1 Emerging Infectious Disease and Uncertainty

Emerging infectious diseases present public health scientists with a uniquely difficult challenge. These diseases pose a potentially serious threat to the health of both human and animal populations, a threat that demands action from these scientists. Yet, this action must often be undertaken in conditions that are characterized by a pervasive lack of knowledge. Recent human and animal epidemics provide clear examples of the uncertainty and ignorance that attend the emergence of new diseases. In 2000, an inquiry into the UK’s BSE crisisFootnote 1 revealed something of the extent of this uncertainty and lack of knowledge. Mr Cruickshank of the Animal Health Group in the UK’s Ministry of Agriculture, Fisheries and Food remarked that “[w]e do not know where this disease came from, we do not know how it is spread and we do not know whether it can be passed to humans” (BSE Inquiry Report, Volume 1, p. 44). Even more recently, global scientific uncertainty has been strikingly evident in the case of the emergence of severe acute respiratory syndrome (SARS). Lingappa et al. (2004) stated that in March 2003, when the global health community first became aware of the emergence of SARS:

[T]he international health community faced a potential pandemic for which there were no identified causal agent, no diagnostic laboratory assays, no defined properties or risk factors for transmission, no infection-control practices of proven efficacy, and no known treatment or prevention measures (p. 167).

The BSE and SARS epidemics were eventually contained.Footnote 2 However, these outbreaks of infectious disease, and others like them, have occasioned reflection on the part of investigators about how uncertainty may best be tackled in future epidemics.Footnote 3 Nowhere is the need for such reflection more pronounced than in epidemiology, the branch of science that is responsible for detecting and monitoring the emergence of new infectious diseases. While mathematical modelling of epidemics is commonplace in epidemiology, the modes of reasoning that are integral to these models are construed along strictly deductive–inductive lines.Footnote 4 A reorientation away from deductive and inductive modes of reasoning towards presumptive frameworks is central to the view of scientific reasoning that I will discuss in this article (and may even assist scientists as they engage in reflection of how epidemiology may best respond to uncertaintyFootnote 5). Specifically, I will argue that the presumptive character of certain informal fallacies makes them ideally suited to the task of advancing scientific inquiry in contexts of uncertainty. It is to an examination of these fallacies and their role in scientific reasoning that we now turn.

2 Informal Fallacies and Scientific Inquiry

The history of the informal fallacies has been an interesting one to say the least. Since Aristotle first examined the fallacies in Sophistical Refutations, and with the exception of contributions from medieval logicians and theorists such as Sidgwick, Whately and Mill, the fallacies languished in a state of almost total neglect until the latter part of the twentieth century. In 1970, Charles Hamblin’s book Fallacies reversed the fortune of this branch of logical inquiry in a way that is still being felt to the present day. Specifically, Hamblin was concerned to challenge the so-called standard treatment of the fallacies that was found in logic textbooks.Footnote 6 His own analysis of the fallacies emphasized the use of dialectical structures for the normative evaluation of arguments, a point that had been largely overlooked in the study of fallacies but which had been central to Aristotle’s original account. Hamblin’s dialectical framework was significant in the following respect. It spawned a number of studies that were to describe how variants of the informal fallacies were nonfallacious in particular contexts of use. In a study of nonfallacious arguments from ignorance, for example, Walton (1992) directly attributes the presumptive framework that is the basis of his analysis to Hamblin’s formal dialectic:

This analysis of presumption clearly itself presumes the existence of a dialectical framework for the evaluation of arguments where two parties “reason together.” But such a framework is given in the outline of formal dialectic presented by Hamblin (1970)…; (Walton 1992, p. 383).

Steadily, one informal fallacy after another was shown to have nonfallacious variants. By far the most significant contributors to this area of fallacy theory have been John Woods and Douglas Walton. In a large number of books and journal articles, these theorists described nonfallacious forms of petitio principii (begging the question), argumentum ad ignorantiam (the argument from ignorance), and argumentum ad baculum (the argument from the stick or appeal to force), amongst others (Walton 1985, 1992; Woods 1995). Informal fallacies were now experiencing an intellectual renaissance that had not been witnessed in many earlier centuries of inquiry in logic. As more and more theorists turned their attention to the rational and epistemic features of the informal fallacies, it became clear that these arguments, and the presumptive frameworks that licensed them, had applications in domains where deductive and inductive modes of reasoning had previously dominated. One such domain was scientific inquiry. In this way, in Cummings (2000, 2002, 2004) I described how nonfallacious forms of three informal fallacies—petitio principii, arguments from analogy and argumentum ad ignorantiam—functioned as reasoning heuristics that facilitate the progress of scientific inquiry under conditions of epistemic uncertainty. How surprising this new found status of the fallacies would have appeared to the logicians of earlier centuries.Footnote 7

