Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Psychometrics in action, science as practice

  • Reflections
  • Published:
Advances in Health Sciences Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Practitioners in health sciences education and assessment regularly use a range of psychometric techniques to analyse data, evaluate models, and make crucial progression decisions regarding student learning. However, a recent editorial entitled “Is Psychometrics Science?” highlighted some core epistemological and practical problems in psychometrics, and brought its legitimacy into question. This paper attempts to address these issues by applying some key ideas from history and philosophy of science (HPS) discourse. I present some of the conceptual developments in HPS that have bearing on the psychometrics debate. Next, by shifting the focus onto what constitutes the practice of science, I discuss psychometrics in action. Some incorrectly conceptualize science as an assemblage of truths, rather than an assemblage of tools and goals. Psychometrics, however, seems to be an assemblage of methods and techniques. Psychometrics in action represents a range of practices using specific tools in specific contexts. This does not render the practice of psychometrics meaningless or futile. Engaging in debates about whether or not we should regard psychometrics as ‘scientific’ is, however, a fruitless enterprise. The key question and focus should be whether, on what grounds, and in what contexts, the existing methods and techniques used by psychometricians can be justified or criticized.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Arabatzis, T., & Schickore, J. (2012). Introduction: Ways of integrating history and philosophy of science. Perspectives on Science, 20(4), 395–408.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2002). Kuhn’s wrong turning. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 33, 443–463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2008). The historical turn in the philosophy of science. In S. Psillos & M. Curd (Eds.), Routledge companion to the philosophy of science (pp. 67–77). Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borsboom, D. (2006). The attack of the psychometricians. Psychometrika, 71(3), 425–440.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burian, R. M. (1977). More than a marriage of convenience: On the inextricability of the history and philosophy of science. Philosophy of Science, 44, 1–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butterfield, H. (1931). The Whig interpretation of history. London: G. Bell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut, W. (1993). Taking the naturalist turn, or how real philosophy of science is done. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cano, S. J., & Hobart, J. C. (2011). The problem with health measurement. Patient Preference and Adherence, 5, 279–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. (1975). Against method. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forster, M. (2000). Hard problems in the philosophy of science: Idealization and commensurability. In R. Nola & H. Sankey (Eds.), After Popper, Kuhn and Feyerabend: Issues in theories of scientific method (pp. 231–250). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, S. (2003). Kuhn vs Popper: The struggle for the soul of science. Cambridge: Icon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gieryn, T. (1983). Boundary-work and the demarcation of science from non-science: Strains and interests in professional ideologies of scientists. American Sociological Review, 48(6), 781–795.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gieryn, T. (1999). Cultural boundariews of sceince: Credibility on the line. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1975). The emergence of probability. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1999). The social construction of what?. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (2002). ‘Style’ for historians and philosophers. Historical ontology (pp. 178–199). Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, N. R. (1962). The irrelevance of history of science to philosophy of science. The Journal of Philosophy, 59, 574–586.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S. O. (2006). Falsificationism falsified. Foundations of Science, 11(3), 275–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hobart, J. C., Cano, S. J., Zajicek, J. P., & Thompson, A. J. (2007). Rating scales as outcome measures for clinical trials in neurology: Problems, solutions, and recommendations. Lancet Neurology, 6, 1094–1105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2006). Context of discovery versus context of justification and Thomas Kuhn. In J. Schickore & F. Steinle (Eds.), Revisiting discovery and justification. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jardine, N. (2000). The scenes of inquiry: On the reality of questions in the sciences (2nd ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jones, L. V., & Thissen, D. (2007). A history and overview of psychometrics. Handbook of Statistics. doi:10.1016/S0169-7161(06)26001-2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1998 [1781]). Critique of pure reason (T. b. P. G. a. A. Wood, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Klein, U. (2003). Experiments, models, paper tools: Cultures of organic chemistry in the nineteenth century. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1970a). Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge (pp. 91–195). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1970b). History of science and its rational reconstructions. In PSA: Proceedings of the biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association (pp. 91–136).

