Bickerton (2009) and Barnard (2012) have argued that the grooming and gossip hypothesis does not explain the complexity of language and the conceptual sophistication required for it, and each contends that language evolved for purposes quite apart from social evaluation and cohesion.

  3. Joyce (2006), handling a similar objection from Lahti (2003), suggests it makes little sense to ask why selection didn’t simply strengthen existing motivational tendencies to get us to act in certain ways. He asserts that natural selection did design us to act this way, and evaluative judgment was a way to do it. Joyce frames the question as being about natural selection choosing between two options, namely a desire for a given behavior or a mechanism that facilitates the desire. But the relevant question is about the reliability of evolved evaluative tendencies for cooperative behavior already in place among our ancestors prior to the evolution of evaluative judgment.

  4. ALA appears also to stand in tension with dual process models of social cognition (DPMs), which are prevalent in the social and cognitive psychology literature. DPMs generally distinguish between two levels of cognitive processes that jointly underwrite human behavioral, social, and moral judgments. On one level are cognitive processes marked by speed, unregulated automaticity, and efficiency with respect to the formation of mental representations of, and behavioral motivation in response to, environmental stimuli. Commonly grouped among these processes, which are often dubbed ‘System 1’ (S1) processes, are emotional regulation, attention biases, behavior contagion, and threat and reward sensitivity. According to DPMs, S1 processes are contrasted with ‘System 2’ (S2) processes, which are slow, reflective, and selective with respect to execution. DPM theorists often take S1 processes to be evolutionary old and phylogenetically widespread, and S2 processes to be evolutionarily recent. While Street’s characterization of evaluative tendencies would appear to place them at the S1 level, her view of basic evaluative judgments as reflective endorsements of such tendencies would seem to place them at the S2 level. If that is correct, then basic evaluative judgments would hardly resemble hard-wired processes, but instead would look more like regulated, selective S2 interventions.

  5. It is worth noting that the claim that a given trait is not an adaptation does not entail the view that the trait was never adaptive. While an effect was not the target of selective pressures, it could have been co-opted after its emergence to play some adaptive role at a later evolutionary stage of a population (Gould and Vrba 1982; Gould 1991).

  6. Street briefly considers the byproduct option before summarily dismissing it as implausible: “It is completely implausible, for instance, to suggest that the human eye in its present developed form emerged as the purely incidental byproduct of selection for some other, unrelated capacity. I suggest that it is no more implausible to claim that the sophisticated ability to grasp independent evaluative truths emerged as such a byproduct” (2006, 143). Street’s dismissal not only ignores byproduct accounts of many sophisticated cognitive traits (e.g., Atran 2010; De Smedt and De Cruz 2010; Piattelli-Palmarini 1989), but also plainly begs the question against a byproduct account of evaluative judgment by comparing the evolutionary processes that brought about the capacity for evaluative judgment to those that brought about the human eye.

  7. I take the label and category of ‘relaxed realist’ from Cuneo and Shafer-Landau (2014) and McGrath (2014).

  8. Joyce (2006) and James (2011) appeal to kin selection to explain initial tendencies in early humans for directing helping behaviors toward non-kin, and they suggest that such tendencies underlie further evolved dispositions for cooperation. James suggests that there would not have been selective pressures for fine-grained kin-detection devices, since early humans would have lived in tightly knit communities consisting largely of individuals related to various degrees, who consequently would have been disposed to cooperate to some degree. Following Joyce, James utilizes this kin selection hypothesis to work up to a more complex explanation of a psychological tendency in early humans to cooperate with those living in close proximity, with ‘false positives’ sometimes prompting the cooperation with non-kin. For their accounts to work, a surprising number of major trait transitions would have had to occur within an improbably short evolutionary timeframe after the spit from humans’ common ancestor with chimpanzees and bonobos: (1) loss of olfactory sensitivity to close kin; (2) loss of capacity for finer-grained kin detection based on phenotypic clues, a trait that extant primates still possess and, presumably, so too did the last common ancestor before the Pan-Homo split (Parr and De Waal 1999; Silk 2005; Widdig 2007; Chapais 2010); (3) a significant change in group composition from primate social groups composed of kin and non-kin to social groups consisting mostly of kin; (4) despite the evolution of stable breeding bonds and increased biparental care of offspring in early hominid communities, selection would have elaborated the psychological tendencies put in place by kin selection to gradually intensify novel cooperative dispositions toward non-kin. Additionally, according to James, all these rapid transitions likely would have occurred in early humans before the evolution of language. Now, this is not to say that the stories James and Joyce tell are false, but it is to say that their stories appear much less plausible when we take into account probable phylogenetic constraints on kin bias among early hominids and the very short evolutionary time scale on which the trait transitions required for James’s and Joyce’s stories to work—many of which are phylogenetically novel—would have had to occur.