Some consideration of informal fallacies and presumptive frameworks in general reveals why these arguments are well suited to the analysis of reasoning within scientific contexts. Presumption is a rather tentative epistemic category. It contains a commitment to a thesis that is of an altogether weaker nature than either knowledge or belief, for example.Footnote 8 This commitment can be easily eroded in the presence of countervailing conditions. So an agent may presume that p, but relinquish commitment to p as soon as conditions give the slightest indication to reject p. The tentative, provisional nature of presumption is described by Rescher as follows:

[A] presumption is a plausible pretender to truth whose credentials may well prove insufficient, a runner in a race it may not win. The “acceptance” of a proposition as a merely presumptive truth is not acceptance at all but a highly provisional and conditional epistemic inclination toward it, an inclination that falls far short of outright commitment (2006, p. 3).

These features of presumption mean that this epistemic concept is particularly well suited to an analysis of reasoning in the context of scientific inquiry in at least three respects. Firstly, the fallible nature of scientific inquiry demands that our various epistemic concepts must be able to withstand error and failure. Moreover, the fact of the occurrence of error should not erode our confidence in those concepts which deliver truths to us on enough occasions for us to continue to operate by them. Presumption, it seems, is the ideal epistemic candidate for such a fallible process of scientific inquiry:

Their inherent defeasibility means that appropriate presumptions are impervious to occasional failure (Rescher 2006, p. 7).

Secondly, many scientific inquiries are conducted under conditions of extreme urgency and uncertainty. Where the health of the public is at risk, as is the case in a newly emerging infectious disease, urgency and uncertainty become uneasy bedfellows. In order to maximize the urgency of a scientific response to an epidemic, scientists are often compelled to institute disease containment measures using knowledge bases that are incomplete and uncertain. We saw in Sect. 1, for example, how scientists investigating SARS and BSE lacked knowledge of all key aspects of the epidemics that confronted them (types of pathogen, route(s) of transmission, etc.). However, if the implementation of containment measures must await the development of certain knowledge bases, the urgency of a scientific response will be compromised with possible devastating consequences for the health of a population. Presumption is the epistemic concept that enables scientists to balance the practical demands of disease containment against the theoretical requirement for complete and certain knowledge. For it is presumption that licenses decisions of the practical sphere when complete and certain knowledge is beyond the immediate grasp of scientists:

[P]resumption is certainly not knowledge: we do not know what we merely presume to be so. As an informative resource its standing is quite different from that of knowledge… [presumption] nevertheless is an informative resource—and a highly useful one at that, since it serves to close up an otherwise debilitating gap (Rescher 2006, p. 6; italics in original).

Thirdly, in yielding to considerations that are more plausible, presumptions are inextricably linked to the standards and types of evidence that apply in a particular domain. The evidence that is required to defeat a presumption varies on the basis of context-specific considerations such as the importance of the question at issue.Footnote 9 For example, one might reasonably expect scientists who are testing a new drug for use in humans to have to meet a very high burden of proof before such a drug can be licensed. In such a case, the precautionary principleFootnote 10 requires that there is a presumption against the safety of the new drug which extensive clinical trials must seek to overcome. As more and more trials are conducted and no adverse health effects of the drug are observed, the presumption shifts in favour of the safety of the new drug. Long-standing presumptions grow in epistemic stature as they are “retrospectively validated” by inquiry.Footnote 11 This capacity of presumptions to improve their epistemic standing is the direct result of the dialectical to and fro that occurs between presumption and burden of proof in scientific inquiry. Where this dialectical exchange does not occur, or is otherwise subverted, it is usually to the detriment of scientific inquiry. We will see subsequently how a presumption in support of the non-transmissibility of BSE to humans became “fossilized” in the BSE inquiry with quite disastrous consequences for human health.

These three features of presumption are significant in the following respect: they are integral to the view of the informal fallacies that I am espousing in this article, a view in which these fallacies facilitate scientific inquiry under conditions of uncertainty. To demonstrate this claim, I will draw on two earlier analyses of fallacies in Cummings (2002, 2004). However, where those earlier analyses described the logical features and functions of the fallacies in question, there was little consideration of their presumptive character. That presumptive character, I will argue, is what makes the fallacies ideally suited to the rational methodology of science.

