Skip to main content
Log in

Information, complexity and generative replication

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The established definition of replication in terms of the conditions of causality, similarity and information transfer is very broad. We draw inspiration from the literature on self-reproducing automata to strengthen the notion of information transfer in replication processes. To the triple conditions of causality, similarity and information transfer, we add a fourth condition that defines a “generative replicator” as a conditional generative mechanism, which can turn input signals from an environment into developmental instructions. Generative replication must have the potential to enhance complexity, which in turn requires that developmental instructions are part of the information that is transmitted in replication. Demonstrating the usefulness of the generative replicator concept in the social domain, we identify social generative replicators that satisfy all of the four proposed conditions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The authors are very grateful to Marion Blute, David Hull, Pavel Luksha, Peter Richerson, Kim Sterelny, Viktor Vanberg, anonymous referees and several others for comments and discussions.

  2. See Dawkins (1983), Hull (1988), Dennett (1995), Hodgson (2004, 2005) and Hodgson and Knudsen (2006a).

  3. Wimsatt (1999) rejects the replicator-interactor distinction but retains the genotype-phenotype concepts. This is inconsistent if we accept the former distinction as a generalization of the latter (Brandon 1996).

  4. Aunger (2002) refines Sperber’s (2000) definition by adding a fourth condition of “duplication”, meaning that replication of one entity gives rise to two or more. We are unconvinced that Aunger’s fourth condition of “duplication” is necessary or useful. The critical issue in understanding the process of replication is the nature and function of the structure that is passed on, including any information that it might hold.

  5. Note Hull’s (1988, p. 408) definition of an interactor as “an entity that directly interacts as a cohesive whole with its environment in such a way that this interaction causes replication to be differential.” See Hodgson and Knudsen (2004b) for a refinement of this definition.

  6. Even so-called benign computer viruses can be mildly destructive for the computer systems they infect, by taking up computer memory, causing erratic performance or triggering system crashes.

  7. We use a binary string as a useful simplification for expositional reasons.

  8. Prior research on self-replicating automata (Molofsky 1994; Wolfram 1984, 2002) has typically excluded such errors.

  9. Note that, if it did exist, “Lamarckian” inheritance could have similarly negative cumulative effect. Lamarckism upholds that the acquired characteristics of the interactor may affect the replicator, leading to the inheritance of these acquired characteristics. In biology, Lamarckian inheritance is widely ruled out because of the Weismann barrier. Although social evolution is widely described as Lamarckian, this idea is contested (Hodgson and Knudsen 2006b).

  10. We used sequences of length 100, but additional simulations show that our results are robust for much longer sequences.

  11. Similarity in neural connection design, even with similar genes and environment, is very unlikely (Edelman 1989). Underlying neuronal configurations supporting similar habits are likely to differ between individuals.

References

  • Adami C (2002) What is complexity? BioEssays, 24(12):1085–1094

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adami C, Ofria C, Collier TC (2000) Evolution of biological complexity. Proc Natl Acad Sci 97(9):4463–4468

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aunger R (2002) The electric meme: a new theory of how we think. Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Bagehot W (1872) Physics and politics, or, thoughts on the application of the principles of ‘natural selection’ and ‘inheritance’ to political society. Henry King, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Baguñà J, Garcia-Fernàndez J (2003) Evo–devo: the long and winding road. Int J Dev Biol 47:705–713

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackmore S (1999) The meme machine. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd R, Richerson PJ (1985) Culture and the evolutionary process. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon RN (1996) Concepts and methods in evolutionary biology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell DT (1965) Variation, selection and retention in sociocultural evolution. In: Barringer HR, Blanksten GI, Mack RW (eds) Social change in developing areas: a reinterpretation of evolutionary theory. Schenkman, Cambridge, MA, pp 19–49. Reprinted in General Systems 14, 1969, pp 69–85

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin CR (1859) On the origin of species by means of natural selection, or the preservation of favoured races in the struggle for life, 1st edn. Murray, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin CR (1871) The Descent of Man, and Selection in Relation to Sex, 1st edn., 2 vols. Murray, London; Hill, New York

