Skip to main content
Log in

Productivity, relevance and natural selection

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recent papers by a number of philosophers have been concerned with the question of whether natural selection is a causal process, and if it is, whether the causes of selection are properties of individuals or properties of populations. I shall argue that much confusion in this debate arises because of a failure to distinguish between causal productivity and causal relevance. Causal productivity is a relation that holds between events connected via continuous causal processes, while causal relevance is a relationship that can hold between a variety of different kinds of facts and the events that counterfactually depend upon them. I shall argue that the productive character of natural selection derives from the aggregation of individual processes in which organisms live, reproduce and die. At the same time, a causal explanation of the distribution of traits will necessarily appeal both to causally relevant properties of individuals and to causally relevant properties that exist only at the level of the population.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. While these three interpretations are widely recognized, there are different ways in which philosophers have named and classified the varying interpretations of the theory of natural selection (and of evolutionary theory more generally). What I’m calling the individualistic interpretation has chiefly been argued for by Bouchard and Rosenberg. (Bouchard and Rosenberg 2004; Rosenberg and Bouchard 2005). The statistical interpretation has been championed in a number of articles by Ariew, Lewins, Matthen, and Walsh (Matthen and Ariew 2002; Walsh 2000; Walsh et al. 2002; Walsh 2007). The locus classicus of the dynamical interpretation is Sober 1984, and that interpretation has been recently defended by Millstein, Shapiro and Sober (Millstein 2006; Shapiro and Sober 2007) The term ‘dynamical interpretation’, which I borrow from (Walsh 2007), alludes to Sober’s analogy between evolutionary forces and the forces of classical mechanics.

  2. Admittedly the individualists and statisticalists spend a lot of time disagreeing about what fitness is and what it means to say that natural selection is a statistical process. These differences are not, however, germane to the main issue of this paper.

  3. I do not think it is necessary for me here to commit to any particular theories about the nature either of facts or events. The main reason for distinguishing between them is that there are a lot more facts than there are events—as the examples I discuss will show. For more on the nature of events, facts and other possible candidates for causal relata see Schaffer 2003.

  4. See Hitchcock (2007) and Godfrey-Smith (forthcoming) for overviews of the varieties of causal pluralism. Campagner and Galavotti (2007) offer an account of causal pluralism focusing specifically on mechanistic and manipulability approaches to causation.

  5. See Glennan (forthcoming) for a more detailed explanation of the relationship between productivity, relevance and mechanisms.

  6. In Glennan 1996, I emphasized the fact that mechanisms were composed as parts, which I required to be objects. The major point of the object requirement was related to a point Woodward (2002) has emphasized about mechanisms, namely that parts be in principle independently manipulable. Machamer et al. have used the term ‘entity’ while Bechtel (Bechtel and Abrahamsen 2005) has preferred the term ‘component’ though these terminological differences are not indicative of substantive disagreements. I shall use the words ‘object’ and ‘entity’ interchangeably.

  7. While paradigm cases are fairly clear, it is difficult or perhaps impossible to give strict criteria for deciding when a population is sufficiently stable in its structure and organization that it can be considered an individual undergoing selection. It seems to me that Sober and Wilson’s idea of common fate (Sober 1984; Sober and Wilson 1998) is important. For further discussion of this problem in the context of the units of selection problem see Glennan 2002.

  8. The concern that perhaps all non-fundamental entities and properties lack causal powers has been the subject of considerable discussion, especially among philosophers of mind. Jaegwon Kim (1984, 1998) in particular has flirted with thoroughgoing epiphenomenalism. I cannot, in the space of this paper, provide a general answer to these worries, though I have tried to show how a mechanistic account of causation can do so in Glennan (forthcoming). Shapiro and Sober’s (2007) analysis of epiphenomenalism offers a complementary response to Kim.

  9. Forber and Reisman (2007) have made points similar to those of Millstein. They have argued on the basis of manipulability approaches to causation that population level parameters (such as population size) can cause evolutionary change. Manipulability criteria do indeed demonstrate the causal relevance of these parameters, but this fact is not inconsistent with the claim that the producers of evolutionary change in such cases are individual organisms.