2.1 Scientific Error and the Informal Fallacies

The reason logicians are so quick to legislate against the fallacies is that they are standardly taken to lead us into error.Footnote 12 Error is an interesting concept which has hidden dimensions that have relevance for the account of fallacies that I am developing in the present context. One of those dimensions is the persistence of error. Notwithstanding our best efforts to minimize and even eliminate errors, they are a persistent feature of our various cognitive deliberations.Footnote 13 The persistence of error in the form of fallacies is remarked upon by John Woods. Woods is struck by the recurrence of certain fallacies (the so-called “gang of eighteen”Footnote 14) in the literature. His explanation of their recurrence “generation-in and generation-out” is revealing of the status that Woods affords to the fallacies:

[T]he standard examples caricature (because they over-simplify) improprieties of rational performance of which they themselves can be considered a kind of idealized symptom. Those misperformances in turn are failures of one or another of our basic rational survival skills (2004, pp. 10–11).

Woods clearly links the persistence of the fallacies to the role they play in our cognitive rationality. I agree with this view in part—fallacies have a much closer connection to our cognitive rationality than logicians have typically acknowledged. But I think Woods tends to follow other logicians in presenting a rather negative case against the fallacies. Quite apart from being “improprieties of rational performance,” the fallacies, I contend, are a core component of our rational competence. Of course, on occasion, they let us down—we can make errors based on the particular cognitive directions in which they lead us. But these errors do little damage to the rational standing of the argument forms in question. This is because presumption is the very essence of these argument forms and, like presumption, these forms are “impervious to occasional failure.” This is amply demonstrated by two informal fallacies—the argument from ignorance and the argument from analogy—which played a key role in the reasoning of BSE scientists. The argument from ignorance was used so extensively during the BSE crisis in the UK that the public inquiryFootnote 15 that was set up to investigate the handling of the epidemic labeled it as the “mantra” of the BSE story. Although different forms of the argument were used, it was most commonly employed in relation to the question of the transmissibility of BSE to humans. In this way, Dr Calman (Chief Medical Officer, 1991–1998) released a statement on 26 January 1994 in which he stated:

[O]n the basis of the work done so far, there was no evidence whatever that BSE caused CJD and, similarly, not the slightest evidence that eating beef or hamburgers caused CJD (BSE Inquiry Report, Volume 1, p. 143; italics added).

On 7 December 1995, Dr Robert Kendell (Chief Medical Officer for Scotland, 1991–1996) made a public statement in which he claimed “[w]e have no evidence of any connection between BSE and CJD” (BSE Inquiry Report, Volume 1, p. 150; italics added). In a letter to the Chief Medical Officer dated 24 July 1990, the Spongiform Encephalopathy Advisory Committee (SEAC)Footnote 16 concluded that:

[W]e believe that there is no scientific justification for not eating British beef and that it can be eaten by everyone (BSE Inquiry Report, Volume 1, p. 131; italics added).

These repeated claims by scientistsFootnote 17 that there was “no evidence” that BSE caused CJD in humans and that there was “no scientific justification” for not eating British beef had the effect of persuading an anxious public that BSE was not transmissible to humans. The vehicle of this persuasion was a classic argument from ignoranceFootnote 18 which can be reconstructed as follows:

  • There is no evidence that BSE in cattle causes CJD in humans.

  • ∴ BSE in cattle does not cause CJD in humans.

That BSE would not transmit to humans was also the conclusion of a second argument form that was used extensively by BSE scientists. This was the argument from analogy, where scientists used purported similarities of BSE with scrapie disease in sheep to argue that BSE would not transmit to humans. Analogical reasoning was integral to the deliberations of the Southwood Working PartyFootnote 19:

The conclusion that BSE would behave in the same way as scrapie was essentially a matter of judgement in the face of uncertainties, or an “educated guess.” This was not something that the Working Party sought to conceal, as is clear from private correspondence which Sir Richard had with a number of scientists about BSE. In a letter to a Mr J. Granger (a veterinary surgeon) on 25 October 1988, Sir Richard wrote: I have to say that it is my view that the risk of transmission of BSE to man is relatively small, but this view is based entirely on drawing a parallel with scrapie… (BSE Inquiry Report, Volume 4, p. 47).

