Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

On balance

  • Published:
Artificial Intelligence and Law Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In the course of legal reasoning—whether for purposes of deciding an issue, justifying a decision, predicting how an issue will be decided, or arguing for how it should be decided—one often is required to reach (and assert) conclusions based on a balance of reasons that is not straightforwardly reducible to the application of rules. Recent AI and Law work has modeled reason-balancing, both within and across cases, with set-theoretic and rule- or value-ordering approaches. This article explores a way to model balancing in quantitative terms that may yield new questions, insights, and tools.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Indeed, under such banners as ‘proportionality analysis’ balancing has become widely diffused as a preferred and legitimate procedure for constitutional and other forms of adjudication. See e.g. Alexy (2003) and Sweet and Matthews (2008).

  2. Note that the weight being accorded a factor is a kind of co-efficient, not to be confused with the metaphorical weight of options in the imaginary balancing process. These two different senses of ‘weight’ are often conflated and a source of confusion.

  3. Examples of these models can be found in the references in Sect. 3.6 below.

  4. In addition to readily handling option sets with more than two members, the approach outlined here has the advantage over the two-pan scale model of showing all assessments on a given factor in the same row, for easier comparison.

  5. In conceptual spaces greater than two dimensions, of course, a line does not suffice to partition one area from another, and hyperplanes (of one dimension less than the ambient space) are needed. By expressing an arbitrary number of comparative ‘dimensions’ in the single mode of ‘factor,’ interestingly, the choicebox model can largely remain within an intuitive three-dimensional space for interface purposes at least.

  6. Other work by some of these authors does introduce quantitative aspects. E.g., in Chorley and Bench-Capon (2005a) factors are held to promote values to different extents, and values are then assigned weights to give an overall score. In Bench-Capon and Prakken (2010) values are also promoted to differing degrees to accommodate the language in the decisions considered that speak of “reduced expectations” of privacy. No numbers are attached, but case facts are held to put particular situations above or below a required threshold. Bench-Capon et al. (2013) introduces argument schemes that encompass varying degrees to which values are promoted, although degree is limited to two states, strong and weak. The ‘triadic’ model proposed by Alexy (2003) incorporates ‘light,’ ‘moderate,’ and ‘serious’ degrees to which principles are satisfied.

  7. Some weighting schemes require weights to sum to a fixed quantity, but it can be easier for users to express them in whatever relative numbers they choose, and let the system handle the associated mathematics behind the scenes. In the example here, for instance, it is easier to say that the two factors stand in an importance ratio of 5 to 2 (totaling 7), rather than having to figure out what that ratio would be against a fixed total of 10 (approximately 0.7142857–0.2857142).

  8. Whether numbers, shapes, or other devices are used to express ratings and weightings quantitatively, in many cases results can be indifferent within ranges of quantities, and hence sensitivity analysis can be used to detect how much any particular judgments would need to change in order for the result to be different.

  9. 131 S. Ct. 1143, at 1160.

  10. The literature on argument accrual of course reminds us that things are sometimes not so simple. Prakken (2005) for instance shows that accruals can be weaker than their accruing elements when those elements are not independent, and presents a logical formalization of argument accrual as a kind of inference. Lucero et al. (2009) turn to ‘possibilistic defeasible logic programming’ to model conflict and defeat in accrual structures.

  11. See https://carneades.github.io/carneades/.

References

  • Alexy R (2003) On balancing and subsumption. A structural comparison. Ratio Juris 16(4):433–449

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow K (1963) Social choice and individual values, 2nd edn. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashley K, Brüninghaus S (2005-2006) Computer Models for legal prediction. Jurimetrics 46:309

  • Ashley K, Brüninghaus S (2009) Automatically classifying case texts and predicting outcomes. Artif Intell Law 17:125–165

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bench-Capon T, Prakken H (2010) Using argument schemes for hypothetical reasoning in law. Artif Intell Law 18(2):153–174

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bench-Capon T, Prakken H, Wyner W, Atkinson K (2013) Argument schemes for reasoning with legal cases using values. In: Proceedings of the Fourteenth International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law, pp 13–22

  • Brams S (2008) Mathematics and democracy: designing better voting and fair-division procedures. Princeton University Press, Princeton

  • Chorley A, Bench-Capon T (2005a) AGATHA: using heuristic search to automate the construction of case law theories. Artif Intell Law 13(1):9–51

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chorley A, Bench-Capon T (2005b) An empirical investigation of reasoning with legal cases through theory construction and application. Artif Intell Law 13(3–4):323–371

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawes R (1979) The robust beauty of improper linear models in decision making. Am Psychol 34:571–582

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Emerson P (2010) Consensus voting and party funding: a web-based experiment. Eur Polit Sci 9:83–101

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grabmair M, Ashley K (2012) A survey of uncertainties and their consequences in probabilistic legal argumentation. In: Zenker F (ed) Bayesian argumentation. Springer, Netherlands

    Google Scholar 

  • Hage J (1993) Monological reason-based logic: a low level integration of rule-based reasoning and case-based reasoning. In: Proceedings of the Fourth International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law, p 30–39

  • Hoeflich MH (1986) Law and geometry: legal science from Leibniz to Langdell. Am J Legal Hist 30:95

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horty J, Bench-Capon T (2012) A factor-based definition of precedential constraint. Artif Intell Law 20:181–214

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jarke M, Jelassi M, Shakun M (1987) Mediator: towards a negotiation support system. Eur J Oper Res 31:314–334

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy D (1986) Freedom and constraint in adjudication: a critical phenomenology. J Legal Educ 36:518

    Google Scholar 

  • Lauritsen M (2010) Lawyer’s guide to working smarter with knowledge tools. American Bar Association, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Lauritsen M (2011) Intelligent tools for managing legal choices. In: Proceedings of the Thirteenth International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law, p 106–110

  • Lauritsen M (2014) ‘Boxing’ choices for better dispute resolution. Int J Online Disput Resolut 1(1):70–92

    Google Scholar 

  • Lucero MJG, Chesñevar CI, Simari GR (2009) Modelling argument accrual in possibilistic defeasible logic programming. In: Symbolic and quantitative approaches to reasoning with uncertainty. Springer, Berlin Heidelberg, p 131–143

  • McFadden P (1988) The balancing test. BCL Rev 29:585

    Google Scholar 

  • Morge M (2006) Collective decision-making process to compose divergent interests and perspectives. Artif Intell Law 13:79–92

    Google Scholar 

  • Prakken H (2005) A study of accrual of arguments, with applications to evidential reasoning. In: Proceedings of the Tenth International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law (2005)

  • Saari D (1995) Basic geometry of voting. Springer, New York

  • Sartor G (2010) Doing justice to rights and values: teleological reasoning and proportionality. Artif Intell Law 18(2):175–215

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartor G (2013) The logic of proportionality: reasoning with non-numerical magnitudes. German LJ 14:1419

    Google Scholar 

  • Sieckmann J (2003) Why non-monotonic logic is inadequate to represent balancing arguments. Artif Intell Law 11:211–219

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sweet AS, Mathews J (2008) Proportionality balancing and global constitutionalism. Columbia J Transl Law 47:72

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to several anonymous reviewers for insightful suggestions and encouragement.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marc Lauritsen.

Additional information

This work is based on an earlier work: “On Balance,” in Proceedings of the Fourteenth International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law, © ACM (2013). http://dx.doi.org/10.1145/2514601.2514611

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lauritsen, M. On balance. Artif Intell Law 23, 23–42 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10506-015-9163-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10506-015-9163-0

Keywords

Navigation