  • Lakatos, I. (1976). Proofs and refutations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (1987). Science in action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mari, L., & Wilson, M. (2014). An introduction to the Rasch measurement approach for metrologists. Measurement, 51, 315–327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Massof, R. W. (2008). Moving toward scientific measurements of quality of life. Ophthalmic Epidemiology, 15, 209–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Masterman, M. (1970). The Nature of a paradigm. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge (pp. 59–89). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Messick, S. (1989). Validity. In R. L. Linn (Ed.), Educational measurement (pp. 13–103). New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Messick, S. (1995). Standards of validity and the validity of standards in performance assessment. Euducational Measurement: Issues and Practice, 14(4), 5–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michell, J. (2008). Is psychometrics pathalogical science? Measurement: Interdisciplinary Research and Perspectives, 6, 7–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norman, G. (2016). Is psychometrics science? Advances in Health Sciences Education (Theory and Practice), 21, 731–734.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearce, J. (2015). Historicizing scale development: Shifting epistemic practices in Rasch measurement. Paper presented at the IMEKO XXI World Congress, Prague. https://www.imeko.org/publications/wc-2015/IMEKO-WC-2015-TC7-194.pdf

  • Pendrill, L. (2014). Man as a measurement instrument. NCSLI Measure Journal of Measurement Science, 9(4), 24–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pendrill, L., & Fisher, W. P. (2015). Counting and quantification: Comparing psychometric and metrological perspectives on visual perceptions of number. Measurement, 71, 46–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pesudovs, K. (2010). Item banking: A generational change in patient-reported outcome measurement. Optometry and Vision Science, 87(4), 285–293.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pickering, A. (1992). From science as knowledge to science as practice. In A. Pickering (Ed.), Science as practice and culture. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Prelli, L. J. (1989). The rhetorical construction of scientific ethos. Evolution, 34(5), 87–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rasmussen, N. (1997). Picture control: The electron microscope and the transformation of biology in America, 1940–1960. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger, H.-J. (2010). On Historicizing Epistemology: An Essay (D. Fernbach, Trans.): Stanford University Press.

  • Ritson, S., & Camilleri, K. (2015). Contested boundaries: The string theory debates and ideologies of science. Perspectives on Science, 23(2), 192–227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (2009). The Darwinian revolution: Rethinking its meaning and significance. PNAS, 106(1), 10040–10047.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C. (1970). Bayes’s theorem and the history of science. In R. H. Stuewer (Ed.), Historical and philosophical perspectives on science. Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science 5. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schoenherr, J. R., & Hamstra, S. J. (2016). Psychometrics and its discontents: An historical perspeective on the discourse of the measurement tradition. Advances in Health Sciences Education (Theory and Practice), 21, 719–729.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sturm, T., & Feest, U. (2011). What (good) is historical epistemology? Erkenntnis, 75, 285–302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, S. (1998). The revolution that didn’t happen. New York Review of Books, 45(15), 48–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkins, J. S. (2010). Retrieved from https://thonyc.wordpress.com/2010/11/12/galileo%E2%80%99s-great-bluff-and-part-of-the-reason-why-kuhn-is-wrong/

  • Wilson, M. (2013). Seeking a balance between the statistical and scientific elements in psychometrics. Psychometrika, 78(2), 211–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Kristian Camilleri, Neville Chiavaroli and William P Fisher Jr for constructive feedback on an earlier version of this paper, along with the helpful comments made by editors and reviewers during the peer review process. I would also like to acknowledge Kristian Camilleri for his guidance over the years regarding HPS discourse.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jacob Pearce.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Pearce, J. Psychometrics in action, science as practice. Adv in Health Sci Educ 23, 653–663 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10459-017-9789-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10459-017-9789-7

Keywords

Navigation