The analogical argumentFootnote 20 that was central to the reasoning of the Southwood Working Party can be reconstructed as follows:

  • BSE is similar to scrapie in certain respects.

  • Scrapie has not transmitted to humans.

  • ∴ BSE will not transmit to humans.

Of course, we now know that the conclusions of these ignorance and analogical arguments were erroneous. BSE did indeed transmit to humans and cause CJD, a fact that was acknowledged for the first time on 20 March 1996 when Mr Stephen Dorrell, the then Secretary of State for Health, announced the emergence of new variant CJD to British Parliament. That these conclusions were ultimately shown to be erroneous did nothing to invalidate the initial legitimacy of the presumptive reasoning strategies that led to these conclusions. The ultimate defeat of specific presumptive conclusions in inquiry is in no way remarkable. Presumption is, after all, a highly tentative epistemic category that should be rejected as soon as countervailing conditions emerge.Footnote 21 Moreover, the failure of one presumption in inquiry is not grounds for the rejection of presumptions in toto. The inherent defeasibility of presumptions is what makes this epistemic concept able to accommodate scientific error and to respond to such error in a way that does not involve the wider destruction of scientific inquiry. This is evident in the piecemeal fashion in which presumptive conclusions were rejected during the BSE inquiry as evidence from other sources became available. In this way, analogies with scrapie were used to guide decision-making on a whole range of issues beyond the question of the transmission of BSE to humans. One such issue was the cattle tissues to include in the Specified Bovine Offal (SBO) ban of November 1989:

Tissues from cattle aged under six months were exempt from the ban on the basis that scrapie infectivity had not been found in lambs of this age (BSE Inquiry Report, Volume 1, p. 14).

The decision to exclude tissues from cattle in the first six months of life from the SBO ban was reversed in June 1994 when it became apparent that the pathogenesis of BSE was dissimilar in significant respects from that of scrapie (BSE Inquiry Report, Volume 1, pp. 137–138). Specifically, a pathogenesis study that had been initiated at the Central Veterinary Laboratory (CVL) in December 1991 revealed infectivity in bovine tissues (e.g., ileum) earlier than had been expected using the scrapie model (BSE Inquiry Report, Volume 2, p. 121). The rejection of the presumption that it was safe to exclude the tissues of calves from the SBO ban displayed all the hallmarks of defeasible presumptions—the tentative epistemic commitment to this presumption was eroded as soon as scientists obtained evidence which led them to question the plausibility of this presumption. In fact, so immediate was the rejection of this presumption and any decisionsFootnote 22 that were based on it that the public inquiry team which investigated the handling of the BSE crisis described the response as “a model of how government ought to handle such an issue” (BSE Inquiry Report, Volume 1, p. 138). At the same time, however, the defeat of the presumption that calf tissues were not infective did not trigger the wholesale rejection of every presumption that had been established through analogical reasoning based on scrapie. In particular, the decision to give special consideration to the safety of bovine tissues in medicinal products was premised on earlier scrapie research which had revealed that the parenteral route of transmission was more efficient than the oral route.Footnote 23 If every presumption that had been licensed on the basis of an analogy with scrapie had been rejected once it was discovered that calf tissues were infective, the measures that were put in place to safeguard medicines and surgical products may well have been differently implemented, if they were implemented at all.Footnote 24 Put quite simply, the demonstration of error in the case of one presumptive conclusion—the presumption that calf tissues were not infective—had a rather circumscribed impact on scientific inquiry into BSE. Presumption was the mechanism whereby this error could be absorbed without necessitating any wider destruction of the scientific inquiry into BSE. We will now consider how presumption also functioned in the scientific inquiry into BSE by licensing decisions in the practical sphere in the absence of complete and certain knowledge.

2.2 Scientific Uncertainty and the Informal Fallacies

If informal fallacies are particularly well adapted to dealing with the occurrence of error during scientific inquiry, they are even more suited to the task of bridging knowledge gaps during inquiry. These knowledge gaps were painfully evident to everyone involved in the BSE crisis, as can be seen from Mr Cruickshank’s comments in Sect. 1 above. It became clear to those whose task it was to contain the spread of the disease in cattle and to prevent its transmission to humans that key decisions would have to be taken against a wider epistemic context of uncertainty. The only other possible course of action—delaying the institution of disease containment measures until a complete knowledge base became available—presented an unacceptable level of risk to the health of the population. It is against this background of uncertainty, I contend, that certain informal fallacies served to advance the inquiry into BSE. Specifically, the presumptive nature of these fallacies licensed decisions of the practical sphere and suggested important research directions when relevant knowledge was essentially lacking. In this section, we consider two such cases in which this occurred. A more detailed treatment of each case can be found in Cummings (2002).