  9. Joyce aims to provide reasons in favor of taking moral judgment to be an adaptation as opposed to an evolutionary byproduct (2006, 133–139), but his discussion slips from the question of whether moral judgment is an evolutionary adaptation to whether moral judgment is innate. That a trait is innate does not entail that it is an adaptation.

References

  • Atran S (2010) The evolution of religion: how cognitive byproducts, adaptive learning heuristics, ritual displays, and group competition generate deep commitments to prosocial religions. Biol Theory 5(1):18–30

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ayala FJ (2009) The difference of being human: morality. Proc Natl Acad Sci 107:9015–9022

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baker A (2007) Occam’s razor in science: a case study from biogeography. Biol Philos 22:193–215

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barnard A (2012) Genesis of symbolic thought. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bartels DM (2008) Principled moral sentiment and the flexibility of moral judgment and decision making. Cognition 108:381–417

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bateson P, Gluckman P (2011) Plasticity, robustness, development and evolution. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bickerton D (2009) Adam’s tongue: how humans made language, how language made humans. Hill and Wang, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Burian RM (1983) Adaptation. In: Greene M (ed) Dimensions of Darwinism. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Chapais B (2010) The deep structure of human society: primate origins and evolution. In: Kappeler PM, Silk JB (eds) Mind the gap: tracing the origins of human universals. Springer, Heidelberg, pp 19–51

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cuneo T, Shafer-Landau R (2014) The moral fixed points: new directions for moral nonnaturalism. Philos Stud 171:399–443

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Lazari-Radek K, Singer P (2014) The point of view of the universe: Sidgwick and contemporary ethics. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • De Smedt J, De Cruz H (2010) Toward an integrative approach of cognitive neuroscientific and evolutionary psychological studies of art. Evol Psychol 8:695–719

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Enoch D (2011) Taking morality seriously: a defense of robust realism. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • FitzPatrick WJ (2008) Robust ethical realism, non-naturalism, and normativity. In: Shafer-Landau R (ed) Oxford studies in metaethics, vol 3. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 159–206

    Google Scholar 

  • FitzPatrick WJ (2015) Debunking evolutionary debunking of ethical realism. Philos Stud 172:883–904

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fraser BJ (2014) Evolutionary debunking arguments and the reliability of moral cognition. Philos Stud 168:457–473

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (1996) Complexity and the function of mind in nature. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (1991) Exaptation: a crucial tool for evolutionary psychology. J Soc Issues 47:43–65

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ, Vrba ES (1982) Exaptation—a missing term in the science of form. Paleobiology 8:4–15

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamlin JK (2012) A developmental perspective on the moral dyad. Psychol Inq 23:166–171

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heiphetz L, Young L (2014) A social cognitive developmental perspective on moral judgment. Behaviour 151:315–335

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James SM (2011) An introduction to evolutionary ethics. Wiley, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce R (2006) The evolution of morality. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kellert SH, Longino HE, Waters CK (2006) Introduction: the pluralist stance. In: Kellert SH, Longino HE, Waters CK (eds) Scienftic pluralism. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp vii–xxix

    Google Scholar 

  • Kochanska G (2002) Committed compliance, moral self, and internalization: a mediational model. Dev Psychol 38(3):339–351

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kochanska G, Murray KT (2000) Mother–child mutually responsive orientation and conscience development: from toddler to early school age. Child Dev 71:1424–1440

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kochanska G, Forman DR, Aksan N, Dunbar SB (2005) Pathways to conscience: early mother–child mutually responsive orientation and children’s moral emotion, conduct, and cognition. J Child Psychol Psychiatry 46(1):19–34

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kummer H, Daston L, Gigerenzer G, Silk J (1997) The social intelligence hypothesis. In: Weingart P, Richerson P, Mitchell SD, Maasen S (eds) Human by nature: between biology and the social sciences. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Hillsdale, pp 157–179

    Google Scholar 

  • Lahti DC (2003) Parting with illusions in evolutionary ethics. Biol Philos 18:639–651

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laible D (2007) Attachment with parents and peers in late adolescence: links with emotional competence and social paper. Personal Individ Differ 43(5):1185–1197

