Skip to main content
Log in

Why how and why aren’t enough: more problems with Mayr’s proximate-ultimate distinction

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Like Laland et al., I think Mayr’s distinction is problematic, but I identify a further problem with it. I argue that Mayr’s distinction is a false dichotomy, and obscures an important question about evolutionary change. I show how this question, once revealed, sheds light on some debates in evo-devo that Laland et al.’s analysis cannot, and suggest that it provides a different view about how future integration between biological disciplines might proceed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It did more than this, but these are the issues that concern us here.

  2. Mayr originally framed his distinction in terms of causation, and Laland et al. have followed his lead. Like others (Amundson (2005), for example), I prefer to talk of different kinds of explanation.

  3. Ronald Amundson has argued for some time that the conflict between developmental and evolutionary biologists often comes down to their interest in different kinds of explanation (Amundson 2001), and he points to Mayr distinction as a source of confusion on this topic (See discussion in Amundson 2005). My arguments in this paper are an attempt to say precisely what those differences are.

  4. As far as I know, Ariew (2003) was the first to suggest that Mayr’s distinction may have something to do with individuals and populations, though he presents the issue in rather different light than I do here.

  5. Due to space limitations, I’m giving a very informal version of mechanistic explanation, grounded in an interventionist account of causation (See, for example, Craver 2009; Glennan 2005; Machamer et al. 2000; Woodward 2002).

  6. For an example, go here: http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Sickle-cell_disease.

  7. In philosophy-speak, the difference between a sick and a healthy person is the explanandum, and the shape of the red blood cells is the explanans. I’m using the terms explanatory target and difference-maker here.

  8. Obviously there is a fourth question too: How do populations work at a time? One possible way to intepret this question is as understanding proximate aspects of social interaction. I’ll say nothing further about this option here.

  9. Tetrapods are four-limbed vertebrates. Their ancestors were fish. So the question concerns how fins were transformed into limbs. See, for example, Hall (2007) or Shubin (2008).

  10. For futher discussion of this example, see Calcott (2009).

  11. For further discussion of feather development, see Calcott (2009).

  12. Ingo Brigandt outlines a much more piecemeal way that integration might occur across biological disciplines (Brigandt 2010). He suggests that, rather than integrating entire fields, integration may occur in smaller epistomological units—such as a particular research problem.

References

  • Amundson R (2001) Adaptation and development. In: Orzack SH, Sober E (eds) Adaptationism and optimality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Amundson R (2005) The changing role of the embryo in evolutionary thought roots of evo-devo. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ariew A (2003) Ernst Mayr’s “ultimate/proximate” distinction reconsidered and reconstructed. Biol Philos 18:553–565

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt I (2010) Beyond reduction and pluralism: toward an epistemology of explanatory integration in biology. Erkenntnis 73:295–311

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Calcott B (2009) Lineage explanations: explaining how biological mechanisms change. Br J Philos Sci 60:51–78

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coyne JA (2006) Comment on “gene regulatory networks and the evolution of animal body plans”. Science 313:761–762

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver CF (2009) Explaining the brain, 1st edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin C (1872) The origin of species. Cornell University Library, Ithaca

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson EH, Erwin DH (2006) Gene regulatory networks and the evolution of animal body plans. Science 311:796–800

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewsbury D (1999) The proximate and the ultimate: past, present, and future. Behav Process 46:189–199

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Erwin DH, Davidson EH (2006) Response to comment on “gene regulatory networks and the evolution of animal body plans”. Science 313:796–800

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Francis R (1990) Causes, proximate and ultimate. Biol Philos 5:401–415

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan S (2005) Studies in history and philosophy of science part C: studies in history and philosophy of biological and biomedical sciences. Model Mech 36(2):443–464

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall BK (ed) (2007) Fins into limbs: evolution, development, and transformation. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoekstra HE, Coyne JA (2007) The locus of evolution: evo devo and the genetics of adaptation. Evolution 61:995–1016

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirschner MW, Gerhart JC (2006) The plausibility of life: resolving Darwin’s Dilemma. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Laland KN, Sterelny K, Odling-Smee J, Hoppitt W, Uller T (2011) Cause and effect in biology revisited: is Mayr’s proximate-ultimate dichotomy still useful? Science 334:1512–1516

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laland KN, Odling-Smee J, Hoppitt W, Uller T (2012) More on how and why: cause and effect in biology revisited. Biol Philos. doi:10.1007/s10539-012-9335-1

  • Machamer P, Darden L, Craver CF (2000) Thinking about mechanisms. Philos Sci 67(1):1–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1961) Cause and effect in biology. Science 134:1501–1506

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nilsson DE, Pelger S (1994) A pessimistic estimate of the time required for an eye to evolve. Proceed R Soc B Biol Sci 256:53–58

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peel A, Akam M (2003) Evolution of segmentation: rolling back the clock. Curr Biol 13:708

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prum RO (1999) Development and evolutionary origin of feathers. J Exp Zool Part B Mol Dev Evol 285:291–306

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prum RO (2005) Evolution of the morphological innovations of feathers. J Exp Zool Part B Mol Dev Evol 304:570–579

    Google Scholar 

  • Shubin N (2008) Your inner fish. A journey into the 3.5-billion-year history of the human body. Pantheon Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern DL, Orgogozo V (2008) The loci of evolution: how predictable is genetic evolution? Evolution 62:2155–2177

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Truman JW, Riddiford LM (1999) The origins of insect metamorphosis. Nature 401:447–452

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West SA, Griffin AS, Gardner A (2007) Evolutionary explanations for cooperation. Curr Biol 17:661

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (2002) What is a mechanism? A counterfactual account. Philos Sci 69(3):S366–S377

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Brett Calcott.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Calcott, B. Why how and why aren’t enough: more problems with Mayr’s proximate-ultimate distinction. Biol Philos 28, 767–780 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-013-9367-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-013-9367-1

Keywords

Navigation