We have already seen how the argument from ignorance formed the mainstay of scientific and ministerial pronouncements about the (lack of) risk of BSE to human health. Time and time again, consumers were told that that there was no evidence that BSE in cattle caused CJD in humans. The implication of this particular statement was, of course, that BSE did not cause CJD in humans. Of course, we now know that BSE did transmit to humans. Yet, this fact does nothing to diminish the very important role that this particular argument played during the BSE crisis. To understand this role, it is necessary to consider the type of knowledge that was required to address the question of transmission and whether there was a realistic prospect of scientists obtaining that knowledge in the short and (foreseeable) longer term. It was known, for example, that transmissible spongiform encephalopthies had very long incubation periods.Footnote 25 On the assumption that BSE would exhibit an equally lengthy incubation period in humans, scientists were facing a situation in which they would be unable to address the question of transmission for many years to come. If disease containment measures were not established until BSE-related disease first emerged in humans, the number of people who could have become infected in the intervening years was potentially very large indeed. Ethical considerations prohibited the type of experimentation that would have directly addressed this question. Moreover, the closest knowledge of the transmission of spongiform encephalopathies to humans involved cases that either failed to replicate the species barrier that BSE would have to cross in order to infect humansFootnote 26 or failed to replicate the oral route of transmission by means of which BSE would make its way into the human population.Footnote 27 The knowledge base that was needed to address the question of the transmission of BSE to humans was thus incomplete in all key respects.

Unable to address the question of BSE transmission to humans directly, scientists had little option but to set this question to one side during inquiry. The argument from ignorance enabled scientists to disengage from the question of BSE transmission to humans and to address other questions for which there was at least a reasonable prospect of obtaining answers. By representing the question of transmission to humans as disconfirmed (this is, in effect, what the ignorance argument presented in Sect. 2.1 achieved), there was no longer a requirement on scientists to actively pursue a response to it. If the question had remained unconfirmed,Footnote 28 it would have continued to be subject to deliberation by BSE scientists during inquiry. The argument from ignorance had the beneficial effect of creating an economical order in which questions were examined during the BSE inquiry—where a question was unlikely to be addressed in either the short or longer term, it was set to one side to make way for questions that could be directly tackled. Quite apart from dismissing the important question of transmission to humans, BSE scientists were responding to the uncertainty that confronted them by instituting a rational epistemic policy. This policy enabled scientists to concentrate their cognitive and technical resources in areas were gains could reasonably be expected to be made. To this extent, the argument from ignorance served to facilitate inquiry under conditions that might otherwise have seen it grind to a halt. We will see shortly that this facilitative effect is the direct result of the presumptive character of this particular argument form.

The question of transmission of BSE to humans was also addressed through another argument form that was based upon an analogy with scrapie in sheep. Scientists argued that scrapie had not transmitted to humans in 250 yearsFootnote 29 and that BSE, which was presumed to be similar to scrapie (if not actual scrapie in cattle), would not transmit to humans either. In reality, the analogy with scrapie motivated a large number of research questions concerning BSE in addition to the question of transmission of the disease to humans. Just how many was evident in a paper produced in December 1988 by Mr Bradley of the CVL. The paper described five experiments that were already in progress at the CVL and which were addressing questions in the areas of epidemiology, clinico-pathological studies, transmission, molecular biology and molecular genetics. All five experiments were premised on earlier research into scrapie in sheep. For example, molecular genetic studies were designed “to determine any genetic factors involved in disease expression in cattle, and to determine whether an equivalent to the sinc or sip genes existed in cattle” (BSE Inquiry Report, Volume 2, p. 187). The sinc and sip genes are mice and sheep genes (respectively) that regulate the incubation period of natural and experimental scrapie. The list of tissues included in tissue infectivity studies was based on “extrapolation of data from Hadlow’s studies into scrapie in sheep” (BSE Inquiry Report, Volume 2, p. 194). By providing a research framework, the analogy with scrapie was able to generate many productive lines of inquiry for scientists to pursue when little was known about BSE. Analogical reasoning had the effect of advancing inquiry on grounds that held at least some degree of initial plausibility. It thus functioned to bridge gaps in scientific knowledge, gaps that would otherwise have adversely affected the progress of inquiry. This was possible at all because of the essentially presumptive character of the analogical arguments involved. We consider the role of presumptions in these arguments below.