References

  • Bechtel W, Abrahamsen A (2005) Explanation: a mechanist alternative. Stud His Philos Bio Biomed Sci 36(2):421–441

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bouchard F, Rosenberg A (2004) Fitness, probability and the principles of natural selection. Br J Philos Sci 55(4):693–712. doi:10.1093/bjps/55.4.693

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campagner R, Galavotti MC (2007) Plurality in causality. In: Wolters G, Machamer P (eds) Thinking about causes: from Greek philosophy to modern physics. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins J, Hall N, Paul LA (2004) Causation and counterfactuals. Bradford Book/MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin C (1859[1964]) On the origin of species. Facsimile of the 1st edition. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowe P (2000) Physical causation. Cambridge studies in probability, induction, and decision theory. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Forber P, Reisman K (2007) Can there be stochastic evolutionary causes? Philos Sci 74(5):616–627. doi:10.1086/525608

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Futuyma DJ (1986) Evolutionary biology, 2nd edn. Sinauer, Sunderland, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Glennan SS (1996) Mechanisms and the nature of causation. Erkenntnis 44(1):49–71. doi:10.1007/BF00172853

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan SS (2002) Contextual unanimity and the units of selection problem. Philos Sci 69(1):118–137. doi:10.1086/338944

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan SS (forthcoming) Mechanisms, causes and the layered model of the world. Philos Phenomenol Res

  • Godfrey-Smith P (forthcoming) Causal pluralism. In: Beebee H, Hitchcock C, Menzies P (eds) Oxford handbook of causation. Oxford University Press, New York

  • Hall N (2004) Two concepts of causation. In: Collins J, Hall N, Paul LA (eds) Causation and counterfactuals. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock CR (1995) Discussion: Salmon on explanatory relevance. Philos Sci 62(2):304–320. doi:10.1086/289858

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock CR (2007) How to be a causal pluralist. In: Wolters G, Machamer P (eds) Thinking about causes: from Greek philosophy to modern physics. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson F, Pettit P (1990) Program explanation: a general perspective. Analysis 50(2):107–117. doi:10.2307/3328853

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim J (1984) Epiphenomenal and supervenient causation. Midwest Stud Philos 9:257–270. doi:10.1111/j.1475-4975.1984.tb00063.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim J (1998) Mind in a physical world: an essay on the mind–body problem and mental causation. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P, Sterelny K (1988) The return of the gene. J Philos 85:339–361. doi:10.2307/2026953

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D (1973) Causation. J Philos 70:556–567. doi:10.2307/2025310

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer P, Darden L, Craver CF (2000) Thinking about mechanisms. Philos Sci 67(1):1–25. doi:10.1086/392759

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen M, Ariew A (2002) Two ways of thinking about fitness and natural selection. J Philos 99(2):55–83. doi:10.2307/3655552

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millstein RL (2006) Natural selection as a population-level causal process. Br J Philos Sci 57:627–653. doi:10.1093/bjps/axl025

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg A, Bouchard F (2005) Matthen and Ariew’s obituary for fitness: reports of its death have been greatly exaggerated. Biol Philos 20(2–3):343–353. doi:10.1007/s10539-005-2560-0

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon WC (1984) Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer J (2003) The metaphysics of causation. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Spring 2003 edn. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2003/entries/causation-metaphysics/

  • Shapiro LA, Sober E (2007) Epiphenomenalism—the dos and the don’ts. In: Wolters G, Machamer P (eds) Thinking about causes: from Greek philosophy to modern physics. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1984) The nature of selection: evolutionary theory in philosophical focus. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E, Wilson DS (1998) Unto others: the evolution and psychology of unselfish behavior. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh DM (2000) Chasing shadows: natural selection and adaptation. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 31(1):135–153. doi:10.1016/S1369-8486(99)00041-2

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh DM (2007) The pomp of superfluous causes: the interpretation of evolutionary theory. Philos Sci 74(3):281–303. doi:10.1086/520777

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh DM, Lewens T, Ariew A (2002) The trials of life: natural selection and random drift. Philos Sci 69(3):452–473. doi:10.1086/342454

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (2002) What is a mechanism? a counterfactual account. Philos Sci 69(3 Supplement):S366–S377. doi:10.1086/341859

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (2003) Making things happen: a theory of causal explanation. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

An earlier version of this paper was presented at the 2007 meeting of the International Society for the History Philosophy and Social Studies of Biology in Exeter, the United Kingdom. I am grateful to participants in the conference for their feedback. I also had useful conversations about this paper with Lisa Lloyd and members of the Biological Studies Reading Group at Indiana University.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stuart Glennan.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Glennan, S. Productivity, relevance and natural selection. Biol Philos 24, 325–339 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-008-9137-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-008-9137-7

Keywords

Navigation