  • Dawkins R (1976) The selfish gene. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (1982) The extended phenotype: the gene as the unit of selection. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (1983) Universal Darwinism. In: Bendall DS (ed) Evolution from molecules to man. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 403–425

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (2004) Extended phenotype – but not too extended. A reply to Laland, Turner and Jablonka. Biol Philos 19(3):377–396

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC (1995) Darwin’s dangerous idea: evolution and the meanings of life. Allen Lane and Simon and Schuster, London and New York

  • Diggins JP (1994) The promise of pragmatism: modernism and the crisis of knowledge and authority. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Durham WH (1991) Coevolution: genes, culture, and human diversity. Stanford University Press, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • Edelman GM (1989) The remembered present: a biological theory of consciousness. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Freitas RA, Merkle RC (2004) Kinematic self-replicating machines. Landes Bioscience, Georgetown, TX

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert SF, Opitz JM, Raff RA (1996) Resynthesizing evolutionary and developmental biology. Dev Biol 173(2):357–372

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2000a) The replicator in retrospect. Biol Philos 15:403–423

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2000b) Information, arbitrariness, and selection: comments on Maynard Smith. Philos Sci 67(2):202–207

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (1977) Ontogeny and phylogeny. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (1996) Life’s grandeur: the spread of excellence from Plato to Darwin. Cape, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer JR (1994) Tools for talking: human nature, Weismannism and the interpretation of genetic information. In: Cranor C (ed) Are genes us? The social consequences of the new genetics. Rutgers University Press, New Brunswick, NJ, pp 69–88

    Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer JR (1999) Materials for the study of evolutionary transition. Biol Philos 14:127–142

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE, Gray RD (1994) Developmental systems and evolutionary explanation. J Philo 91(6):277–304

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE, Gray RD (1997) Replicator II – judgment day. Biol Philos 12:471–490

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE (2001) Genetic information: a metaphor in search of a theory. Philos Sci 68(3):394–412

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henrich J (2004) Cultural group selection, coevolutionary processes and large-scale cooperation. J Econ Behav Organ 53(1):3–35

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henrich J, Boyd R (2001) Why people punish defectors: why conformist transmission can stabilize costly enforcement of norms in cooperative dilemmas. J Theor Biol 208(1):79–89

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM (2005) Generalizing Darwinism to social evolution: some early attempts. J Econ Issues 39(4):899–914

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM (2003) The mystery of the routine: the Darwinian destiny of an evolutionary theory of economic change. Revue Économique 54(2):355–384

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM (2004) The evolution of institutional economics: agency, structure and Darwinism in American institutionalism. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM, Knudsen T (2004a) The complex evolution of a simple traffic convention: the functions and implications of habit. J Econ Behav Organ 54(1):19–47

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM, Knudsen T (2004b) The firm as an interactor: firms as vehicles for habits and routines. J Evol Econ 14(3):281–307

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM, Knudsen T (2006a) Why we need a generalized Darwinism: and why a generalized Darwinism is not enough. J Econ Behav Organ 61(1):1–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM, Knudsen T (2006b) Dismantling Lamarckism: why descriptions of socio-economic evolution as Lamarckian are misleading. J Evol Econ 16(4):343–366

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull DL (1988) Science as a process: an evolutionary account of the social and conceptual development of science. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka E, Szathmáry E (1995) The evolution of information storage and heredity. Trends Ecol Evol 10:206–211

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joas H (1993) Pragmatism and social theory. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson-Laird PN (1981) Comprehension as the construction of mental models. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci 295(1077):353–374

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karmiloff K, Karmiloff-Smith A (2001) Pathways to language: from fetus to adolescent. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller AG (1915) Societal evolution: a study of the evolutionary basis of the science of society. Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller L (ed) (1999) Levels of selection in evolution: monographs in behavior and ecology. Princeton University Press, Princeton

  • Kubovy M, Epstein W (2001) Internalization: a metaphor we can live without. Behav Brain Sci 24(4):618–625

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knudsen T (2002) The significance of tacit knowledge in the evolution of human language. Selection 3(1):93–112