The ignorance and analogical arguments that we have examined in this section were effective, I am arguing, in bridging gaps in scientific knowledge during the BSE crisis. Some examination of the nature of these arguments reveals why this was the case. Presumption was the operative epistemic concept in these different arguments. The concept of presumption exhibits a distinctly exploratory quality. It licenses investigators to pursue courses of action when knowledge is lacking. At the same time, it contains an implicit guarantee that should a particular course of action be found to be wanting, our tentative commitment to the presumption that warranted this course can be easily eroded. The “epistemic damage” of running with a presumption that is ultimately shown to be incorrect is thus quite circumscribed. Certainly, it is sufficiently limited in extent not to deter an investigator, scientific or otherwise, from becoming committed to future presumptions or indeed to the same “erroneous” presumption under different circumstances. The ignorance and analogical arguments that were used extensively during the BSE inquiry were presumptive reasoning strategies. These arguments conferred sufficient warrant on the presumptions that were generated by means of them that scientists were able to initiate research studies and implement disease containment measures. Yet, the merely tentative nature of these presumptions meant that when they began to appear problematic, scientists were readily able to reject them. Such rejection occurred in some cases in which it was warranted (e.g., the rejection of the presumption that it was safe to exclude calf tissues from the SBO ban). It is one of the tragedies of the BSE affair that it did not take place in every situation in which presumptions based on ignorance and analogical arguments were shown to be inadequate. We consider this issue in the next section.

2.3 Scientific Dialectic and the Informal Fallacies

Models of scientific inquiry that are based on disputation are by now well established. One of the most prominent proponents of this dialectical approach to scientific methodology is Nicholas Rescher. Rescher (1977) proposes a scientific dialectic in which:

[C]reative science appears in the light of an adversary procedure, with proponents and opponents carrying on a debate to secure the approbation of knowledgeable but “disinterested” (i.e., unaligned) parties—often as not the rising generation of specialists in the field (p. 111; italics in original).

Within this dialectical approach, presumption and burden of proof is the mechanism by means of which evidential considerations in support of scientific theses are effectively managed. In this way, the opponent of a scientific thesis must advance grounds why a particular claim should not be allowed to stand. Where these grounds are judged to be sufficiently plausible, the opponent has successfully discharged his burden of proof. A presumption now exists in favour of his thesis, a presumption which the proponent (now opponent) must seek to dislodge through his own advancement of evidence. Where no evidence can be advanced against a thesis, or the evidence that is advanced is not judged to be sufficiently plausible, the thesis held as a presumption grows in epistemic stature. As the participants in inquiry take it in turn to discharge their burden of proof and secure a presumption in support of their thesis, the probative standing of theses is steadily revealed.

This dialectical model of scientific inquiry is only revealing of the grounds of theses to the extent that the participants in inquiry recognize when sufficient plausible evidence has been adduced to discharge a burden of proof. Where this burden of proof is unreasonably high and the corresponding presumption is excessively difficult to dislodge, the dialectical character of inquiry becomes distorted. Presumptions, which are typically defeasible, may become resistant to the type of countervailing conditions that would normally bring about their rejection. These presumptions can then persist in inquiry regardless of the plausibility of the evidence that is adduced against them. Many of the ignorance and analogical arguments that facilitated inquiry into BSE in the early stages of the epidemic became so deeply entrenched that the presumptions which they generated soon assumed the status of unassailable theses. Consider again the analogical argument based on scrapie that led scientists to believe that BSE would not transmit to humans. Even as evidence began to emerge, for example, that the host range of BSE was not the same as that of scrapie, scientists continued to subscribe to the view that BSE was bovine scrapie and that BSE was not transmissible to humans. Officials at the Department of Health and the Ministry of Agriculture, Fisheries and Food reported to ministers on 6 May 1990 that Bristol University had diagnosed a “scrapie-like” spongiform encephalopathy in a domestic cat. It was known that scrapie had never been successfully transmitted by inoculation to a cat. So this was the first indication that BSE had a different host range from scrapie. If BSE could infect a cat, it was entirely possible that it could differ from scrapie in one other salient respect. This was the question of BSE transmission to humans.