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laible D, Thompson RA (2000) Mother–child discourse, attachment security, shared positive affect, and early conscience development. Child Dev 71(5):1424–1440

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laland KN, Brown G (2011) Sense and nonsense: evolutionary perspectives on human behavior, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd EA (2005) The case of the female orgasm: bias in the science of evolution. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • MacDougall-Shackleton SA (2011) The levels of analysis revisited. Philos Trans R Soc B 366:2076–2085

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGrath S (2014) Relax? Don’t do it! Why moral realism won’t come cheap. In: Shafer-Landau R (ed) Oxford studies in metaethics, vol 9. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 87–108

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller JG (1994) Cultural diversity in the morality of caring: individually oriented versus duty-based interpersonal moral codes. Cross Cult Res 28(1):3–39

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller JG, Bersoff DM (1992) Culture and moral judgment: how are conflicts between justice and interpersonal responsibilities resolved? J Pers Soc Psychol 62(4):541–554

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols S (2002) On the genealogy of norms: a case for the role of emotions in cultural evolution. Philos Sci 69:234–255

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parr L, De Waal FBM (1999) Visual kin recognition in chimpanzees. Nature 399:647–648

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piattelli-Palmarini M (1989) Evolution, selection and cognition: from ‘learning’ to parameter setting in biology and in the study of language. Cognition 31:1–44

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinker S, Bloom P (1992) Natural language and natural selection. In: Barkow JH, Cosmides L, Tooby J (eds) The adapted mind: evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz JJ (2009) Against moral nativism. In: Murphy D, Bishop M (eds) Stich and his critics. Wiley, Oxford, pp 167–189

    Google Scholar 

  • Roeser S (2011) Moral emotions and intuitions. Palgrave Macmillan, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg A (1990) The biological justification of ethics: a best-case scenario. Soc Philos Policy 8:86–101

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruse M (1986) Evolutionary ethics: a phoenix arisen. Zygon 21:95–112

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shafer-Landau R (2003) Moral realism: a defense. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sherman PW (1988) Levels of analysis. Anim Behav 36:616–618

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Silk JB (2003) Cooperation without counting: the puzzle of friendship. In: Hammerstein P (ed) Genetic and cultural evolution of cooperation. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 37–54

    Google Scholar 

  • Silk JB (2005) The evolution of cooperation in primate groups. In: Gintis H, Bowles S, Boyd R, Fehr E (eds) Moral sentiments and material interests: the foundations of cooperation in economic life. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Silk JB, Boyd R (2010) From grooming to giving blood: the origins of human altruism. In: Kappeler PM, Silk JB (eds) Mind the gap: tracing the origins of human universals. Springer, Heidelberg, pp 223–244

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1990) Let’s razor Ockham’s razor. In: Knowles D (ed) Explanation and its limits, vol 27. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 73–93

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K (2003) Thought in a hostile world: the evolution of human cognition. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K (2012) The evolved apprentice: how evolution made humans unique. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stratton-Lake P (2002) Introduction. In: Stratton-Lake P (ed) Ethical intuitionism: re-evaluations. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Street S (2006) A Darwinian dilemma for realist theories of value. Philos Stud 127:109–166

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson RA, Laible DJ, Ontai LL (2003) Early understandings of emotion, morality, and self: developing a working model. Adv Child Dev Behav 31:137–171

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tinbergen N (1963) On the aims and methods of ethology. Z Tierpsychol 20:410–433

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vaish A, Carpenter M, Tomasello M (2009) Sympathy through affective perspective taking and its relation to prosocial behavior in toddlers. Dev Psychol 45:534–543

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vaish A, Carpenter M, Tomasello M (2010) Young children selectively avoid helping people with harmful intentions. Child Dev 81:1661–1669

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Widdig A (2007) Paternal kin discrimination: the evidence and likely mechanisms. Biol Rev 82:319–334

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank audiences at MIT, DePauw University, the University of Western Ontario, the University of Colorado Boulder, the University of Notre Dame, and the 2012 APA Eastern Division Meeting for helpful discussions of early versions of this paper. I am especially grateful to Robert Audi, Matthew Braddock, Justin Horn, Cailin O’Connor, Grant Ramsey, Benjamin Rossi, Christopher Shirreff, Kim Sterelny, Aleksy Tarasenko-Struc, Brandon Williams, and anonymous reviewers for valuable comments on drafts of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael J. Deem.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Deem, M.J. Dehorning the Darwinian dilemma for normative realism. Biol Philos 31, 727–746 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-016-9529-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-016-9529-z

Keywords

Navigation