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kurthen M (2001) The archeology of internalism. Behav Brain Sci 24(4):682–683

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lee J, Beebe K, Nangle LA, Jang J, Longo-Guess CM, Cook SA, Davisson MT, Sundberg JP, Schimmel P, Ackerman SL (2006) Editing-defective tRNA synthetase causes protein misfolding and neurodegeneration. Nature 443:50–55. doi:10.1038/nature05096

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luksha PO (2003) Formal definition of self-reproductive systems. In: Standish RK, Bedau MA, Abbass HA (eds) Artificial life VIII: Proceedings of the Eighth International Conference on Artificial Life. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 414–417

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J, Szathmáry E (1995) The major transitions in evolution. WH Freeman Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J (2000a) The concept of information in biology. Philos Sci 67(2):177–194

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J (2000b), Reply to commentaries. Philos Sci 67(2):214–218

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1974) Behavior programs and evolutionary strategies. Am Sci 62(6):650–659

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1988) Toward a new philosophy of biology: observations of an evolutionist. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Michod RE (1999) Darwinian dynamics: evolutionary transitions in fitness and individuality. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Molofsky J (1994) Population dynamics and pattern formation in theoretical populations. Ecology 1:30–39

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay B (2002) The return of the replicator: what is philosophically significant in a general account of replication and selection. Biol Philos 17(1):109–121

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson RR, Winter SG (1982) An evolutionary theory of economic change. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • von Neumann J (1966) Theory of self-reproducing automata, edited and completed by Arthur W. Burks. University of Illinois Press, Urbana

  • Polanyi M (1967) The tacit dimension. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Prusiner SB (1998) Prions. Proc Natl Acad Sci 95:13,363–13,383

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam H (1995) Pragmatism. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Reber AS (1993) Implicit learning and tacit knowledge: an essay on the cognitive unconscious. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Ridley M (2000) Mendel’s demon: gene justice and the complexity of life. Weidenfeld & Nicolson, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Ritchie DG (1896) Social evolution. Int J Ethics 6(2):165–181

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar S (2000) Information in genetics and developmental biology: comments on Maynard Smith. Philos Sci 67(2):208–213

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saunders PT, Ho MW (1976) On the increase in complexity in evolution. J Theor Biol 63:375–384

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saunders PT, Ho MW (1981) On the increase in complexity in evolution ii: the relativity of complexity and the principle of minimum increase. J Theor Biol 90:515–530

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shannon CE, Warren W (1949) The mathematical theory of communication. University of Illinois Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (1990) A mechanism for social selection and successful altruism. Science 250:1665–1668

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sipper M (1998) Fifty years of research on self-replication: an overview. Artifi Life 4(3):237–257

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober E, Wilson DS (1998) Unto others: the evolution and psychology of unselfish behavior. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber D (2000) An objection to the memetic approach to culture. In: Aunger R (eds) Darwinizing culture: the status of memetics as a science. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 162–173

    Google Scholar 

  • Stadler BMR, Stadler PF, Wagner GP (2001) The topology of the possible: formal spaces underlying patterns of evolutionary change. J Theor Biol 213:241–274

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K, Smith KC, Dickison M (1996) The extended replicator. Biol Philos 11:377–403

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K (2000) The “genetic program” program: a commentary on Maynard Smith on information in biology. Philos Sci 67(2):195–201

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szathmáry E (2000) The evolution of replicators. Philos Trans Biol Sci 355(1403):1669–1676

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello M (1999) The cultural origins of human cognition. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Veblen TB (1899) The theory of the leisure class: an economic study in the evolution of institutions. Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt WC (1999) Genes, memes, and cultural heredity. Biol Philos 14(2):279–310

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolfram S (1984) Universality and complexity in cellular automata. Physica 10D:1–35

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolfram S (2002) A new kind of science. Wolfram Media, Inc., Champaign, IL

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Geoffrey M. Hodgson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Hodgson, G.M., Knudsen, T. Information, complexity and generative replication. Biol Philos 23, 47–65 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-007-9073-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-007-9073-y

Keywords

JEL classification

Navigation