So concerned were scientists and government ministers by this development that their immediate response was to attempt to downplay its significance for the question of transmission to an anxious public. Essentially, scientists and ministers continued to maintain that BSE was scrapie in cattle and, as such, BSE was unlikely to transmit to humans. However, in the light of this new evidence, scientists could only continue to adopt this position by adhering to a somewhat implausible claim. This was the claim that scrapie maybe had transmitted to a cat but that such transmission had gone undetected:

[I]f this could happen to a cat, why should not human beings suffer the same fate? Yet it was far too soon to jump to any such conclusion. It was possible that there had always been the occasional case of feline spongiform encephalopathy (FSE) which had gone unrecognised (BSE Inquiry Report, Volume 1, p. 128).

This claim was implausible for two reasons. Firstly, the oral route of transmission was known to be less effective than transmission via inoculation. If inoculation had never transmitted scrapie to a cat, it was even less likely that transmission would have occurred orally. Secondly, scrapie had been in the sheep population for some 250 years. If cats were susceptible to scrapie, it is likely that natural transmission to cats would have been detected at some stage in this long history of the disease. While the impulse of scientists and government ministers to “prop up” the original analogy of BSE to scrapie was an understandable one—ministers in particular were concerned to allay the public’s fears that BSE would transmit to humans—this was only achieved at the expense of defending the non-transmission thesis against plausible counter-evidence, specifically the evidence that BSE and scrapie had different host ranges. The non-transmission thesis became a “fossilized” presumption in the BSE inquiry in that it persisted in immutable form even as contrary evidence became available to scientists. What should have been a defeasible presumption came to be treated by scientists and government ministers alike as a well established fact. By failing to allow plausible counter-evidence to stand against the non-transmission thesis, scientists and government ministers had effectively subverted the dialectical mechanism of presumption and burden of proof in the BSE inquiry. While this subversion achieved the short-term goal of convincing the public that beef was safe to eat, it had adverse long-term consequences in terms of public distrust of scientific pronouncements about risk (Cummings 2005a).

3 Summary

Presumption, it emerges, is a highly versatile epistemic concept. Its central characteristic of defeasibility means that presumption is ideally suited to the fallible nature of scientific inquiry. Even where scientific error does occur and specific presumptions fall by the wayside, the immediate effect on inquiry is rather limited. This is because our commitment to presumption is as easily broken as it is forged. As well as accommodating scientific error, presumption enables scientists to make decisions and pursue courses of action in the practical sphere when certain and complete knowledge is essentially lacking. Presumption thus has fundamental relevance to scientists who are confronted with newly emerging infectious diseases. These scientists must put into action disease containment measures when everything from type of pathogen to route(s) of transmission is unknown. It is in a context of epistemic uncertainty that the exploratory nature of presumption comes to the fore. This concept allows investigators to move forward in inquiry in the spirit that nothing ventured is nothing gained (or, perhaps more aptly, the scientist who does not venture forth in inquiry is likely to incur significant epistemic and practical penalties). Of course, as well as serving inquiry in these important ways, presumption can also subvert inquiry. Subversion occurs when the dialectical nature of this concept is neglected and plausible counter-evidence is not allowed to stand against presumptions. Such presumptions become “fossilized” in inquiry and persist long after reasonable counter-evidence has been adduced against them.

All three aspects of presumption were manifested in the reasoning of scientists during the BSE crisis. That reasoning contained numerous examples of arguments that logicians have traditionally classified as fallacies. Two cases in point were the argument from ignorance and analogical argument. I have argued in this article that these arguments were quite far from being fallacious; indeed, they conferred a number of epistemic gains on the inquiry of which they were a part. This was at all possible, I contended, because these arguments were presumptive in nature. Yet, the same presumptive forms of reasoning that served to advance inquiry under certain conditions—for example, when knowledge was lacking—stifled inquiry in other situations. This analysis of these argument forms represents a significant departure from traditional accounts of the fallacies. Firstly, the traditional distinction between fallacious and non-fallacious arguments is recast in terms of presumptions that are applied to the benefit of inquiry in some circumstances and are misapplied with adverse consequences for inquiry in other circumstances. Secondly, the fallaciousness of any argument becomes a context-sensitive affair and is related ultimately to the probative standards that operate in a particular setting. This study thus contributes to the “pragmatic turn” that has occurred in fallacy theory in recent years (Cummings 2005b, p. 173).